1 Introduction

The purpose of this paper is to contribute to the ongoing debate about the definition of metalinguistic negation (henceforth, MLN). MLN standardly refers to “a formally negative utterance which is used to object to a previous utterance on any grounds whatever, including the way it was pronounced” (Horn 1989/2001: 374).1 It corrects the pronunciation of items, their morphological make-up (1b), their sociolinguistic (1a, 1c) and pragmatic effects (1d, e).

(1) a. They don’t have kids, they have children.
  b. She’s not interesting, she’s interested.
  c. I don’t want to buy pants, but trousers.
  d. He isn’t a proto-fascist demagogue, he’s the POTUS.
  e. She hasn’t seen many of Murnau’s films, she’s seen all of them.2

Beyond this, how MLN should be defined is unclear. Such a definition should do at least three things, relating to the morpho-syntactic reflexes of MLN, how it differs from other negative uses, and what it has in common with other metalinguistic uses.

A definition of MLN should account for its morpho-syntactic reflexes. Of these, the most stable cross-linguistic behaviour is that of the connective that introduces the correction. In some languages, there is a connective specialised for the MLN use, as German sondern and Spanish sino (Anscombre & Ducrot 1977; Horn 1989/2001: 406ff.; Schwenter 2002). As for languages that do not have a specialised connective for the MLN reading, the adversative connective that they use for both MLN and denial nonetheless can behave differently under each interpretation. This is the case with English but introducing a full clause, that is acceptable with denial, but infelicitous with MLN;

(2) a. They don’t have kids, (*but) they have children. MLN
  b. They do not have kids, (but) they have plenty of pets. Denial

And reverse MLN acceptability with a fragment:

(2) c. They don’t have kids, *(but) children. MLN

Another cross-linguistically stable behaviour is that MLN cannot be expressed by a lexically incorporated negative.

(3) a.   It’s not probable, but certain that they will show up.
  b. *It’s improbable, but certain that they will show up.
(4) a.   John borrows money not from anyone in his office but from his family.
  b. *John borrows money from no-one in his office but from his family.
    (McCawley 1991: 201)

Second, a definition of MLN should distinguish it from denial and descriptive uses. That is, it should say how MLN, in examples (a) below, is different from denial, as in examples (b), and descriptive uses, as in examples (c).

(5) a. They don’t have kids, they have children. MLN
  b. That’s not true! They do not have kids. Denial
  c. At least, they don’t have kids. Descriptive
(6) a. She’s not interesting, she’s interested. MLN
  b. She’s not interesting, but she’s not extraordinarily boring either. Denial
  c. Pity she’s not interesting. Descriptive
(7) a. I don’t want to buy pants, I want to buy trousers. MLN
  b. No, I do not want to buy pants. Denial
  c. I don’t want to buy pants, I don’t have any money. Descriptive
(8) a. He isn’t a proto-fascist demagogue, he’s the POTUS. MLN
  b. He is not a proto-fascist demagogue, as the liberal elite conspiracy would no doubt have it. Denial
  c. Thank God he’s not a proto-fascist demagogue. Descriptive
(9) a. She hasn’t seen many films by Murnau, she’s seen all of them. MLN
  b. No, she hasn’t seen many films by Murnau, although she might have seen a couple. Denial
  c. She wouldn’t know because she hasn’t seen many films by Murnau. Descriptive

I assume that there are three major uses, following the initial proposal by Ducrot (1972). MLN is a reactive, corrective act. The corrected segment is rejected, while the rest of the sentence plus the correcting segment are the case: (7a) asserts a desire to buy what is called trousers. Denial is a reactive move that rejects an entire sentence. A descriptive negation is an initiative move (Foolen 1991) that similarly rejects the material under its scope. Unlike MLN, neither denial nor descriptive uses necessarily imply that parts of the sentence are the case, and a desire to buy is asserted by neither (7b) and (7c).

This ternary distinction between descriptive, denial and metalinguistic uses is in contrast to the binary opposition between descriptive and metalinguistic proposed by some researchers. For Horn (1989/2001) and Seuren (1988: 191) among others, metalinguistic and denial are part of the same category, that is opposed to descriptive uses. I maintain (with Schwenter & Johnson 2011 contra Martins 2014, as well as contra Batllori 2016 and Déprez, Tubau, Cheylus & Espinal 2015, to cite but a few recent papers) that MLN and denial are different uses, that are associated with different effects. As discussed in the previous paragraph, MLN implies that a part of the corrected sentence is the case, something that cannot necessarily be assumed with denial. MLN and denial have a divergent relation to connective but as in (2) above, and to because (Laurence R. Horn, personal communication):

(10) a. ?*They don’t have kids, because they have children. MLN
  b.     That’s not true! They do not have kids, because they both have demanding careers. Denial

They react differently to specialised formulaic expressions such as Like hell, which communicate denial but typically not MLN (pace footnote 2).

(11) a. ?*Like hell they have kids, they have children. MLN
  b.     Like hell they have kids, but they have plenty of pets. Denial

A distinct interaction with NPIs is also found, as illustrated below.

(12) a. ?*They don’t have any kids, they have children. MLN
  b.     They do not have any kids, but they have plenty of pets. Denial

On this basis, it seems useful to separate denial from MLN.

Finally, on top of explaining morpho-syntactic reflexes of MLN and distinguishing MLN from denial and descriptive uses, a definition of MLN should identify the properties that the different instantiations of MLN share. I assume that such common properties do exist, moving away from the scepticism expressed by e.g. Geurts (1998) and Davies (2016). Such properties should also be found with other metalinguistic configurations, as in conditionals, comparatives and questions.

(13) If Iran is going nucular, you must be a George Bush admirer.
(14) Giannakidou & Yoon (2011: 5, example (9a))
  We’d better go to the police than to the police!
(15) Carston (1996: 161)
  Since when have you been eating tom[eiDuz] and getting stressed out?

The identification of a property common to metalinguistic uses3 should allow an answer to be formulated to the questions of why such usage is felt to be marked in terms of frequency and interpretation.

The paper is organised as follows. It reviews, after a brief evocation of the definition of MLN in terms of truth-conditions, its characterisation as a corrective construction, recently proposed by Jacques Moeschler (Moeschler 2013; 2015; 2016) and collaborators (Blochowiak, Grisot & Moeschler 2016; Albu 2017). While the characterisation seems intuitively correct, it does not deal with the well-established morpho-syntactic reflexes of MLN. I argue that these reflexes follow from analysing MLN as a corrective configuration. I then articulate the Information Structure of the speech-act. It is organised as a discourse-old sequence from which the corrected segment is turned into discourse-new information as a result of its focal status. The change in informational flow common to metalinguistic uses explains their markedness. How this paradoxical informational configuration can be mapped by a cartographic approach is speculated upon in the final section.

A number of novel proposals are put forward. A new definition is provided of MLN that appeals to its speech-act status and informational configuration. The definition aims to account for morpho-syntactic reflexes of MLN, notably its relation to connectives, and for its relation to different instantiations of corrective and metalinguistic structures. I hope to move the debate forward by showing that correction applied to a focused segment of a discourse-old sequence is the defining characteristic of MLN. We start below with a discussion of two existing definitions.

2 A functional definition of metalinguistic negation

2.1 Is metalinguistic negation truth-conditional?

It was proposed early on that unlike other uses of negation, MLN is unconcerned with matters of truth (i.a. Horn 1985). It focuses on elements that are not part of the truth-conditions of a sentence. Such elements comprise morphological, sociolinguistic and pragmatic dimensions, as shown by the initial illustrations, repeated below for convenience.

(1) a. They don’t have kids, they have children.
  b. She’s not interesting, she’s interested.
  c. I don’t want to buy pants, but trousers.
  d. He isn’t a proto-fascist demagogue, he’s the POTUS.
  e. She hasn’t seen many of Murnau’s films, she’s seen all of them.

None of these elements is normally part of the truth conditions of a sentence. In a modular view of language à la Fodor, morphological, sociolinguistic and pragmatic dimensions should not be accessible to the semantic module. This separation is nicely illustrated by the following literary example.

(16) “And then you won’t have no one left to teach.”
  “anyone,” he says.
  “You won’t have anyone left to teach. Not no one.”
  Laura looks at him with an expression she might also give someone who’s speaking to her in Latin.
  “It’s a double negative,” he says. “Won’t and no one.” (Nathan Hill, 2016, The Nix)

In a vericonditional usage, the sequence Not no one in the third line would lead to cancellation of the two negators and yield an existential interpretation represented by someone. Yet, in the MLN usage illustrated by the passage, not no one is not intending to communicate the equivalent of the incoherent You won’t have anyone left to teach. Someone. The intention is to signal that the word no one is sociolinguistically inappropriate in that context and should be replaced by anyone. One way to deal with such cases is for all the dimensions of a sentence, including the morphological, pragmatic and sociolinguistic ones, to be entered into the semantic module (and be “semanticised”). This procedure may be applied to all sentences, which considerably complicates the semantic representation of a proposition, or only for those ML cases, which might appear ad hoc. Another way to approach MLN is not to deal with it in the semantic module at all; MLN then becomes a non-truth-conditional negation. Since MLN is expressed by the same negative markers that convey truth-conditional uses in most languages (but see e.g. Kroeger 2014), negation must be cross-linguistically ambiguous, the consequence of which has been extensively discussed (especially in the late 1980’s, see Carston 1988; Seuren 1988; Burton-Roberts 1989; and the overview in Pitts 2011).

The proposal of a non-truth-conditional definition of MLN seems unconvincing (for a general recent assessment, see Davis 2016). MLN may be marked, but it is interpreted, and interpreted without much greater difficulties than other uses of negation (Noh, Choo & Ko 2013; Blochowiak, Grisot & Moeschler 2016). Foolen finds that it is “intuitively acceptable to ask whether The job isn’t pretty hard is true or false. Although the utterance may have as its primary function the rejection of (part of) the positive counterpart as stated by the previous speaker, the ground for rejection is the presumed falsity of that positive counterpart.” (1991: 225). Similarly, when choice of lexical expression is being rejected, as in (1d) above, questions of truth may be at stake: an exchange as to whether a certain person is a demagogue or not does not seem devoid of meaning.4 Finally, if MLN had no relation to truth-conditions, it should not be found with explicit evocations of truth (Carston 1998: 326, 336). In other words, a sequence like It’s not true that she has seen many of Murnau’s films, she’s seen all of them should just not be felicitous, contrary to facts. The existence of such cases constitutes a serious problem for any approach that calls into question the vericonditional dimension of MLN.

This section has provided arguments against defining MLN as non-vericonditional. Lack of truth conditions is not present in all cases, and vericonditional analyses have been proposed – for Geurts & Maier (2005), the corrected segment involves reference to a linguistic expression. Having given reasons to move away from a non-truth-conditional definition of MLN, I now turn to a more recent proposal.

2.2 MLN as a corrective use?

Reference to truth conditions need not be the only approach to defining MLN. Other proposals have been recently made that do not depend on them. Of interest is the current work by Jacques Moeschler and his collaborators (Moeschler 2013; 2015; 2016; Blochowiak, Grisot & Moeschler 2016; Albu 2017). Moeschler’s goal is to provide a model distinguishing MLN from denial and descriptive uses. The model is based on two major properties. One is the outcome of the use of negation (see in particular Albu 2017, who had made the point in the earlier manuscript versions). The proposal is that the outcome of descriptive uses is negative, that of denial is negative with potential positive continuation, and that of MLN positive. In the illustrations below, the descriptive use evokes the negation of having children, as does denial (with the added possibility of a positive continuation, that of having pets for instance), while MLN evokes the positive fact of having what is appropriately called “children”.

(5) a. They don’t have kids, they have children. MLN
  b. That’s not true! They do not have kids (, but they have plenty of pets). Denial
  c. At least, they don’t have kids. Descriptive

The second property is the behaviour of the connective relating the negative clause and its continuation. Connectives in some languages specifically relate to MLN. This is the case with German sondern, Spanish sino, but also Romanian ci (Bîlbîie & Winterstein 2011; Albu 2017). Moeschler seeks to relate a typical connector to each of the three negative uses.5

    1. (17)
    1. French (Moeschler 2016)
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. Abi
    2. Abi
    1. n’
    2. NEG1
    1. est
    2. be-PR-3SG
    1. pas belle,
    2. NEG2 pretty
    1. au contraire,
    2. on the contrary,
    1. elle
    2. 3-SG-NOM
    1. est
    2. be-PR.3SG
    1. quelconque.
    2. ordinary
    1. Descriptive
    2.  
    1. ‘Abi isn’t pretty, on the contrary, she’s ordinary.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Non,
    2. no
    1. Abi
    2. Abi
    1. n’
    2. NEG1
    1. est
    2. be-PR-3SG
    1. pas belle,
    2. NEG2 pretty
    1. mais
    2. but
    1. elle
    2. 3SG.NOM
    1. est
    2. be-PR.3SG
    1. gentille.
    2. nice
    1. Denial
    2.  
    1. ‘No, Abi isn’t pretty, but she’s nice.’
    1.  
    1. c.
    1. Abi
    2. Abi NEG1
    1. n’est
    2. be-PR-3SG
    1. pas
    2. NEG2
    1. belle,
    2. pretty
    1. puisqu’elle
    2. since 3SG.NOM
    1. est
    2. be-PR.3SG
    1. superbe.
    2. drop-dead gorgeous
    1. MLN
    2.  
    1. ‘Abi isn’t pretty, since she’s drop-dead gorgeous.’

These properties provide an elegant, symmetrical model of the three usages of negation. In this model, MLN is a corrective use of negation. That seems intuitively correct. Unexpectedly for the proposal however, correction is not always explicitly required of MLN (Larrivée 2011), as shown by the following attestations from French.

    1. (18)
    1. a.
    1. French (Radio-Canada, 18.2.1998)
    1.  
    1.  
    1. A.
    1. Vous
    2. 2PL.NOM
    1. avez
    2. have-PR-2PL
    1. presque
    2. almost
    1. eu
    2. have-PRT
    1. les
    2. the
    1. larmes
    2. tear-PL
    1. aux
    2. at-the-PL
    1. yeux.
    2. eye-PL
    1.  
    1.  
    1. B.
    1. Pas
    2. Not
    1. presque!
    2. almost
    1.  
    1.  
    1. A.
    1. ‘You almost had tears in your eyes.’
    1.  
    1.  
    1. B.
    1. ‘Not almost!’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. French (Film La Turbulence des fluides)
    1.  
    1.  
    1. A.
    1. Est-ce
    2. is this
    1. que
    2. that
    1. tu
    2. 2SG.NOM
    1. penses
    2. think
    1. à
    2. to
    1. ta
    2. your-SG
    1. femme
    2. wife
    1. des
    2. of-the-PL
    1. fois?
    2. time-PL
    1.  
    1.  
    1. B.
    1. Pas
    2. not
    1. des
    2. of-the-PL
    1. fois.
    2. times-PL
    1.  
    1.  
    1. A.
    1. ‘Do you think of your wife sometimes?’
    1.  
    1.  
    1. B.
    1. ‘Not sometimes.’

However the fact that the corrected segment is a PPI which in the immediate scope of negation can only be used with a MLN, suggests that a correction is in order. The correction is left to be inferred from the context: that the speaker in (18a) indeed had tears in their eyes and that the one in (18b) is thinking about their wife constantly. That these can be accommodated by Moeschler’s model as they would have to be by any model does not cast important doubts on the proposal.

Doubts do however arise as to the ability of the model to fully engage with well-recognised morpho-syntactic reflexes of MLN. This particularly concerns patterns of connective behaviour and scopal conditions. Regarding connective behaviour, remember that with MLN, but cannot introduce a clausal correction (2a), unlike with denial (2b). Also, but must introduce a fragment MLN correction (2c).

(2) a. They don’t have kids, (*but) they have children. MLN
  b. They do not have kids, (but) they have plenty of pets. Denial
  c. They don’t have kids, *(but) children. MLN

MLN reverse constructions cannot be introduced by but, as noted in the literature (McCawley 1991; Neeleman & Vermeulen 2011: footnote 5, referring to Horn 1989/2001).

(19) a. They have children, (*but) they don’t have kids. MLN
  b. They have plenty of pets, (but) they don’t have kids. Denial
  c. They have children, (*but) not kids. MLN
  d. They have pets, (but) not children. Denial

These facts remain unaccounted for, and how they could be explained by the aforementioned model is not immediately obvious.

Regarding scopal behaviour, MLN requires negation to have clausal scope, as it does with denial, although not with descriptive uses.

(3) a.   It’s not probable, but certain, that they will show up. MLN
  b. *It’s improbable, but certain, that they will show up MLN
  c.   - It’s probable that the Spencers will show up. Denial
      - Come on, it’s not probable that they will.  
  d.   - It’s probable that the Spencers will show up. Denial
      - ?*Come on, it’s improbable that they will.  
  e. After all, it’s improbable that they will show up. Descriptive

This is related to the observation that MLN is incompatible with a lexically incorporated negative.6

(4) McCawley (1991: 201)
  a.   John borrows money not from anyone in his office but from his family.
  b. *John borrows money from no-one in his office but from his family

Not only does MLN have clausal scope, it has high clausal scope. In Indonesian, the MLN marker (bukan) is always in a higher position than the co-occurring descriptive marker (tidak) (Kroeger 2014). In Mandarin Chinese, MLN is more readily available when the negative attaches to a higher verb such as an auxiliary or a modal (Wible & Chen 2000). In American Sign Language, MLN can only be expressed by a negative headshake that ranges over the whole clause, with or without localised manual signing, that cannot on its own communicate MLN (Fleckenstein & Yoon 2016). Again, why MLN associates to high clausal scope is not immediately explained by Moeschler’s proposals.

In sum, the proposal by Moeschler and colleagues to characterise MLN as a corrective use of negation seems intuitively correct. MLN does yield a positive outcome and is associated with particular connective behaviour. However, the characterisation is not clearly related to the well-established syntactic reflexes of MLN, and the reasons for the observed patterns of connectives and the scopal condition remain to be provided. The next section develops an alternative definition of MLN and considers how it can help account for its syntactic reflexes.

2.3 MLN as a corrective speech-act

The previous section has shown that it makes sense to characterise MLN as a corrective use. But what does it mean for a negative to have a corrective use? That is, at what level of representation should this characteristic apply? An answer starts to emerge when we reconsider the scope of MLN.

While having high scope, MLN cannot focus over everything. It never corrects the speech-act value of a sentence.7 Consider the following elicitations that attempt to convey the rejection of an assertive in favour of an exclamative and of an interrogative respectively.

(20) A.   Abi is beautiful.
  B. *Abi isn’t beautiful, boy is Abi beautiful!
  B’. *Abi isn’t beautiful, is Abi beautiful?

They are infelicitous to the point of being barely intelligible. That is because negation never scopes over the speech-act value of the sentence that contains it.8 It comes under the scope of the speech-act, and is restricted to assertion.

The assertive value of the speech-act in which MLN is found explains an observation by Neeleman & Vermeulen (2011) that both corrected and correcting segments are not presupposed but asserted. This is shown by the redundancy of the following.

(21) a. #John invited Pia and he invited not BILL but PIA.
  b. #John invited not BILL but PIA and he invited Pia.
  c. #John didn’t invite Bill and he invited not BILL but PIA.
  d. #John invited not BILL but PIA and he didn’t invite Bill.

The fact that John invited not Bill but Pia is redundant with respect to John invited Pia in (21b) means that both assert that Pia was invited. This confirms that MLN is an assertive speech-act, where the assertion scopes over the corrective function.

I therefore propose that a single speech-act is involved in the following equivalent structures.

(2) a. They don’t have kids, (*but) they have children.
  c. They don’t have kids, *(but) children.
(19) a. They have children, (*but) they don’t have kids.
  c. They have children, (*but) not kids.

Their function is to assert a correction brought about by an inappropriate designation in the antecedent context. A strong argument in favour of this is the fact that even in bi-clausal MLN, the second clause cannot convey a different speech-act. Witness the infelicity of the following,

(22) a. ?*They don’t have kids, do they have children? MLN
  b. ?*They have children, do they have kids? MLN

These might be acceptable, but only in denial, as made clear by addition of connective but below (with change of contrasting lexical items to avoid incoherence).

(23) a. They don’t have kids, but do they have pets? Denial
  b. They have children, but do they have pets? Denial

This observation shows that a single assertive speech-act is communicated by MLN, which isn’t necessarily the case with denial uses.

The observation also makes visible, again, the differential behaviour of connectives. But how is one to explain the impossibility of but for bi-clausal MLN and fragment reverse MLN, and its compulsory use in fragment MLN? I propose here an explanation based on speech-act status. With bi-clausal cases like They don’t have kids, they have children (and the reverse They have children, they don’t have kids), the addition of a but is impossible with MLN. This is due to the fact that adding a connective would allow the clauses to be conceived as two separate speech-acts, as is the case with denial in (23) above, whereas a single corrective speech-act is involved with MLN. By contrast, fragment cases such as They don’t have kids, but children require the use of but. I suggest that this is because but is necessary to signal the integration of the fragment into the single act. That leaves the ungrammaticality of *They don’t have kids, children to be explained. In any case, the ungrammaticality, in view of the acceptability of MLN They don’t have kids, but children, means that there is no competing fragment configuration that could be associated with denial alone. Competition between MLN and denial arises with reverse fragment between e.g. They have children, not kids which is only MLN and They have pets, but not kids, which is only denial. Each construction is associated with a given use by virtue of competition between denial and MLN. The reasoning is akin to the blocking analysis proposed by Bîlbîie & Winterstein (2011). While a blocking analysis does not explain why one connective goes with one configuration, it does account for the complementary distribution. There are two dimensions of explanation therefore. One is the unity of the corrective speech-act of MLN, that explains the impossible explicit connection between two clauses and the compulsory connection with a fragment. The second is the competition between MLN and denial that accounts for the complementary distribution around reverse fragment constructions. The proposal goes further than existing analyses by offering an explanation for the observed connective behaviour. The proposals are summarised in Table 1.

Table 1

Metalinguistic negation and uses of connective but.

MLN configuration Behaviour of connective but Cause of behaviour
They don’t have kids, (*but) they have children. excluded MLN is a single speech-act, adding but would allow the sequence to be read as two speech-acts, so it is excluded with MLN but allowed with denial
They have children, (*but) they don’t have kids.
They don’t have kids, *(but) children. compulsory MLN is a single speech-act, adding but integrates the fragment into it. The absence of but makes the sequence ungrammatical, and there is no competing sequence to express denial
They have children, (*but) not kids. excluded Adding but signals denial

This section has proposed that MLN is defined as a corrective speech-act. It asserts the correction of an inappropriate designation in the antecedent context. MLN is always found in the scope of an assertive speech-act, and while it must have maximum scope over the material that it is to correct, it cannot correct the speech-act of the sequence that contains it. What’s more, the speech-act represented by MLN is a unitary one. Even in bi-clausal cases, the clauses are integrated and cannot independently express a different speech-act. The unity of the speech-act expressed by MLN is used to account for the behaviour of connectives: but cannot connect the two clauses of MLN, as it might lead them to be interpreted as two different speech-acts, where only one is evoked by MLN; but must connect the corrected clause to the correcting fragment to signal the fragment’s integration in the speech-act. Competition with denial explains the complementary distribution in reverse fragments. In the next section, the informational organisation of the speech act is discussed and identified as a second distinctive property of MLN.

3 Correction and Information Structure

In the previous section, it has been proposed that MLN is a corrective speech-act, a status that explains its principal morpho-syntactic reflexes. However, MLN comes in a variety of formats (i.a. McCawley 1991), as illustrated by the following.

(24) I want to buy not pants, but trousers.
(25) I want to buy trousers, not pants.
(26) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. You mean you want to buy trousers.
(27) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. Trousers.

These contrastive structures raise the question of what common properties they share with the canonical clausal MLN in (1a) They don’t have kids, they have children. A related question is what contrastive structures and clausal MLN have in common with other metalinguistic configurations in conditionals, comparatives and interrogatives exemplified by (13) to (15) above;

(13) If Iran is going nucular, you must be a George Bush admirer.
(14) Giannakidou & Yoon (2011: 5, example (9a))
  We’d better go to the police than to the police!
(15) Carston (1996: 161)
  Since when have you been eating tom[eiDuz] and getting stressed out?

And by the elicitations below:

(28) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. If you want to buy pants, you must be an American in need of trousers.
(29) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. It might be better around here to ask for trousers rather than pants.
(30) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. Are you maybe looking for trousers?
(31) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. Pants?

More generally, metalinguistic uses are felt to be marked. What is the common property of metalinguistic uses that makes them marked? I propose in this section that the answer to these three questions has to do with Information Structure.

Contrastive structures, like MLN and other metalinguistic configurations, all involve correction. However, correction is not enough. McCawley points out that the not X but Y construction does not live solely on MLN environments.910 There are denial uses of those corrective constructions.

(32) So at each moment, all the sun-made right triangles were exactly the same shape – not the same size, but the same shape. (www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/thales.htm)

The difference between denial corrective structures and MLN uses can be illustrated by comparing the attestation above to the elicitation below.

(33) A. Are these triangles acute?
  B. Come on now, these triangles are not acute, but oblique.

It relates to the informational status of the sequence: whereas the rejected material in (32) is discourse-new – it is not a piece of information that is accessible to the reader before that point in the text – it is discourse-old with MLN in (33) – by virtue of the information being made available immediately before in the exchange. MLN, contrastive structures and metalinguistic configurations share the largely acknowledged property of ranging over discourse-old material that is explicitly present in the antecedent context.11 This is what is suggested by the label “metalinguistic” itself. MLN is variously described as echoic (Horn 1989/2001; Krifka 1991; van der Sandt 1991; Dancygier 1992, i.a.), metarepresentational (Carston 1996, i.a.) or an instance of mention rather than use (Jiang 2015).

A shared characteristic of MLN, MLN contrastive structures and other metalinguistic configurations is that they scope over discourse-old information, which does not necessarily apply to denial. The second shared property is the informational status of the corrected segment. The segment is in focus, as assumed without discussion by various recent studies (Geurts & Maier 2005; Kawamura 2007; Kolokonte 2008). Focus is discourse-new information, that is information that is not accessible to the hearer at that point in the discourse, or following Halliday, that is “not being recoverable from the preceding discourse” (1967: 208). Among the various types of Focus (Kiss 1998; Rooth 2016), the case that we are dealing with is contrastive focus. The entity under contrastive Focus is interpreted against a set of alternatives; it is new information against the background of the rest of the proposition that represents the Question Under Discussion (Roberts 1996; Rooth 1996; Kadmon 2001).12

MLN has the corrected segment as contrastive Focus,13 that is explicitly contrasted to another alternative represented by the correction.

(1) c. I don’t want to buy pants, but trousers
(7) a. I don’t want to buy pants, I want to buy trousers.

The same situation obtains with contrastive cases,

(24) I want to buy not pants, but trousers.
(25) I want to buy trousers, not pants.

Things are less immediately obvious with some conditionals, comparatives, and interrogatives that highlight a previously used form without providing an explicit correction.

(28) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. If you want to buy pants, you must be an American in need of trousers.
(29) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. It might be better around here to ask for trousers rather than pants.
(31) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. Pants?

Likewise for the uncorrected correctives of the type below.

(34) Sometimes I just can’t get out of bed… Well not sometimes… For the past week… Depression sucks … (http://whisper.sh/whisper/05268ebb2815c94f515e330c15af1859ade0cc/Sometimes-I-just-cant-get-out-of-bed-Well-not-sometimes-For-the-p)
(35) Mr MOORE. The WTO accession agreement is really a blank page, and countries who are already members of WTO can write what they want on that page. …
  Mr. HOUGHTON. Well, not really, I mean –
  Mr MOORE. Well, almost.
  Mr. HOUGHTON. Well, not almost. They are not going to get into the WTO by handing back a blank page. (P. Crane, 1999, US-China Trade Relations…, p. 200)

However, in both cases, a correction is suggested by attention being driven14 to the sociolinguistic dimension of the form pants as a designation of an outer garment worn on the lower part of the body, and by the PPIs being in the direct scope of negation.15

So MLN is a speech-act that proposes the correction of a segment in Focus from a sentence that is explicitly discourse-old. It is different from denial negation, that does not have Focus on a sentential segment, and from both denial and descriptive, that do not necessarily range over discourse-old material.

At this stage, a paradox emerges. MLN ranges over discourse-old information. That critically includes the segment to be corrected, which is therefore also discourse-old. However, the segment is in Focus, and Focus is understood as being discourse-new information.16 Therefore, both discourse-new and discourse-old status characterise the corrected segment. How is such an apparent contradiction possible? It is possible because the corrected segment is discourse-old as part of the sequence as a whole, and discourse-new as a corrected segment. In the sequence They don’t have kids, they have children, the MLN in the first clause ranges over information that has been explicitly used in the antecedent context. All of the clause is therefore explicitly discourse-old. The corrected segment kids is however focused, and therefore, from discourse-old, is turned into discourse-new information. This atypical discursive move in large parts explains the possible garden-path effects that MLN makes possible (i.a. Attal 1990).17 The first clause of the following may be initially interpreted as a rejection of silliness inviting positive evaluation of the interlocutor; the interpretation disappears in view of the negative qualification offered by the second, correcting clause.

(36) Dynel (2004: 149)
  You’re not silly… You’re simply remarkably stupid.

Such garden-path effects are due to the fact that a descriptive use might be the default interpretation of a negative sentence, that requires specific cues to be interpreted otherwise, only provided after the fact in (38). MLN upsets the normal flow of information.18 In They don’t have kids, it would normally be assumed in an unspecified context that it is having children that is negated; however, rejection of the appropriateness of the form kids alone to assert that a couple indeed has children is definitely marked. The cause of markedness of metalinguistic usage is found in its peculiar Information Structure.

My proposal is that the defining characteristic of the correction offered by MLN relates to Information Structure. MLN ranges over a discourse-old sequence, and turns the part that it objects to into new information by virtue of its focal status. Turning old information into new is what distinguishes it both from descriptive and denial. It is what brings together the different metalinguistic corrective constructions (24)–(27), and metalinguistic uses in questions and conditionals (28)–(31). In other words, MLN upsets the expected discourse-old/discourse-new information dynamics: it ranges over discourse-old material, and sees the discourse-old information transformed into discourse-new focal material. Modifying the expected flow of Information Structure is why they may give rise to garden-path effects, and why more generally metalinguistic usage is marked.

4 An excursus into maps

The previous section has proposed that the markedness of MLN is due to an informational paradox: MLN ranges over discourse-old material, and turns one segment of it into discourse-new information by having it in Focus. Whether such an Information Structure can be mapped into a syntactic structure, and the extent to which it should, are two questions I want to speculate upon in this section.

Informational dimensions can be coded in the left periphery of the sentence assuming Rizzi’s (1997) split-CP hypothesis. The proposed architecture is as follows: [ForceP [TopP [FocP [TopP [FinP [IP.

The higher projection ForceP has to do with the clause type (for MLN, assertion), and the lower FinP relates to Finiteness distinctions. Between these, I assume that the higher TopP can host discourse-old information, that FocP can host contrastive focuses such as MLN corrected segment, and that the lower TopP is the position that non-contrastive focuses would target (see Kolokonte 2008).

Thus, such an architecture could help capture the informational structure of MLN. This is especially useful for a language like Yoruba where overt morphological and positional manifestations of Focus are found (see footnote 13). Checking the morphological Focus feature would be a credible motivation for overt movement of the focused phrase to a FocP position. In the absence of such overt marking, as in English and French, the motivation might be felt to be lacking. However, using covert movement would be desirable to capture the properties of MLN, in particular its informational characteristics, that distinguish it from other negative uses.

How would one go about a left peripheral analysis of the informational status of MLN in a sequence such as They don’t have kids, but children? Several options can be considered regarding negation, the corrected segment in Focus, and the rest of the discourse-old clause.

  1. Only the negative operator moves to FocP, and both the corrected segment and the remaining, discourse-old material stay in situ.

  2. The negative operator and the corrected segment move to FocP, and the discourse-old material stays in situ.

  3. The negative operator and the corrected segment move to FocP, and the discourse-old material moves to the higher TopP.

  4. The negative operator and the corrected segment stay in situ, and the discourse-old material moves to the higher TopP.

Note that I am excluding here the stative option where nothing moves, and where the difference between MLN and other negative uses is not accounted for. A movement analysis raises certain expectations. The expectation is that both Focus and Topic material should move. After all, the point of moving material to the left periphery here is specifically to mark the special informational status of MLN sequences. Leaving Focus or Topic material in situ seems to defeat the purpose of doing a cartographic analysis at all. I’m also assuming that marking the informational status of segments makes it desirable for all the discourse-old material to end up in the same projection. In that respect, the following structure “[TopP [∑P O Joao deu [TopP [CP agora [C’ [FocP [VP um carro a Maria …”, proposed by Martins (2016: 18) for the denial expressed in the Portuguese exchange below

    1. (37)
    1. Portuguese (Martins 2016: 18)
    1.  
    1. A.
    1. O João
    2. the John
    1. deu
    2. give-PST
    1. um
    2. a
    1. carro
    2. car
    1. a
    2. to
    1. Maria.
    2. Maria
    1.  
    1. B.
    1. O João
    2. the John
    1. deu
    2. give-PST
    1. agora
    2. like-hell
    1. um
    2. a
    1. carro
    2. car
    1. a
    2. to
    1. Maria!
    2. Maria
    1.  
    1. A.
    1. ‘John gave a car to Maria.’
    1.  
    1. B.
    1. ‘Like hell John gave a car to Maria!’

is splitting the discourse-old proposition in two, with part of the discourse-old material left in the VP. While this allows to maintain the superficial order, it seems undesirable to separate segments that share the same informational status at a level of representation the objective of which is to make that status visible.

In this approach, the most coherent analysis therefore seems to be iii, illustrated by the sketchy representation below.

iii. [ForceP Assertion [TopP They have[SpecFocP not [FocP kids [TopP [They don’t have kids, but children

It makes it explicit that the rest of the proposition in TopP is unambiguously discourse-old information, and the corrected segment kid is in Focus, under the direct scope of negation in SpecFocP. More would need to be said about the treatment of the correcting segment but children. A plausible proposal is that of Bianchi & Zamparelli (2004), for whom the two conjuncts figure in the Focus projection.

The explicitness of the model allows some of the potential difficulties to be spelled out. One is the fact that the Focus is not always a discrete continuous sequence. There is no clearly identifiable corrected segment in the following, where the existence of a referent, and the responsibility for an action are concerned respectively.

(38) Strawson (1964; cited by von Fintel 2004)
  Whoever the Exhibition was visited by yesterday, it was not visited by the King of France, since there is no such person.
(39) Geurts (1998: 6, example (12))
  A: ‘You left the door open.’
  B: ‘I didn’t leave the door open – you can close it yourself if you wish.’

It could be assumed in these cases that it is the clause as a whole that is in Focus, in which case the opportunity is lost to note explicitly that it was also discourse-old (for the role of Topichood for the King of France cases, see Brandtler 2006; Abrusán & Szendrői 2013). Here, it might be useful to explore how such sequences are dealt with in overt Focus marking languages. Maybe in fact there are reasons to treat those as denial rather than Metalinguistic. This is definitely an area for future work.

Yet another issue is that of syntactic islands. Movement to the Focus position should be constrained by general rules on syntactic operation. One such well-known rule is the ban of movement out of syntactic islands. With normal negative focus, the targeted element cannot be inside e.g. adjuncts headed by before. As a result, a sequence like John didn’t start talking before he had greeted everybody cannot mean that the talking started at a time when not everybody had been greeted. Yet, there seems to be nothing objectionable to the metalinguistic focus being in an island.

(40) A. ‘Bush acted before Iran went nucular.’
  B. ‘Bush didn’t act before Iran went nucular; he acted before it went nuclear.’

Why there is no barrier to Focus movement in MLN remains to be explained.

Thus, MLN can be mapped onto a cartographic analysis. Such an analysis records the informational partition between explicitly discourse-old information and the Focus status of the corrected segment. Foreseeable difficulties include cases where there is no specific item that is objected to that can be raised to a Focus position, and movement escaping island effects. Having raised these open questions, I summarise in the next section the novel proposals put forward in this paper.

5 Conclusion

This paper proposes a definition of metalinguistic negation (MLN) illustrated by They don’t have kids, they have children. MLN is defined as a corrective speech-act that ranges over discourse-old information, the corrected part of which is transformed into discourse-new information by virtue of being in Focus.

The definition is used to answer four main questions.

i. Why is MLN relating to a special behaviour of connectives?
(2) a. They don’t have kids, (*but) they have children.
  c. They don’t have kids, *(but) children.
(19) a. They have children, (*but) they don’t have kids.
  c. They have children, (*but) not kids.
ii. How is MLN (5a) distinguished from denial (5b) and descriptive (5c) uses?
(5) a. They don’t have kids, they have children.
  b. That’s not true! They do not have kids.
  c. At least, they don’t have kids.
iii. What properties relate MLN, other corrective constructions ((24)–(27)) and metalinguistic configurations ((28)–(31))?
(24) I want to buy not pants, but trousers.
(25) I want to buy trousers, not pants.
(26) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. You mean you want to buy trousers.
(27) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. Trousers.
(28) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. If you want to buy pants, you must be an American in need of trousers.
(29) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. It might be better around here to ask for trousers rather than pants.
(30) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. Are you maybe looking for trousers?
(31) A. I want to buy pants.
  B. Pants?
iv. why is MLN felt to be marked?

The characteristic properties that separate MLN from other types of negative uses is that it is a reactive, corrective speech-act. The speech-act dimension accounts for the mysterious behaviour of connectives. I have argued that the impossibility for a metalinguistically negated sequence to be followed by connective but introducing a full clause

(2) a. They don’t have kids, (*but) they have children.

is due to the fact that such coordination would allow the sequence to be understood as two speech-acts; yet, a single speech-act is represented by MLN, as shown by the lack of autonomy of its component parts that cannot express independent speech-acts.

MLN proposes a correction, that neither denial (5b) nor descriptive (5c) uses necessarily suppose. This underlies the paradoxical informational organisation that relates MLN to other corrective constructions. MLN ranges over discourse-old information, as with corrective structures. As with corrective structures, MLN has a corrected segment that is part of the discourse-old sequence, and yet treated as discourse-new by virtue of being in Focus, and contrasted to the correcting segment. The focus on the corrected and correcting segments is what MLN have in common with other metalinguistic configurations. The paradoxical Information Structure of MLN, corrective constructions and metalinguistic configurations account for their equally marked status. They turn the corrected segment of discourse-old information into discourse-new focal material. By upsetting the normal flow of information, they constitute marked uses that are intuitively rare19 and require contextual cues to arise. By having put forward a novel definition of MLN that rests on two properties, I hope to have contributed to defining the metalinguistic usage of negation.

This article has raised a number of topics for future work.20 In particular, more needs to be known about the competition between connectives in view of MLN and denial uses of negation, and whether the equivalents of but distribute between the two readings in a language-specific or in a cross-linguistically stable way. Also, the relationship between MLN and denial uses seem to overlap in some cases. There are cases where it is the whole of the clause that is rejected:

(38) Strawson (1964; cited by von Fintel 2004)
  Whoever the Exhibition was visited by yesterday, it was not visited by the King of France, since there is no such person.
(40) No you dumbazz. I’m not her husband………. She’s my wife.
  (www.topix.com/forum/city/heidrick-ky/…/p2971?print=1)

One might therefore assume these to be simple denials. However, the target interpretation is available only when ranging over discourse-old material, and exclusively with a correction. The complementary distribution of a MLN that relates to a focused segment, and denial that relates to the clause as a whole seems to collapse. A further example (provided by Laurence R. Horn) is from an ad which against the background image of bread dough being kneaded stakes the following claim:

    1. (41)
    1. German
    1. Ich
    2. 1-SG.NOM
    1. backe
    2. bake-PR.1SG
    1. keine
    2. no
    1. Brötchen.
    2. bread
    1.  
    1. Ich
    2. 1-SG.NOM
    1. arbeite
    2. work-PR.1SG
    1. am
    2. on
    1. perfekten
    2. perfect
    1. Morgen.
    2. morning
    1. ‘I do not bake buns. I work on the perfect morning.’

The target interpretation requires the correction, that bears on (almost) all of the clause, that is discourse-old by accommodation, and transformed into discourse-new information because of its focal status. While this does not affect the definition of MLN as a corrective act that turns the corrected, old information into new, it shows that the border between MLN and denial should be revisited in further work. The ability to frame these questions is hopefully an indication of the fruitfulness of the claims made in this paper that MLN is a corrective speech-act that has a paradoxical Information Structure.

Abbreviations

FOC = Focus, MLN = Metalinguistic negation, NEG = Negation, NEG1 = Postverbal negation, NEG2 = Preverbal negation, NOM = Nominative, PL = Plural, PR = Present, SG = Singular

Notes

  1. Similarly, “the disagreement between the parties to the discourse is not over matters of fact but over what words they ought to use in referring to the things they are talking about” (McCawley 1991: 190). A reviewer asserts that “what the negation in (1) corrects is not the proposition that they have kids, but the metalinguistic proposition that their children can properly be called kids.” Another reviewer suggests that this may be captured by “an implicit or abstract “APPROPRIATE” operator” commanding the corrected segment. The ad hoc operator might technically work for MLN, but makes the wrong prediction for other metalinguistic configurations discussed in this paper. In Since they moved to New York, they are stressed out, it is not the (referential) appropriateness of the expression stressed out that is being considered, but rather the (sociolinguistic) fact that it is an Americanism. Appropriateness seems to derive from MLN (if an item is corrected, it is probably because it is judged inappropriate by the speaker), rather than metalinguistic value itself. [^]
  2. In this paper, following the recommendation of reviewers, I am steering clear of cardinals, of the type She doesn’t have three children, she has four. A reviewer proposes that there is a consensus in the literature that cardinals “express ‘exactly n’ and do not merely implicate an upper bound, contra Horn’s original Gricean analysis; cf. e.g. Koenig (1991), Fretheim (1992), Horn (1992), Geurts (1998), and especially Bultinck (2005).” Cardinals would therefore behave differently from other scalars in discourse: the question whether someone solved three theorems apparently cannot be answered without knowing if the speaker means exactly three or at most three, whereas there is no such requirement on answering the question whether someone solve some theorems. Cardinals are also less resilient in understatements: the statement Lise has three children when Lise has four is more likely to be judged false than Luke ate most of the cake when Luke ate it all: Papafragou and Musolino (2003), Hurewitz et al. (2006), Huang et al. (2013) and Doran et al. (2012) are cited. Regarding specifically MLN, it is true that while formulaic expressions specialised in denial are particularly infelicitous with MLN, they are less so with cardinal MLN:
    (i) ?*Like hell they have kids, they have children.
    (ii)   ?Like hell she has three children, she has four.
    This is not to say however that MLN of cardinals do not conform to the general definition put forward in this paper. [^]
  3. As correctly pointed out by a reviewer, such a proposal exists, as according to Carston MLN like other ML cases are explicitly echoic. It is however not clear how this differentiates MLN from denial. Both MLN (5a) and denial (5b) are (normally) explicitly echoic. Such a differentiation should be identified by a definition of MLN. [^]
  4. An argument against a non-truth-conditional treatment of negative uses is provided by a reviewer, who points out that Horn himself (1989/2001: 486–490) recognises that the negation of the existence presupposition of definiteness (as in The king of France isn’t bald – there isn’t any king of France) yields a true negative claim. [^]
  5. The association between uses and connective is not as categorical as Moeschler might wish it to be: au contraire and mais can also be used with MLN; also, puisque could very well be used for descriptive negation. [^]
  6. A reviewer finds (4b) not as bad as McCawley did. The following might be more convincing minimal pairs.
    (i) A.   Did you really say to the Spencers that the Duchess has kids?
      B. ?I didn’t say to anyone that she has kids, but children.
    (ii) A.   Did you really say to the Spencers that the Duchess has kids?
      B. *I said to no one that she has kids, but children.
    (iii) A.   Did you really say that the Duchess has kids to the Spencers?
      B. *I said that she has kids, but children to no one.
    The issue of acceptability is of course related to that of elicitations (see i.a. the discussion in Grisot 2017). [^]
  7. Thanks to Genoveva Puskas for discussions on this. [^]
  8. Thus, Not “Abi is beautiful.” but “Boy, is Abi beautiful!” is a plausible sequence; but the negative is not part of the sentence that it corrects; and it comes under the global assertive act of correction that it cannot itself challenge. [^]
  9. Although they do suppose an alternative, as demonstrated a contrario by the following syntactic pun.
    (i) Wolverhampton has won the annual English heritage most beautiful city award not once, not twice, not three times… obviously. (laughter.) Wolverhampton’s first railway station (laughter) was at Henfield’s heath. (I’m sorry I haven’t a clue, BBC4, 5 dec 2016, episode 4, series 66)
    [^]
  10. See also Mignon (2008) on the differences between metalinguistic and denial fragment constructions in French; it may be as Mignon suggests that while MLN correction is not an elliptical structure – see Neeleman & Vermeulen (2011) – denial is. [^]
  11. Discourse-old is used as synonymous to given or activated, and refers to the property of a linguistic sequence that represents information made available to the hearer by virtue of explicit use in the antecedent context (explicit activation), or of accommodating constructions or inferential relations (accommodated and inferred activation) (Dryer 1996; Schwenter 2005; Larrivée 2012). While the paucity of MLN in actual usage has not made it easy to conduct corpus studies of it (but see indications in Silvennoinen 2017), the assumption that it refers to an explicitly used sequence is supported by the following, where only the explicitly discourse-old case is fully acceptable (the acceptability judgements characterising the response in relation to the initial assertion).
    (i)     A. Iran is going nucular.
      OKB. Iran isn’t going nucular, but nuclear.
    (ii)     A. I’m concerned that Iran is going nuclear.
      ??B. Iran isn’t going nucular, but nuclear.
          vs  
      OKB’. Well, Iran isn’t going nuclear.
    (iii)     A. I’m glad that we’re visiting Iran next month.
      ?*B. Iran isn’t going nucular, but nuclear.
          vs  
      OKB’. Thank God Iran isn’t going nuclear then.
    See Larrivée (2015) on types of discourse-old information. It is however true that there are occasional attestations of MLN that do not reject material explicitly used before (Horn 2014; Davis 2016). Manipulated for effect, these tend to be found in advertising and political speeches. The crucial point is that the information is accommodated as discourse-old. An interesting subcase of this is the reference to linguistic practices of (groups of) speakers, as with the Carston example in (15). In the following elicitations the out-of-the-blue use of a metalinguistic description ((iv)) and negation ((v), (vi)) refers to the linguistic practice of a group or of an individual.
    (iv) After all, Obama is not the kind of politician who fears nucular power.
    (v) Now, in Québec, note that we don’t go to the corner store, we go to the dépanneur. (volunteered by Brandon Waldon)
    (vi) The royal family are very proper. They don’t have kids, they have children. (volunteered by a reviewer)
    Without such a reference, there is no accommodation. Consider the following out-of-blue statement:
    (vii) After all, you wouldn’t want to suffer from maclar degeneration.
    Unless someone is known to the hearer and speaker to confuse maclar with macular, it is difficult to see how such a statement is relevant in the context, and the statement should be infelicitous, or at the very least quite odd. [^]
  12. A reviewer suggests that contrastive Focus may not always be new information:

    For example, {What/The only one} he cares about is himself, there’s focus on himself (one element within a relevant set of alternatives corresponding to possible objects of his caring) but as indicated by the reflexive form, it’s not a discourse-new item. Similarly, if you ask me if John or Mary solved the problem and I say MARY did (or it’s MARY that solved it), again, Mary is old (but her value as value of the relevant variable x in who is the x such that… is new in the sense of unpredictable).

    Yet in either case, contrastive Focus is new information following the interpretation of unpredictability of the entity chosen from a set of alternatives at that point in discourse. [^]
  13. Strong evidence of the Focus status of the corrected segment is provided by languages with overt Focus morphological marking. A Focus marking language is Yoruba (Niger-Congo family) in which the Focus of negation is followed by the negative and a focusing particle (Fábùmni 2013: 2).
      1. (i)
      1. Yoruba (Fábùmni 2013: 2).
      1. O̩ba
      2. king
      1. NEG
      1. ni
      2. FOC
      1. ó
      2. 3-SG-NOM
      1. pàse
      2. give-order-PST
      1. yìí.
      2. this
      1. ‘It was not the king who gave this order.’
    See also Wolff reports (2009: 39) on Afro-Asiatic Lamang, and Robert (2010) on Niger-Congo Wolof. [^]
  14. On the role of prosodic focus in motivating the MLN reading, a reviewer points to King & Stanley (2005). [^]
  15. Note the differential paraphrases of not sometimes and not almost in English (34)–(35) (never and not at all) as compared to their French equivalent (18b) and (18a) (always and indeed). This interesting empirical point should hopefully be explained by future research. [^]
  16. An interesting question raised by a reviewer is in what sense the phonological material corrected, in e.g. Bush didn’t act before Iran went nucular; he acted before it went nuclear, can be treated as information. My answer is that it is information when it is in Focus. The corrected phonological material would be information in the assertion It’s nuclear, in reaction to Iran is going nucular, the point of which is to communicate to the hearer the pronunciation believed to be correct by the speaker, and the pronunciation of words is a piece of information. [^]
  17. More needs to be known about the discursive and psychological effects of garden-path cases of MLN, as pointed out by a reviewer. [^]
  18. Cristina Grisot points out that this is in contradiction with experimental results from Noh, Choo & Ko (2013) and from Blochowiak, Grisot & Moeschler (2016) that evidence no asymmetry between the types of negative uses. This may be to the fact that in Korean, MLN is related to a long marker of negation. The protocol in Blochowiak, Grisot & Moeschler (2016) consist in comparing sentences to pictures, rather than assessing sentences in a linguistic context. What’s more, the focus of negation is in the same post-verbal position both for descriptive and metalinguistic cases (The shoe isn’t big, it’s small/enormous), which might explain the comparable processing time. [^]
  19. This remains to be established, as pointed out by a reviewer. One difficulty, that proves the point, is that MLN is so rare that looking for it in a corpus can be a long and frustrating affair. A preliminary look at a corpus of French political speeches where MLN should be prevalent point to a rate well under 0.5% of MLN usage among clausal negatives. The same conclusion is reached independently by Silvennoinen (2017), who, looking at contrastive constructions where MLN should be common, finds that they are less than 1% in written material, and even rarer in spoken material. [^]
  20. Other topics for future research raised by reviewers are corpus investigations of MLN, an assessment of their contribution to discursive interaction, and an extensive cross-linguistic survey of morpho-syntactic reflexes. [^]

Acknowledgements

This paper has benefited from the constructive comments of the participants at the Université de Genève Linguistics Department Seminar in March 2017, the workshop Negation and Negativity in Natural Language at Ruhr-Universität Bochum in April 2017, the conference The Pragmatics of Negation – Aspects of Communication at Stockholm Universitet in May 2017, and the workshop Left Periphery Reloaded at Universität Zürich in December 2017, where it was presented; of the editors of this issue; and of the three reviewers of this journal. Any remaining infelicities are my sole responsibility.

Competing Interests

The author has no competing interests to declare.

References

Abrusán, Márta & Kriszta Szendrői. 2013. Experimenting with the king of France: Topics, verifiability and definite descriptions. Semantics and Pragmatics 6. 1–43.

Albu, Elena. 2017. Description versus Rejection in the analysis of negation: Evidence from Romanian and English. Lingua 191–192. 22–41. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2017.02.001

Anscombre, Jean-Claude & Oswald Ducrot. 1977. Deux mais en français? Lingua 43. 23–40. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/0024-3841(77)90046-8

Attal, Pierre. 1990. Le concept d’anormal est introduit dans la description sémantique d’énoncés. Linx 22. 43–53. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3406/linx.1990.1145

Batllori, Montserrat. 2016. The significance of formal features in language change theory and the evolution of minimizers. In Pierre Larrivée & Chungmin Lee (eds.), Negation and polarity: Experimental perspectives, 347–377. Cham: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-17464-8_15

Bianchi, Valentina & Roberto Zamparelli. 2004. Edge coordinations: Focus and conjunction reduction. David Adger, Cécile de Cat & George Tsoulas (eds.), Peripheries: Syntactic edges and their effects, 313–327. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Bîlbîie, Gabriela & Grégoire Winterstein. 2011. Expressing contrast in Romanian. The conjunction iar. In Janine Berns, Haike Jacobs & Tobias Scheer (eds.), Romance Languages and Linguistic Theory 2009: Selected papers from ‘Going Romance’ Nice 2009, 1–18. Amsterdam: Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/rllt.3.01bil

Blochowiak, Joanna, Cristina Grisot & Jacques Moeschler. 2016. Is negation ambiguous? Descriptive and metalinguistic uses of negation under experimental and theoretical perspectives. Presentation, Fribourg, February 2016.

Brandtler, Johan. 2006. On Aristotle and baldness – Topic, reference, presupposition of existence, and negation. Working Papers in Scandinavian Syntax 77. 177–204.

Burton-Roberts, Noel. 1989. On Horn’s dilemma: Presupposition and negation. Journal of Linguistics 25. 95–125. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226700012111

Carston, Robyn. 1988. Implicature, explicature and truth-theoretic semantics. Ruth Kempson (ed.), Mental representations: The interface between language and reality, 155–181. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Carston, Robyn. 1996. Metalinguistic negation and echoic use. Journal of Pragmatics 25(3). 309–330. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/0378-2166(94)00109-X

Dancygier, Barbara. 1992. Two metatextual operators: Negation and conditionality in English and Polish. Berkeley Linguistic Society 18. 61–75. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/bls.v18i1.1601

Davis, Wayne A. 2016. Irregular negatives, implicatures and idioms. Cham: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7546-5

Déprez, Viviane, Susagna Tubau, Anne Cheylus & Maria Teresa Espinal. 2015. Double negation in a negative concord language: An experimental investigation. Lingua 163. 75–107. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2015.05.012

Dryer, Matthew S. 1996. Focus, pragmatic presupposition, and activated propositions. Journal of Pragmatics 26. 475–523. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/0378-2166(95)00059-3

Ducrot, Oswald. 1972. Dire et ne pas dire. Paris: Hermann.

Dynel, Marta. 2004. Humorous garden-paths: A pragmatic-cognitive study. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars.

Fábùmni, Felix Abídèmí. 2013. Negation in sixteen Yorùbá dialects. Open Journal of Modern Linguistics 3. 1–8. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.4236/ojml.2013.31001

Fleckenstein, Kristen & Suwon Yoon. 2016. Jespersen’s Cycle and scope of negation in American Sign Language. Presentation at GLOW. Göttingen, April 2016.

Foolen, A. d. 1991. Metalinguistic negation and pragmatic ambiguity: Some comments on a proposal by Laurence Horn. Pragmatics 1(2). 217–237. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/prag.1.2.02foo

Geurts, Bart. 1998. The mechanisms of denial. Language 74. 274–307. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.1998.0264

Geurts, Bart & Emar Maier. 2005. Quotation in context. Belgian Journal of Linguistics 17. 109–128. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/bjl.17.07geu

Giannakidou, Anastasia & Suwon Yoon. 2011. The subjective mode of comparison: Metalinguistic comparatives in Greek and Korean. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 29. 621–655. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-011-9133-5

Grisot, Christina. 2017. A quantitative approach to conceptual, procedural and pragmatic meaning: Evidence from inter-annotator agreement. Journal of Pragmatics 117. 245–263. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2017.06.020

Halliday, Michael A. K. 1967. Note on transitivity and theme in English. Journal of Linguistics 3. 199–244. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226700016613

Horn, Laurence R. 1985. Metalinguistic negation and pragmatic ambiguity. Language 61(1). 121–174. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.2307/413423

Horn, Laurence R. 1989/2001. A natural history of negation. Chicago, IL: The Chicago University Press.

Horn, Laurence R. 2014. Metalinguistic negation and “double processing”. Hand-out, Yale University.

Jiang, Can Zhong. 2015. Nature and categorization of Metalinguistic Negation. Theory & Practice in Language Studies 5(3). 598–604. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.17507/tpls.0503.20

Kadmon, Nirit. 2001. Formal pragmatics: Semantics, pragmatics, presupposition, and focus. Oxford: Wiley.

Kawamura, Tomoko. 2007. Some interactions of focus and focus-sensitive elements. New York: Stony Brook University dissertation.

King, Jeffrey & Jason Stanley. 2005. Semantics, pragmatics, and the role of semantic context. In Zoltan Szabó (ed.), Semantics vs. pragmatics, 111–64. Oxford: Clarendon. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199251520.003.0005

Kiss, Katalin É. 1998. Identificational focus versus information focus. Language 74. 245–273. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.1998.0211

Kolokonte, Marina. 2008. Bare argument ellipsis and Information Structure. Newcastle: Newcastle University dissertation.

Kroeger, Paul. 2014. External negation in Malay/Indonesian. Language 90(1). 137–184. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2014.0000

Larrivée, Pierre. 2011. La définition de la négation métalinguistique. In Jacqueline Bacha, Ammar Azouzi & Khaled Salddem (eds), La négation en discours, 53–69. Sousse.

Larrivée, Pierre. 2012. Positive polarity, negation, activated propositions. Linguistics 50(4). 869–900. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/ling-2012-0027

Larrivée, Pierre. 2015. The syntax of pragmatics: The case of presuppositional negatives. Syntaxe et Sémantique 15. 115–138.

Martins, Ana Maria. 2014. How much syntax is there in metalinguistic negation? Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 32. 635–672. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-013-9221-9

Martins, Ana Maria. 2016. VSX in non-wh sentences (a view from European Portuguese). Presentation at Going Romance. Frankfurt, December 2016.

McCawley, James. 1991. Contrastive negation and metalinguistic negation. In Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS) 27. Vol. 2: The parasession on negation, 189–206.

Mignon, Françoise. 2008. Le choix du marqueur de négation dans l’expression du contraste. Revue Romane 43(1). 63–85. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/rro.43.1.06mig

Moeschler, Jacques. 2013. Négation, portée et distinction négation descriptive/métalinguistique. In Jacques François, Pierre Larrivée, Dominique Legallois & Franck Neveu (eds.), La linguistique de la contradiction, 163–179. Bern: Peter Lang.

Moeschler, Jacques. 2015. Qu’y a-t-il de représentationnel dans la négation métalinguistique? Nouveaux cahiers de linguistique française 32. 11–26.

Moeschler, Jacques. 2016. A criterion for descriptive vs. metalinguistic negation. Presentation at SLE 2016. Naples, August 2016.

Neeleman, A. d. & Reiko Vermeulen. 2011. Interpreting focus under negation. Ms.

Noh, Eun-Ju, Hyeree Choo & Sungryong Koh. 2013. Processing metalinguistic negation: Evidence from eyetracking experiments. Journal of Pragmatics 57. 1–18. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2013.07.005

Pitts, Alyson. 2011. Exploring a ‘pragmatic ambiguity’ of negation. Language 87(2). 346–368. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2011.0035

Rizzi, Luigi. 1997. The fine structure of the left periphery. In Liliane Haegeman (ed.), Elements of grammar, 281–337. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-5420-8_7

Robert, Stéphane. 2010. Focus in Atlantic languages. In Ines Fiedler & Anne Schwarz (eds.), Information Structure in African languages, 233–260. Amsterdam: Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/tsl.91.09rob

Roberts, Craige. 1996. Information Structure: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. In Jae Hak Yoon & Andreas Kathol (eds.), OSUWPL, Vol. 49: Papers in semantics. Columbus, OH: The Ohio State University Department of Linguistics.

Rooth, Mats. 1996. Focus. In Shalom Lappin (ed.), The handbook of contemporary semantic theory, 271–297. Oxford: Blackwell.

Rooth, Mats. 2016. Alternative semantics. In Caroline Féry & Shinichiro Ishihara (eds.), The Oxford handbook of Information Structure, 19–40. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Schwenter, Scott A. 2002. Discourse markers and the PA/SN distinction. Journal of Linguistics 38. 43–69. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226701001232

Schwenter, Scott A. & Mary Johnson. 2011. Neg Nada constructions in comparative perspective: Brazilian Portuguese and Argentinian Spanish. Presentation at IPRA 12. University of Manchester, July 2011.

Seuren, Pieter A. 1988. Presupposition and negation. Journal of Semantics 6. 175–226. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/6.1.175

Silvennoinen, Olli O. 2017. Contrastive negation in English: Constructions in a register perspective. Presentation at The Pragmatics of Negation – Aspects of Communication. Stockholm Universitet, May 2017.

van der Sandt, Rob. 1991. Denial. In Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS) 27, Vol. 2: Parasession on negation, 331–344.

von Fintel, Kai. 2004. Would you believe it? The king of France is back! (presuppositions and truth-value intuitions). In Anne Bezuidenhout & Marga Reimer (eds.), Descriptions and beyond: An interdisciplinary collection of essays on definite and indefinite descriptions and other related phenomena, 269–296. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Wible, David & Eva Chen. 2000. Linguistic limits on metalinguistic negation: Evidence from English and Chinese. Language and linguistics 1(2). 233–255.

Wolff, H. Ekkehard. 2009. The impact of clause types and focus control, aspect, modality, and referentiality on negation in Lamang and Hdi (Central Chadic). In Norbert Cyffer, Erwin Ebermann & Georg Ziegelmeyer (eds.), Negation patterns in West African languages and beyond, 21–56. Amsterdam: Benjamins.