1 Introduction
Since the publication of Larson’s (1988) analysis of ditransitive verbs as involving a layered V, the study of little v (or simply v) has taken different forms. While Kratzer (1996) noted that a Voice head is responsible for the external argument (namely, agent) of a predicate, Chomsky (1995) first proposed the v head, which became an increasingly important topic and received considerable attention among linguists. Within Distributed Morphology, v is assumed to be a ‘verbalizer’, the head that transforms a category-neutral root into a verb. Harley (1995) and Marantz (1997) maintain that v must be present in unaccusative and unergative sentences as well as in transitive sentences. In other analyses, v has been thought of as encoding inner aspectual information (e.g., Folli & Harley 2005; Ramchand 2008; 2013). Much debate has followed since these first formulations, and many different functions have been attributed to v. I hardly attempt to summarize the diverse and insightful findings of the previous studies here. The objectives of this article are:
To show that supralexical causation (and not temporality) is the necessary interpretive perspective encoded in [V] on v (e.g., Wechsler 2005; Harley 2009; 2013a), and
To argue, along the similar lines in Copley & Wolff (2014) and Copley & Harley (2015), for a force-theoretic approach to the causal nature of v.
Working in the framework of Halle & Marantz’s (1993) Distributed Morphology, Panagiotidis (2009; 2011; 2013; 2015) proposes that a [V] feature on v imposes an extending-into-time perspective at LF, whereas an [N] feature on n imposes a sortal perspective at LF. In other words, Panagiotidis claims that the LF-interpretable categorial features [N] and [V], providing sortal and temporal perspectives, respectively, are what make the categorizers n and v semantically distinct. In section 2, after a brief summary of this proposal, I argue that defining temporality in nominals cannot be so easily dispensed with for three main reasons: (i) the time component in nominals provides the to-be-modified element for temporal modifiers, (ii) there is a temporal relation between predicates and their arguments, and (iii) a temporal setting is needed for the interpretation of epistemic adjectives. Then, based on evidence from the adjectival syntax, the morphological expression of time within the nominal domain and the fixed order of adjectives, I argue that the temporal dimension of nominals can be syntactically represented via Nominal Tense (TN) and Nominal Aspect (AspN). On the basis of these arguments, I claim that temporality is not the distinctive feature of v and that Tense is not an exclusively verbal projection. In section 3 I demonstrate, with reference to the (un)grammaticality pattern found in the verbal and nominal forms of Marantz’s (1997) “destroy”, “grow” and “break” classes of roots, that supralexical causation is the interpretive perspective encoded in v, but not in n. Here, the term “supralexical causation” refers to the extra-root causal meaning, defined as an apparatus of forces and a position vector. This causal apparatus licenses the linguistic expression of an external and/or internal cause not licensed by the roots alone. I further argue that Voice does not contribute to the causal meaning of the construction. My arguments rely on the theoretical assumptions of Phase Theory (Chomsky 2001; 2008; 2013) and the presence of Voice in the nominal domain. In section 4, after a short introduction to “make-a-difference” and “generative” theories of causation, following Wolff (2003; 2007; 2014), Copley & Wolff (2014) and Copley & Harley (2015), I take up a force-theoretic approach to the meaning of causation in terms of a causal apparatus that includes a configuration of various forces and a position vector. After this, I portray how this framework can be applied into the causal nature of v and how distinct flavors of v, namely vCAUSE, vDO, vBECOME and vBE, are differentiated in such an account. I dedicate section 5 to concluding thoughts and some issues for further research.
2 [V] on v: A Temporal Feature?
In this section I briefly review Panagiotidis’ account of categorizers and categorial features, and provide several pieces of evidence against his proposal that [V] on v encodes an extending-into-time perspective.
2.1 LF-Interpretable Categorial Features
Adhering to Distributed Morphology (Halle & Marantz 1993; Marantz 1997; 2000; 2006; Harley & Noyer 1999; Embick 2000; among many others) and drawing on Embick and Marantz’s (2008) Categorization Assumption, that roots can appear in syntactic structures only as the complements of categorizers where they are assigned a category and become related to concepts, Panagiotidis (2009) points out that “‘noun’, ‘verb’ and ‘adjective’ are not categorial labels specified on lexical items in a pre-syntactic lexicon,” rather “roots are inserted bare in syntax and the assignment of roots to categories is a syntactic process” where “categorizers – a nominalizer (n), a verbalizer (v) and an adjectivizer (a) – make them nouns, verbs or adjectives.”1,2 Since nPs and vPs are phases, once they are constructed, they must receive phonological and semantic interpretations at the interfaces to the Sensory-Motor (SM) and Conceptual-Intentional (C-I) systems (e.g., Chomsky 2001; 2008). Panagiotidis (2009; 2011; 2013; 2015: Ch. 4) proposes that the (first) phase heads n and v are distinct categorizers because they bear different LF-interpretable categorial features, namely [N] and [V].3 He employs Baker’s (2003) idea that category distinctions must correspond to perspectives on (concepts about) the world and argues that these features impose different perspectives, ‘contexts’, on concepts in their complements (i.e., in their phase domains). The interpretive perspective, in Panagiotidis’ analysis, is necessary for the semantically underspecified and impoverished root to be interpreted at the C-I system. The categorial features [N] and [V] on the categorizers n and v persuasively “close off material associated with the root exactly by providing it with a fundamental perspective for the conceptual systems to view it in” (Panagiotidis 2009). [N] and [V], providing sortal and temporal perspectives, respectively, make the categorizers n and v semantically distinct, as described in (1).
- (1)
- LF-interpretation of categorial features
- An [N] feature imposes a sortal perspective on the categorizer’s complement at LF.
- A [V] feature imposes an extending-into-time perspective on the categorizer’s complement at LF.
- (Panagiotidis 2015: 84, (7))
Baker (2003: 95) claims that nouns are semantically differentiated from verbs by “criteria of identity, whereby they can serve as standards of sameness.” A criterion of identity marks nouns as kind-denoting and this lexical property gives rise to the idea that nouns encode referential power manifested as a referential index in syntax (Baker 2003: Ch. 3; cf. Wunderlich 1996). Identity is also considered to be a criterion of sortality by Prasada (2008). He notes that sortality incorporates three criteria: application, identity and individuation. The criterion of application “means that the representation is understood to apply to things of a certain kind, but not others. Thus, the sortal DOG allows us to think about dogs, but not tables, trees, wood or any other kind of thing,” the criterion of identity “provides the basis for thoughts like dogs, [which] by virtue of being dogs, remain dogs throughout their existence,” and the criterion of individuation states that “two instances of a kind are distinct because they are the kinds of things they are” (Prasada 2008: 6–8).
To explore what nominality means, Panagiotidis (2009; 2011: 371–372; 2013; 2015: 85–86) diverges from Baker’s (2003) stance of regarding [N] as encoding kinds and employs Prasada’s (2008) criteria of “application” and “identity” to define sortality. Following Acquaviva’s (2009: 1) proposal that nouns are sorts, or kind-level entities, “defining the categories of entities in a speaker’s conceptualization of the world,” Panagiotidis then emphasizes that the sortal interpretive perspective of nominals grows out of kinds.4
To argue for the temporal perspective that [V] imposes on the root, following Uriagereka (1999) and referring to Ramchand’s (2008) idea that “VP is the heart of the dynamic predicate, since it represents change through time,” Panagiotidis (2011: 372–373; 2013; 2015: 86–88) notes that verbal constituents are inherently (sub-)eventive by virtue of the temporal perspective contributed by the categorial feature [V] to event structures, and that Voice, Aspect and Tense exclusively combine with verbs because of the ‘extending into time’ perspective that [V] imposes on the root. In §2.2, I provide several pieces of evidence that nominal constituents possess temporal and aspectual interpretations. Also, I argue that including Tense and Aspect as functional projections in the nominal spine not only establishes links for the temporal and aspectual interpretations of noun phrases at the syntax-semantics interface but also explains the fixed order of epistemic and non-epistemic modal adjectives with respect to temporal adjectives (see also Ilkhanipour 2015; 2016). If my arguments are on the right track, then nominal constituents, like verbal constituents, are subject to Voice, Aspect and Tense systems. This ensures that a similar, if not precisely identical, extending-into-time perspective is available in the nominal domain and hence, temporality cannot introduce a plausible distinction between n and v.
2.2 Temporality in the Nominal Domain
Let us begin with Musan’s (1995) observation that noun phrases can be modified by various kinds of temporal expressions, as shown in (2), and that these temporal modifiers can modify nouns denoting life-time or temporary properties, as in (2a) and (2b), respectively.
- (2)
- a.
- clausal modifiers: [The war when my grandfather was young] lasted four years.
- b.
- genitive modifiers: [The sixties’ rebels] are quite established today.
- c.
- adverbial modifiers: [The quarrel yesterday] was totally superfluous.
- d.
- adjectival modifiers: [The present wife of Klaus] is [a former student of his].
- e.
- prepositional modifiers: [The chancellor in 1989] made some serious mistakes.
- (Musan 1995: 160, (1a–e))
Noun phrases can also be modified by aspectual adjectives, as shown in (3).
- (3)
- the gradual/sudden change in the climate
The temporal and aspectual modification of noun phrases, as in (2) and (3), leaves space for the hypothesis that nominals, like verbals, refer to situations that hold at certain times (see also Musan 1999).
Second, the unacceptability of the sentences in (4) can be best justified if we credit the arguments my future job and the present president with some temporal dimension modified by the temporal adjectives future and present (see also Enç 1987).
- (4)
- a.
- #Last week I was dismissed from my future job.
- b.
- #The present president will be elected (president) shortly. (where every person can be president only once)
A relevant discussion of the temporal relation between predicates and their arguments can be found in Musan (1995; 1997; 1999) where existence-implying predicates, including individual-level predicates (e.g., to be from America) and stage-level predicates (e.g., to be happy), are assumed to impose a presuppositional condition on their arguments’ being in existence or alive;5 the utterance John is happy, for instance, is acceptable only if John’s lifetime (i.e., the “time” of John’s existence in the present world) maps onto, or at least covers, the time of his being happy. This issue has been pointed out by Musan also in terms of noun phrases receiving temporally dependent or independent readings (Note that presuming a temporal dimension for noun phrases is crucial for Musan’s discussion):
“A noun phrase occurrence is temporally dependent if and only if its situation time has to intersect with the situation time of the main predicate of its clause.
A noun phrase occurrence is temporally independent if and only if its situation time does not have to intersect with the situation time of the main predicate of its clause.” (Musan 1999: 622)
Third, the acceptability of (5b) in contrast to the unacceptability of (5c) with regard to the situation uttered in (5a) indicates that the noun phrase the probable winner is subject to temporality: the winner is the ‘probable’ winner only before the game finishes. As soon as the game is over, the probable winner is not anymore the ‘probable’ winner; she/he is the winner or the loser. Put it precisely, the epistemic adjective probable is only compatible with noun phrases whose existence time is not in the past of the reference time.6
- (5)
- a.
- The probable winner started clapping.
- b.
- The game had not yet finished when the probable winner started clapping.
- c.
- #The game had finished when the probable winner started clapping.
So, the modification of noun phrases with temporal expressions, the temporal relation between predicates and their arguments and the incompatibility of epistemic adjectives with noun phrases located in the past of the reference time provide evidence for considering some extending-into-time perspective for nominals.7 In the remainder of this subsection, I suggest that Nominal Tense (TN) and Nominal Aspect (AspN) are two functional heads in the extended projection of the nominal spine. I do not attempt to argue that TN and AspN have the same featural specification or semantic properties as their clausal counterparts (Recall that D(eterminer) and its clausal counterpart C(omplementizer) do not have the same syntactic and semantic properties.); however, on the basis of evidence from the location-in-specifier approach to adjectival syntax, the morphological expression of time within the nominal domain, and the fixed order of modal adjectives with respect to temporal adjectives, I indicate that Tense and Aspect do combine with nominals. I argue this even though the combination of temporal markers with nominal constituents results in idiosyncratic, non-compositional readings (see also Alexiadou 2001: 59–66 and Alexiadou 2005 for interesting pieces of evidence for and against Nominal Tense).8
In accordance with Cinque’s (1994; 2010) and Scott’s (2002) proposal that adjectives are base-generated in the specifiers (Specs) of distinct functional projections to which they are associated, I consider the location of temporal adjectives (e.g., present and former in (2d)) to be Spec,TNP and the location of aspectual adjectives (e.g., gradual in (3)) to be Spec,AspNP. Nominal Tense and Nominal Aspect are then two functional projections that not only provide the necessary space for temporal and aspectual adjectives but also contribute to the external and internal temporal interpretation of nouns (See also Alexiadou 2001: 51–56 for arguments on AspP in nominals).
Further, according to Lecarme (1996; 2004; 2008), Sadler and Nordlinger (2001) and Nordlinger and Sadler (2003; 2004a; 2004b), among others, nominals are inflected for tense, aspect and mood in a number of languages. Examples (6) and (7) are two instances from Halkomelem and Guaraní. In these languages, the same set of affixes mark tense on nominals and verbal predicates. Nominal past tense, for example, encoding meanings such as ‘former, ex-, late (dead)’ temporally locates the nominal. When used with a possessed inanimate noun, as in (7), the temporal marker indicates that the possession relation was in the past, or that the possessed item has been destroyed (Burton 1997: 67–68).9
- (6)
- te
- the
- sqwemá:y-elh (Halkomelem)
- dog-PST
- ‘the dead dog’
- (Sadler and Nordlinger 2001)
- (7)
- che-róga-kue (Guaraní)
- 1SG-house-PST
- ‘my former house’
- (from Nordlinger and Sadler 2004a)
The morphological expression of time within the nominal domain provides evidence for the idea that Tense does not exclusively combine with verbs (contra Panagiotidis 2011: 373; 2013; 2015: 88).
Moreover, the study of temporality in the nominal domain provides an exciting opportunity to advance our knowledge of the possible orders of adjectives. In her research, Ilkhanipour (2015; 2016) assumes that, through the appearance of, for instance, temporal adjectives, TN represents the time of existence or occurrence of the modified noun. She argues that much like the position of epistemic and root modals with regard to Tense in the verbal spine, epistemic and root modal adjectives (e.g., probable and reliable, respectively) occupy different positions in the nominal spine with regard to TN. This hierarchy is illustrated in (8).
- (8)
- [Modepis.NP [TNP [Modroot.NP
Ilkhanipour (2015; 2016) discusses that the Persian adjective qæbli ‘previous’ is ambiguous: it may be interpreted as a temporal or ordinal adjective, the latter associated with the highest functional projection in the nominal domain (see also Scott 2002). She points out that when qæbli ‘previous’ occurs with an epistemic adjective, such as Ɂehtemali ‘probable’, it can be interpreted only in the specifier of the ordinal projection, as in (9a), and not as a temporal adjective, as in (9b). Importantly, the unacceptability of (9b) follows from the fact that the past temporal adjective qæbli ‘previous’ yields the certainty of being a winner and this leaves no way for the probability-denoting adjective Ɂehtemali ‘probable’ to be interpreted.
- (9)
- a.
- bærænde-ye
- winner-ez
- Ɂehtemali-ye
- probable-ez
- qæbli (Persian)
- previous
- ‘the previous probable winner’
- (Ilkhanipour 2016: 153, (27))
- b.
- #bærænde-ye
- winner-ez
- qæbli-ye
- previous-ez
- Ɂehtemali (Persian)
- probable
- ‘#the probable previous winner’
- (from Ilkhanipour 2016: 154, (30))
The idea so far is that Tense, Aspect and Modality are not exclusively verbal projections and that temporality is not the property that distinguishes v from n. Before setting out to discuss the causal nature of v, I wish to address two problematic aspects of Acquaviva’s (2008; 2009) non-temporal account of nouns. Panagiotidis’ depriving n from temporality is rooted in Acquaviva’s proposal that reference to temporal constitution is inessential for nouns (including continuants and occurents). There are two main points to be considered here:
First, Acquaviva (2008; 2009) takes collection, growth and destruction as nominalizations with deverbal interpretation (and not nouns). He claims that while these nominals are morphosyntactically nouns, their lexical semantics is entirely determined by the event- and argument-structure of the verbs to collect, to grow and to destroy. Contra this point of view and following Chomsky (1970; 1995; 2020) and Marantz (1997), I believe that nominals like collection, growth and destruction (as opposed to -ing gerunds) are never verbs at any stage in the derivation (see also Grimshaw 1990; Siloni 1997; Harley & Noyer 2000; Alexiadou 2001; Borer 2003). The difference in the argument structure of growing and growth in (10a–b) can be explained if we consider growing a nominalization, a mixed projection involving both v and n, and growth a noun with √GROW directly merged with n (see §3.1 for an explanation of the grammaticality pattern in (10); and see Schoorlemmer 2001; 2002 for details on mixed projections).
- (10)
- a.
- John’s/John growing tomatoes
- b.
- *John’s growth of tomatoes
Second, based on examples (11a–b) from Simons (1987), Acquaviva (2009: 2–3) writes that:
“nouns allow speakers to describe events unfolding in time as if they were complete entities that acquire and lose properties over time. We know that argument or wedding describe events, but we can speak of them as if they could undergo changes in time, as in [(11)]:”
- (11)
- a.
- The argument was calm at first, then it became heated.
- b.
- The wedding moved from the church to the bride’s parents’ house.
- (Simons 1987: 134)
The problem here is that Acquaviva takes into account only the ‘existence/change in time’ of noun phrases and neglects their ‘time of existence/change’. While the former allows speakers to see the referent of the noun phrase as a complete entity existing, moving or changing on the timeline represented by the clausal tense (as in (11)), the latter provides a timeline where the entity/situation comes into existence/starts, develops and vanishes. Although the time of existence/change is usually implied and is recovered in the context of use, it may be explicitly stated via temporal and aspectual markers (affixes, adjectives, etc.). The time clash between the time of the occurrence of the subject argument and the time provided by the clausal Tense in (12) signifies the temporal dimension of noun phrases (see also examples (4a–b) above).
- (12)
- #The argument of tomorrow was calm at first, then it became heated.
These points show, as well put by Acquaviva (2009: 3) himself, the conclusion that “verbal reference has a temporal dimension built in […] [while] nominal reference does not, and can do without such a dimension even when referring to occurrents [l]ike all negative conclusions […] is wide-ranging but also weak. It means that we cannot just apply to nouns the semantic decomposition that works for verbs. It does not mean that event structure never plays any role in the lexical semantics of nouns, but that it is not its fundamental ingredient.” (Italics mine)
In section 3, I will argue that supralexical causation is the necessary interpretive perspective that v imposes on the root.
3 [V] on v: A Causal Feature
Panagiotidis’ (2009; 2011; 2013; 2015) account is based on the sortal/temporal distinction between n and v, and thus it fails to acknowledge the significant role that v plays in determining the argument structure of various constructions, including, most importantly, causative constructions. Wechsler (2005: 193) points out that “what is right about the little v hypothesis and its predecessors is the idea of a generalized grammatical source for agency or causation, apart from the inherent lexical meanings of particular verbs.” In this section, I show that supralexical causation is the interpretive perspective encoded in v, but not in n nor in Voice.
3.1 Causation: Not in n But in v
To argue that v, unlike n, introduces supralexical causation, particularly when the root does not introduce an external and/or internal cause, I makes use of Marantz’s (1997) categorization of roots, reiterated in (13).
- (13)
As shown in (14), verbs of the “destroy” class are generally only transitive while nouns of this class can be transitive or intransitive. Verbs of the “grow” class are either transitive or intransitive while the relevant nouns are only transitive, as shown in (15). And verbs of the “break” class are either transitive or intransitive while nouns of the same class do not take any arguments, as shown in (16) (Marantz 1997).
- (14)
- a.
- The enemy destroyed the city.
- b.
- *The city destroyed.
- c.
- the enemy’s destruction of the city
- d.
- the city’s destruction by the enemy
- (15)
- a.
- John grew tomatoes.
- b.
- Tomatoes grew.
- c.
- *John’s growth of tomatoes
- d.
- the tomatoes’ growth
- (16)
- a.
- John broke the glass.
- b.
- The glass broke.
- c.
- *John’s break of the glass
- d.
- *the glass’s break
A possible explanation of the (un)grammaticality pattern in (14)–(16) is proposed by Alexiadou (2001: 154–155):
[…] whenever a root denotes an externally caused event such as √DESTROY, the specifier of D can be interpreted as an external causer (agent). On the other hand, roots like √GROW which denote an activity that occurs spontaneously, thus being internally caused, do not permit the external causation interpretation of the specifier of D […]. This accounts for the unavailability of transitive nominalizations with verbs like grow entering the causative alternation. Crucially, √GROW can receive an agentive interpretation only if it is inserted under a syntactic causative head.
What I wish to highlight in the quote above is the role of “a syntactic causative head.” If we admit that the verbalizer v, and not the nominalizer n, assigns the interpretive perspective of (supralexical) causation to the category-neutral root, the (un)grammaticality pattern in (14)–(16) will be justified. This account allows the necessary causal relation to be established for the argument(s) involved in causation externally (as in (15a)), internally (as in (16b)) or both externally and internally (as in (16a)) in the verbal domain. On the other hand, the (un)grammaticality of the nominal use of these roots (i.e., where √P is the complement of the nominalizer n) reveals that n is not capable of providing the root with the supralexical causal meaning; only the arguments involved in the inherent (lexical) causal relation set by the root are semantically licensed; for destruction, these arguments are the enemy and the city, and for growth, it is tomatoes. There is not any internal causal relation in break and hence no argument is licensed in its nominal form.
Another candidate for the determination of causal meaning is Voice (see Alexiadou et al. 2015, for instance). Following a substantial literature, in §3.2 I concede the idea that Voice and v are two separate projections. Based on the theoretical assumptions of Phase Theory and the presence of Voice in the nominal domain, I argue that Voice does not contribute to the causal meaning of the construction.
3.2 Causation: Not in Voice But in v
Voice and v are two distinct projections. Based on the interaction of applicative and causative morphology, the existence of two kinds of causatives, and the interaction of passive and verbalizing morphology in Hiaki, Harley (2013a) argues for a tripartite internal structure of the verb phrases, made up of VoiceP, vP and a lexical projection (√P or VP). She cogently distinguishes the external-argument introducing projection VoiceP (Kratzer 1996), which makes no lexical-semantic contribution, from vP whose head hosts causative and verbalizing morphology (Marantz 1997) (see also Pylkkänen 2002; Collins 2005; Alexiadou et al. 2006; 2015; Alexiadou & Doron 2012; Harley 2013b; Merchant 2013; Ilkhanipour & Sugawara 2016; among many others).
Concerning our discussion here, one may claim that the head responsible for the introduction of supralexical causation is Voice. Two arguments can be put forth against this: first, according to Chomsky’s (2001; 2008; 2013) Phase Theory, once a phase (CP or vP) is constructed, its interior (i.e., its complement) is transferred to the interfaces. After interpretation, this complement material is treated as stored and becomes unavailable for further syntactic computation – it becomes “impenetrable.” However, the edge of the phase, that is, the head with anything merged to it and the specifier(s) can be modified in the next higher phase. Let us consider the vP phase. As soon as vP is fully formed, the complement of v is transferred to the C-I system and becomes unavailable to any higher head, namely Voice; therefore, Voice cannot impose a causal perspective onto the complement of v. This is illustrated in (17) (cf. Travis 2013; for the Voice-v order see Cinque 2013 and Harley 2013a).
- (17)
A counter-argument may arise here: upon the √-to-v movement (i.e., internal merge), as is the case of incorporating the root into v (see, e.g., Harley 2007), the root escapes the interior and becomes available to Voice, so that Voice can determine the causative meaning of the sentence. This is not tenable: Voice obviously does not play any role in determining the internal cause, as is the case of The glass broke (16b). Moreover, even if the incorporation account is valid, a copy of the root should stay in the interior of the phase and be transferred to the C-I system for the full interpretation of the √P (or VP) event. This interior copy of the root will not be available to Voice and cannot be dedicated a causal perspective from outside of the phase.
The second argument against the causal interpretation of Voice comes from the presence of Voice in the nominal domain. Based on the presence of manner adverbs (that bear a tight relation to VoiceP) and the morphological reflex of the inclusion of Voice in process nominals, Alexiadou (2001: 47–50) concludes that “process nominals contain a domain that shows clear verbal properties.” While I find Alexiadou’s evidence for VoiceP in nominals quite convincing, I do not regard VoiceP as an exclusively “verbal” projection. In fact, Alexiadou does not distinguish Voice from v in her analysis of functional projections in the nominal domain (see Alexiadou 2001: 56–57, 112; Alexiadou 2019; Yatsushiro & Alexiadou 2020) and this is where my account begins to diverge from hers; I believe that Voice and v are two separate projections and that Voice can be present independent of v. If my account is on the right track, it also deviates from the way of the inclusion of Voice in nominals as presented in Borer (2003), Alexiadou et al. (2007), Sichel (2007), Embick (2010), Anagnostopoulou & Samioti (2013) and Bruening (2013). In their analyses, the presence of Voice is dependent on the presence of v, as shown in (18) below. (For earlier studies on the properties of passive nominals, see Cinque 1980; Anderson 1983; Higginbotham 1983; Grimshaw 1990; Giorgi & Longobardi 1991; Picallo 1991; Longobardi 2001; among others).
- (18)
- [ nP [ (VoiceP) [ vP [ √P ]]]]
In lieu of (18), I assume that in the nominal domain, VoiceP is a projection above nP. Consequently, the two different argument structures in the enemy’s destruction of the city (14c) and the city’s destruction by the enemy (14d) mirror those of their sentential counterparts. The Active Voice head (VoiceAct) provides the necessary space (i.e., its Spec) for the external argument, while the Non-Active Voice (VoiceNAct) leaves out the external argument, so that it is introduced in a by-phrase. (19) illustrates the Voice projection in the nominal domain.10 In (19a), the external argument the enemy is located in Spec,VoiceAct, whereas in (19b), the Non-Active Voice does not project a Spec and hence the external argument is added to the construction as the complement of the preposition by.
- (19)
- a.
- b.
Note that the external argument is semantically licensed by the root √DESTROY and the Active Voice only provides a syntactic position for its merger. The ungrammaticality of *John’s growth of tomatoes (15c) and *John’s break of the glass (16c) is not due to the lack of syntactic position but to the deficient semantic licensing; neither the nominalizer n nor the roots √GROW and √BREAK semantically license an external cause.
To sum up, in this section I illustrated that v (or more precisely, [V] on v) encodes causal meaning and that supralexical causation contributes to the semantic licensing of the external and internal arguments in the verbal domain. Different types or flavors of v (i.e., vCAUSE, vDO, vBECOME, vBE) as proposed by Folli & Harley (2005; 2007) and Harley (2008; 2009), however, may appear to cast doubt on the account presented here: one may assume that only vCAUSE, or at most vCAUSE and vBECOME (and not vDO and vBE), encode causation. I will turn back to this after elaborating on the notion of causation, what it denotes and how it is represented in v in section 4.
4 On the Nature of Causation in v
The literature on causation and the causal language is vast and burgeoning. Causation has been a central topic in the study of human learning, reasoning, perception, and language. Researchers have distinguished “singular” from “general” causation, “intentional” from “physical” causation, “direct” from “indirect” causation, “lexical” from “periphrastic” causation, and so forth. The linguistic study of causal connectives and auxiliaries has also revealed insights into human categorization of causality (see, among others, Wolff 2003; 2007; 2014; Sloman 2005; Sanders & Sweetser 2009; Swanson 2012; Copley & Wolff 2014; Sloman & Lagnado 2015, and references therein). Copley & Wolff (2014: 53) write that “a cognitive and linguistic conversation on causation is now possible, and that this conversation is likely to advance the long-term goal of integrating linguistic theory with the science of the mind.” This section straddles the frontier between cognitive psychology and linguistics focusing on causation as a conceptual relation instantiated linguistically, via little v.
4.1 What Is Causation?
There are two broad theoretical views of causation:
“Make a difference” theories of causation: The theories that are based on this view assume that “causation can be judged without appealing to the particular mechanism relating cause to effect” and claim that “A causes B if A’s occurrence makes a difference to B’s occurrence in one way or another” (Walsh & Sloman 2011: 23, 21). This view underlies counterfactual (e.g., Lewis 1973; 1986; 2000) as well as covariation (e.g., Cheng 1997) and manipulability (e.g., Pearl 2000; Woodward 2004) theories of causation (see Walsh & Sloman 2011: 23–24 for an overview of these theories, and Copley & Wolff 2014: 13–23, and Wolff 2014: §5.3 for problematic phenomena for dependency theories of causation).
“Generative” theories of causation: According to this view, “A causes B if some quantity or symbol gets passed in some way from A to B” (Walsh & Sloman 2011: 21). With reference to the actual causal process linking the cause to the effect (or the causer to the causee), the theories that are based on this view propose that “causal relations are not just stipulated but rather represent mechanisms in the world that take input (causes, enablers, disablers, preventers) and generate outputs (effects)” (Sloman & Lagnado 2015: 227).
Briefly, while “make a difference” theories, based on the idea that a cause is something that makes a difference to the effect, disregard how the effect is brought about, “generative” theories of causation (i.e., causal process theories) rely on the idea that causation involves a process of transmission or exchange of some conserved quantity, such as energy, momentum, force or information, along a causal pathway from the causer to the causee (see Shultz 1982; Salmon 1984; 1994; Dowe 2000).
Wolff (2007) notes that “make a difference” theories, dependency models in his terms, cannot distinguish CAUSE from ENABLE, overdeterminate the cause, sometimes identify non-causal factors as causal, and as such, are better viewed of as tests for causation, not accounts of its representation in the mind. “Generative” theories of causation, studied as physicalist models, on the other hand, reduce causal relationships to dynamics (i.e., the invisible properties of an event, namely the underlying energies and forces that give rise to the motions) rather than kinematics (i.e., the visible properties of an event: the shapes, sizes, positions, points of contact, etc.). The dynamics of an event enter directly into the conception of causation as they are central to causation in the actual world, and thus physicalist models put forth a better understanding of causal relations. Physicalist models, however, much like dependency models, do not distinguish causation from other kinds of relationships (Wolff 2007). To solve this problem, Wolff and his colleagues propose the force theory of causation (introduced as the dynamics model of causation), a physicalist model based on Talmy’s (1988) theory of force dynamics (Wolff & Zettergren 2002; Wolff 2003; 2007; 2014; Wolff & Song 2003; Wolff et al. 2005; Wolff et al. 2010).
According to the force theory, causation is associated with configurations of forces and an endstate vector.11 Causal interactions involve an affector and a patient, and are described at two levels of analysis. At the category level, cause-related concepts are specified in terms of three dimensions: the tendency of the patient for the endstate, the presence of concordance (or opposition) between the affector and the patient, and progress toward the endstate. At the computational level, these three dimensions are redescribed in terms of patterns of forces, or vectors. Four types of force vectors are relevant: A represents the direction of the force exerted on the patient by the affector; P represents the direction of the force generated by the patient itself or its resistance to change; O represents the direction of the summation of the remaining other forces acting on the patient; and R represents the direction of the resultant force acting on the patient. In addition to these four forces, vector E specifies the mental representation of the patient’s location with respect to an endstate. Figure 1 is a schematization.
The relationship between the category level and the computational level is as follows. The tendency of the patient for the endstate is the result of the collinearity of P and E, concordance of the affector and the patient is the result of the collinearity of A and P, and progress toward the endstate is the result of the collinearity of R and E (Wolff 2007).
What I wish to subjoin to Wolff and his colleagues’ force theory here is the idea of profiling from Langacker’s Cognitive Grammar. This will be used to differentiate the distinct flavors of v in §4.2. Langacker (1991; 2009) proposes that speakers, employing the conventional conceptualizations of language and cognitive processes (construal in his terms), can have different active characterizations of events including action chains where energy is transmitted from one entity to another. One type of the speaker’s construal is profiling, which allows her/him to choose to give special prominence to (or single out as a kind of focus of attention) certain segments (i.e., substructures, including entities and/or interactions) of an action chain. Profiling is well applicable to the causal apparatus in Figure 1; different patterns of forces or composites of diverse forces and the endstate vector can be profiled, that is, different substructures of the causal apparatus can be chosen by the speaker to receive enhanced prominence. For instance, the speaker can construe the causal scene, profiling P, but not A, and possibly R and O, as is the case for Tomatoes grew (15b) and The glass broke (16b). I will get back to the details of this issue in the next subsection.
How the force theory of causation decomposes CAUSE to a finer level of detail, as explained above, and how speakers construe a causal event or scene in alternative ways give us the opportunity to plausibly account for the causal nature of [V] and to differentiate the four flavors of v. In §4.2 I will deal with these issues.
4.2 A Force-Theoretic Approach to v
Not all theories of causation can address the causal distinction between n and v. In order to accommodate this difference, a theory of causation must be capable of elucidating the ungrammaticality of *John’s growth of tomatoes (15c) and *John’s break of the glass (16c) in contrast to the grammaticality of John grew tomatoes (15a) and John broke the glass (16a). The causer John and the effect grow/break are the only elements necessary for “make a difference” theories to be satisfied. Both of these elements are present in (15c) and (16c), as well as in (15a) and (16a). Thus, causation as defined by these theories cannot distinguish v from n.
If our definition of causation involves a causal mechanism, as “generative” theories do, however, the causal distinction between n and v will be expounded; v encodes the necessary supralexical causal pathway from cause to effect, hence the grammaticality of (15a) and (16a), while n is not able to provide any causal relation supralexically, hence the ungrammaticality of (15c) and (16c). Thus, so far, we can conclude that the categorial feature [V] on v establishes the necessary causal process/mechanism/pathway from cause to effect. However, two questions still remain to be discussed: first, what is the nature of the causal mechanism as encoded in [V]? And second, how can the different flavors of v be distinguished?
To answer these questions, I resort to the force theory of causation as alluded to above. There are two main reasons for pursuing this theory: first, the fine decomposition of the causal mechanism proposed in the force theory gives us the ability to discern how linguistic elements might correspond to units of cognition (here forces and the position vector, as illustrated in Figure 1). Second, the force theory of causation has been employed in the study of language and argued to be more suited to some linguistic data; Copley & Wolff (2014), for instance, argue that a force-theoretic framework offers us a better understanding of three linguistic phenomena: (i) defeasible causation in non-culminating accomplishments, (ii) agency through dispositions, and (iii) representations of causal chains. Copley & Harley (2015) also use the concept of force (i.e., input of energy) to account for the problem of non-culmination. They further apply the force theory to the composition of Vendlerian eventuality types (Vendler 1957) and discuss that stative predicates are predicates of situations, while dynamic predicates are predicates of forces. In the remainder of this section, I submit, along the similar lines as Copley & Harley, that the force theory of causation yields new insight into the causal nature of v and tells us how distinct flavors of v, namely vCAUSE, vDO, vBECOME and vBE, can be differentiated. The proposal here differs from Copley & Harley’s (2015) study in two respects: first, while Copley & Harley make use of the force theory to decompose basic Vendlerian eventuality types and replace event and world arguments with force and situation arguments, in this paper I use the force theory to differentiate v from n and attempt to apply this theory to distinct flavors of v by employing the idea of profiling. Second, Copley & Harley, employing the tools of formal semantics, come to a type-theoretic distinction between forces and situations at the syntax-semantics interface. Here, I do not use any linguistic tools to describe the nature of [V] on v or to distinguish different flavors of v; understanding dynamic and stative situations as introduced in the force theory of causation in terms of a causal apparatus (Figure 1) and the speaker’s profiling of different substructures of this apparatus are parts of the speaker’s extra-linguistic cognitive capacity that, I attempt to show, provides the bases for differentiating verbal and nominal constituents.
According to Folli & Harley (2005; 2007) and Harley (2009), all flavors of v serve the verbalizing function although they express distinct structural properties and different meanings to do with the initiation, or lack thereof, of the verbal event. The activity-denoting vDO selects for an agent and can take a nominal complement, while vCAUSE with a causer external argument requires a small clause complement. vBECOME and the stative vBE, on the other hand, select for a small clause complement and do not take any external argument. Harley (2009) also points out that vCAUSE and vBECOME, unlike vDO and vBE, involve some change of state.
In order to uphold the analysis in which v encodes a causal mechanism and simultaneously make this analysis responsive to different flavors of v, it suffices to highlight the prominence that the speaker chooses to give to specific vectors or particular patterns of forces (in the spatial schema provided by v) by employing distinct flavors of v. While the categorial feature [V] on v introduces the apparatus illustrated in Figure 1 above (i.e., a conventional conceptualization in language), different flavors of v reflect the speaker’s alternate ways of profiling the (causal) scene.
vCAUSE reflects the speaker’s accentuation of the process of the exchange of energy. At the computational level of analysis, ||A|| and ||P|| (double vertical lines denote magnitude) are greater than zero, but ||R|| and ||O|| can equal zero (see also Wolff 2007). Take, for instance, John grew tomatoes (15a) and John broke the glass (16a). In these sentences, vCAUSE provides the positive ||A|| which is not available in the roots √GROW and √BREAK. In contrast, the nominal forms *John’s growth of tomatoes (15c) and *John’s break of the glass (16c) lack v, a supralexical causal apparatus, and thus lack the positive ||A|| necessary for the semantic licensing of an external cause (i.e., an affector in the force theory). Full profiling of the causal apparatus is observed for vCAUSE; the patient’s initial and endstate positions, the affector’s force and its concordance or opposition with the patient’s force and other forces (if any) are all profiled imaging some progress toward the endstate via the transmission of energy from the affector to the patient (i.e., a full-fledged causal mechanism).
vBECOME reflects the speaker’s focus on the patient’s change toward the endstate. At the computational level of analysis, A is not defined, ||P|| is greater than zero, but ||R|| and ||O|| can equal zero. Consider The glass broke (16b). In this sentence, vBECOME provides the positive ||P|| which is not available in the root √BREAK (remember from (13) that √BREAK encodes only the result of the change of state). The nominal *the glass’s break (16d), in contrast, lacks the causal apparatus altogether and thus cannot involve the patient-related force (cf. Gärdenfors 2014).
So far, I have illustrated that a force-theoretic definition of causation as encoded in [V] on v sets forth the grammaticality pattern in (15) and (16). As noted above, for vCAUSE and vBECOME, it is possible that ||R|| and ||O|| do not equal zero. This is, in fact, the case of verbs of maintaining, such as keep and stay in (20a–b), which are dynamic but do not provoke a change of any kind.
- (20)
- a.
- The gloves keep my hands warm.
- b.
- My hands stay warm.
Following Talmy (1988), Copley & Harley (2015) propose that keep and stay (and other verbs of maintaining, like sit, stand, lie, sleep, etc.) involve a force that maintains a property’s truth from one situation to the successor situation, against a tendency otherwise. To put this in terms of the force theory, in keeping and staying, there are vCAUSE and vBECOME, respectively, such that ||R|| and ||O|| do not equal zero, but the summation of the forces’ magnitude is zero and the transition is trivial as the endstate is the same as the initial state of the patient (see also Copley & Harley 2015).
Now let us see how the force-theoretic approach to v accounts for vDO and vBE. vDO, as exemplified in (21), incises the initiation of a force on behalf of the affector (cf. Copley & Harley’s (2015) vOCCUR).
- (21)
- The winners dance.
Here, what is crucially profiled is vector A whose magnitude is greater than zero. Other segments of the causal apparatus provided by [V] on v are not involved in typical cases of activity situations. However, this does not mean that other vectors cannot be linguistically activated. See, for instance, (22) where a secondary predicate provokes the endstate vector E.
- (22)
- The winners dance, some even to their deaths.
The stative vBE, as in (23), makes a prominent reference to the position of the patient, that is to say, the position vector, as defined in the causal apparatus explained above, is profiled. (Note that the term “position” covers not only the patient’s spatial status but also its mental, social, etc. state of being, as well as its property attributions.)
- (23)
- The winners are excited.
There are two points to be clarified here: first, vBE is different from the stay-type vBECOME in that for vBE other vectors (i.e., force vectors) and their magnitudes are not relevant and thus are not profiled, while for stay the interaction of forces and their total zero magnitude are of paramount importance; for stay there are at least two profiled forces exerted in opposite directions by the patient on the one side and by some other source on the other. The summation of the magnitude of these forces equals zero resulting in the sameness of the patient’s initial and endstate positions. Second, defining vBE as referencing the stable position of the patient does not make it synonymous to n. [N] on n does not provide the apparatus illustrated in Figure 1 and thus is not capable of referring to the position of the patient in such an apparatus.
To sum up, [V] on v provides a configuration of forces and a position vector, that is, a causal mechanism/apparatus. Different flavors of v then reflect the speaker’s profiling of different substructures of this apparatus, that is, patterns of forces or the position vector. It should be noted that, although similar results can be found in Copley & Harley (2015), according to the present proposal, we can identify different flavors of v at an extra-linguistic level: different flavors of v encode and activate different patterns of forces regardless of the complements they will take at the linguistic level. Copley & Harley’s dual nature of forces as conceptual forces (perceived inputs of energy) and linguistic forces (functions from situations to situations), on the contrary, leads them to differentiate distinct flavors of v (all, except one (vBE), of which are predicates of forces) only when they are involved in different linguistic contexts, for instance, when they take different types of arguments: vBECOME is a predicate of forces that takes a predicate of situation, syntactically represented as a small clause, as its arguments, and vCAUSE (vAPPEAR in Copley & Harley) is another predicate of forces that takes an entity, the internal argument, as its argument, for instance.
The current analysis has another advantage over Copley & Harley’s, allowing us to explain the force-theoretic causal distinction between v and n. Copley & Harley’s (2015) force-based treatment of predicates is a great leap forward in our understanding of the mapping between linguistic semantics and the cognitive system; however, it is limited to the verbal domain. Two issues arise here: first, dealing with schema (i.e., non-sortal) nouns, following Copley & Harley, one finds identical conceptual “net” force and situation in (14a) and (14c), repeated here in (24). Similar event and argument structures are observed in these examples, thus, one expects similar force analyses for the vP in (24a) and the nP in (24b). This is not tenable; from the discussion in previous sections, we know that due to the causal nature of v (and the non-causal nature of n), (24a) and (24b) must have different force-based analyses.
- (24)
- a.
- The enemy destroyed the city.
- b.
- the enemy’s destruction of the city
Second, in Copley & Harley (2015: § 4.3) roots are treated as predicates of forces that add information about the nature of the forces introduced by v. Based on this account, √DESTROY in The enemy destroyed the city (14a) and √BREAK in The glass broke (16b) are both predicates of forces (type <f,t>) that modify vCAUSE and vBECOME, respectively. If roots are predicates of forces that modify other predicates of forces (i.e., any node of type <f,t>), then we should accept that roots modify some predicate of forces in nominals, namely little n. This is not true; as argued above, n does not provide any configuration of forces and hence cannot be considered to be a predicate of forces.
The analysis in this paper addresses these two issues. The idea is that not only v, but also roots encode some causal apparatus (unlike n). Different root classes, as in (13), provide different patterns of force and/or position vectors. Roots of “destroy” class show a full causal apparatus where ||A|| and ||P|| are greater than zero, but ||O|| can equal zero. Roots of “grow” class encode a configuration of forces where A is not defined, ||P|| is greater than zero, but ||O|| can equal zero. Remember from (13) that √GROW is internally caused. For roots of “break” class only the endstate vector E is relevant. This model serves to explain the external/internal causal pattern of the noun phrase as well as the semantic licensing of the arguments in the nominal domain.
Based on this proposal, the force analyses of the vP in (24a) and the nP in (24b) can be schematized as in (25a) and (25b), respectively. Other forces (vector O) is disregarded here for the sake of ease. As shown in (25a), the causal apparatus of √DESTROY is mapped onto that of vCAUSE in the verbal domain. Thus, the patient is identified as the city and the endstate is identified as the state of being destroyed. In the nominal domain, as shown in (25b), this mapping does not take place since n does not provide any causal apparatus. Thus, the causal reading of the noun phrase is merely rooted in the root’s force configuration. Note that the empty space for n in (25b) does not mean that n is meaningless, but that it lacks causal meaning.
- (25)
- a.
- b.
The mapping in the verbal domain (25a) is not trivial; below, it is shown that the proper mapping of these causal apparatuses is crucial to have well-formed verbal constructions.
An interesting consequence of the view proposed here is that matching the causal apparatus encoded in v with the causal apparatus encoded in the root turns out why not all flavors of v can select all types of roots (e.g., vBE does not select a root of “destroy” class): all flavors of v select roots with weaker or at most similar causal apparatus compared with theirs. vCAUSE can select roots of different classes as it has a full causal apparatus itself, whereas vBECOME selects roots of “grow” or “break” class, but not roots of “destroy” class since the causal apparatus in the latter involves vector A that is not defined in the causal apparatus of vBECOME. This is schematized in (26).
- (26)
On the other hand, when a flavor of v selects a root with a weaker causal apparatus (e.g., when vCAUSE selects √GROW, as shown in (27)), the causal capacity of the phrase is augmented (e.g., an external cause can be expressed when vCAUSE selects √GROW). This is not the case with nominals, as seen in (15a) and (15c) above. I leave details of this final issue for further research.12
- (27)
5 Conclusions
As causality is a research field with roots in philosophy, psychology, physics and application domains in medicine and knowledge engineering, this study attempted to offer some insight into the expression of causal relations in natural language and to set the stage for a new chapter in the field.
Concerning the objectives listed in the introduction, this article argued that we need to consider some temporal perspective for the interpretation of noun phrases and that Nominal Tense provides an opportunity to account for several issues, including adjectival syntax and the possible orderings of adjectives. Different semantic and syntactic behaviors of the clausal Tense and Nominal Tense remain to be investigated; Musan’s (1997; 1999) “life-time effect”, “presuppositional conditions” and “information-status” as observed in noun phrases would provide clear avenues for further research. The crucial conclusion in section 2 was that the categorial feature [V] on v is not responsible for an extending-into-time perspective at LF.
It was then suggested that causation is the necessary interpretive perspective encoded in v, but not in n nor in Voice. In order to be precise in our understanding of the causal nature of v, the force theory of causation was applied to define causation not as change-of-state/location, but in terms of an atemporal arrangement of four types of forces and a position vector. In the light of the force-theoretic approach to v, the finer distinction of the different flavors of v was delineated with reference to different patterns of forces in the causal apparatus provided by [V] on v. Follow-up questions are: How does this force-theoretic framework account for the expression of external and internal cause as provided by, for instance, roots of the “destroy” class? And if a similar force configuration can be detected in roots, how does it interact with the causal apparatus of v in the verbal domain? Could there be, apart from syntactic reasons (e.g., Case checking), a mechanism of “force identification” that blocks, for example, the co-occurrence of √DESTROY and vBE?
The temptation to cast doubt on the causal nature of v by viewing causal relations as temporal relations opens up another avenue for further research. This is not truly problematic, as, though related, causal structure and temporal structure are distinct. Wolff (2007) notes that “from a force dynamic perspective, temporal priority is not a requirement of causation; rather, it is an artifact of the way forces often converge” (see also Copley & Harley 2015 and reference therein). This, however, requires careful investigation.
Notes
- Note that Embick & Marantz (2008: 6) consider n and v “category-defining functional heads,” whereas Panagiotidis (2009; 2011; 2013; 2015) believes that categorizers (n and v) are the only possible “lexical” heads. While categorizers are “bundles of UG features bearing category,” functional heads are “bundles of UG features bearing uninterpretable categorial features” (Panagiotidis 2011: 366). [^]
- For information on how much meaning a root encodes independently of its syntactic categorization, see Alexiadou & Lohndal (2017), and for more recent elaboration on the nature of roots, see Panagiotidis (2020). [^]
- According to Ramchand (2008), the phases headed by categorizers are First Phases. [^]
- For the semantics of kinds, see Carlson (1977), Chierchia (1998), Müller-Reichau (2006), and references therein. [^]
- For details on individual-level and stage-level predicates see Kratzer (1989). [^]
- Compare the discussion of modal adjectives here with Wunderlich (1996: sec. 4–5) who proposes that the category of nouns lacks a possible world component and consequently is not subject to modality. Note, however, that Wunderlich does not claim that nouns lack a time component altogether, but that nouns express the more static or permanent properties, whereas verbs express the more dynamic or temporary properties. (I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing Wunderlich’s work to my attention and to Dieter Wunderlich for sending me a copy of his article.) [^]
- An anonymous reviewer, following Acquaviva (2009), pointed out that when combined with temporal expressions, nominals behave differently from verbal constituents. While I do agree with the reviewer in that temporal (and also aspectual) properties of nominals are different from those of verbals (which is an interesting topic for further research), I believe that, as indicated in examples (4) and (5), the idea that temporal constitution is inessential for nominal reference is untenable (contra Acquaviva 2009). [^]
- The reviewer also noted that “the existence of a temporal expression does not entail Tense.” Interestingly, this is not the case only with nominals; the same point has been extensively discussed with regard to the expression of time in the verbal domain in tenseless languages (see Bittner 2005; Smith 2005; Tonhauser 2011; among others). [^]
- Tonhauser (2006; 2007) argues that nominal temporal markers in Paraguayan Guaraní are aspect (and not tense) markers. It is beyond the scope of this paper to decide on aspect/tense analysis of nominal temporal markers in this language. However, it bears emphasizing that even with the aspect analysis, the temporal dimension of nominals can be held up since “[a]spect is also a grammatical system relating to time, … [where] the speaker may choose how to describe the internal temporal nature of a situation” (Saeed 2009: 119). [^]
- It is beyond the scope of this study to examine the interaction of the nominal Voice with the Possession Phrase or any other genitive case assigner (see Alexiadou 2001 and references therein). [^]
- A force can be presented as a vector since it has a magnitude, a direction and a point of origin (Gärdenfors 2014: 140). Vectors are indicated in boldface. [^]
- Related to this issue, in a paper, Goldschmidt & Zwarts (2016) discuss that force vectors are the necessary components of force verbs that bring about their aspectual and directional meanings and lead us to their lexical definitions (cf. my idea on force vectors as encoded in the roots). They also note that not all prepositions can be used with force verbs in German (e.g., schlagen ‘to hit’ requires auf ‘on’, whereas ziehen ‘to pull’ requires an ‘on’) and attribute this restriction to “the need to match the direction of the force vectors of the path assigned to the event with those of the set of paths denoted by the PP to arrive at a non-empty set-intersection” (Goldschmidt & Zwarts 2016: 447) (cf. my idea on the selectional restrictions of different flavors of v). [^]
Acknowledgements
The author is extremely grateful to Isabel Cooke McKay for kindly editing a previous version of this article. Parts of this research were presented at Little v Workshop in Leiden, 2013, and in SinFonIJA 8, Ljubljana, 2015; the author wishes to express her gratitude to the organizers and the audience of those conferences for their feedback. Also, the author would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for their insightful comments. Finally, special thanks to Johan Rooryck, the editor-in-chief of Glossa, for taking his time carefully considering my replies to the extensive commentary of anonymous reviewers.
Competing interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
References
Acquaviva, Paolo. 2008. Roots and lexicality in Distributed Morphology. Ms., University College Dublin/Universität Konstanz.
Acquaviva, Paolo. 2009. The roots of nominality, the nominality of roots. Ms., University College Dublin.
Alexiadou, Artemis. 2001. Functional structure in nominals: Nominalization and ergativity. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.42
Alexiadou, Artemis. 2005. Tense (and mood) in the nominal domain(?). Paper presented at The Workshop on the Linguistic Representation of Tense and Mood, Stuttgart.
Alexiadou, Artemis. 2019. Passives, unaccusativity, and nominalization. In Malicka-Kleparska, Anna & Bloch-Trojnar, Maria (eds.), Valency in verbs and verb related structures. Sounds – Meaning – Communication 9, 33–54. Berlin: Peter Lang.
Alexiadou, Artemis & Anagnostopoulou, Elena & Schäfer, Florian. 2006. The properties of anticausatives crosslinguistically. In Frascarelli, Mara (ed.), Phases and Interpretation, 187–211. Berlin: Mouton. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110197723.4.187
Alexiadou, Artemis & Anagnostopoulou, Elena & Schäfer, Florian. 2007. PP licensing in nominalizations. Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 38. MA: GLSA.
Alexiadou, Artemis & Anagnostopoulou, Elena & Schäfer, Florian. 2015. External arguments in transitivity alternations: A layering approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2016.0035
Alexiadou, Artemis & Doron, Edit. 2012. The syntactic construction of two non-active voices: Passive and middle. Journal of Linguistics 48. 1–34. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226711000338
Alexiadou, Artemis & Lohndal, Terje. 2017. On the division of labor between roots and functional structure. In D’Alessandro, Roberta & Franco, Irene & Gallego, Ángel J. (eds.), The verbal domain, 85–104. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198767886.003.0004
Anagnostopoulou, Elena & Samioti, Yota. 2013. Allosemy, idioms and their domains: Evidence from adjectival participles. In Folli, Raffaella & Sevdali, Christina & Truswell, Robert (eds.), On syntax and its limits, 218–250. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199683239.003.0012
Anderson, Mona. 1983. Prenominal genitive NP. The Linguistic Review 3. 1–24. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/tlir.1983.3.1.1
Baker, Mark. 2003. Lexical categories: Verbs, nouns and adjectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511615047
Bittner, Maria. 2005. Future discourse in a tenseless language. Journal of Semantics 22. 339–387. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffh029
Borer, Hagit. 2003. Exo-skeletal vs. endo-skeletal explanations: Syntactic projections and the lexicon. In Moore, John & Polinsky, Maria (eds.), The nature of explanation in linguistic theory, 31–67. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bruening, Benjamin. 2013. By-phrases in passives and nominals. Syntax 16. 1–41. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9612.2012.00171.x
Burton, Strang C. 1997. Past tense on nouns as death, destruction, and loss. In Kusomoto, Kiyomi (ed.), Proceedings of NELS 27, 65–77. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts.
Carlson, Gregory. 1977. Reference to kinds in English. University of Massachusetts at Amherst doctoral dissertation.
Cheng, Patricia W. 1997. From covariation to causation: A causal power theory. Psychological Review 104. 367–405. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.104.2.367
Chierchia, Gennaro. 1998. Reference to kinds across languages. Natural Language Semantics 6. 339–405. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008324218506
Chomsky, Noam. 1970. Remarks on Nominalization. In Jacobs, Roderick & Rosenbaum, Peter (eds.), Readings in English transformational grammar, 184–221. Waltham, Mass.: Ginn and Company.
Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262527347.001.0001
Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Kenstowicz, Michael (ed.), Ken Hale: A life in linguistics, 1–52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/4056.003.0004
Chomsky, Noam. 2008. On phases. In Freiden, Robert & Otero, Carlos & Zubizarreta, Maria L. (eds.), Foundational issues in linguistic theory. Essays in honor of Jean-Roger Vergnaud, 291–321. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262062787.003.0007
Chomsky, Noam. 2013. Problems of projection. Lingua 130. 33–49. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2012.12.003
Chomsky, Noam. 2020. Remarks on Nominalization: Background and motivation. In Alexiadou, Artemis & Borer, Hagit (eds.), Nominalization: 50 years on from Chomsky’s Remarks, 25–28. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198865544.003.0002
Cinque, Guglielmo. 1980. On extraction from NP in Italian. Journal of Italian Linguistics 5. 47–99.
Cinque, Guglielmo. 1994. Evidence for partial N-movement in the Romance DP. In Cinque, Guglielmo & Koster, Jan & Pollock, Jean-Yves & Rizzi, luigi & Zanuttini, Raffaella (eds.), Paths towards Universal Grammar: Studies in honor of Richard S. Kayne, 85–110. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2010. The syntax of adjectives: A comparative study. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262014168.001.0001
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2013. Cognition, universal grammar, and typological generalizations. Lingua 130. 50–65. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2012.10.007
Collins, Chris. 2005. A smuggling approach to the passive in English. Syntax 8(2). 81–120. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9612.2005.00076.x
Copley, Bridget & Harley, Heidi. 2015. A force-theoretic framework for event structure. Linguistics and Philosophy 38(2). 103–158. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-015-9168-x
Copley, Bridget & Wolff, Phillip. 2014. Theories of causation should inform linguistic theory and vice versa. In Copley, Bridget & Martin, Fabienne (eds.), Causation in grammatical structures, 11–53. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199672073.003.0002
Dowe, Phil. 2000. Physical causation. New York: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511570650
Embick, David. 2000. Features, syntax, and categories in the Latin perfect. Linguistic Inquiry 31. 185–230. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/002438900554343
Embick, David. 2010. Localism and globalism in morphology and phonology. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262014229.001.0001
Embick, David & Marantz, Alec. 2008. Architecture and blocking. Linguistic Inquiry 39. 1–53. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2008.39.1.1
Enç, Mürvet. 1987. Anchoring conditions for tense. Linguistic Inquiry 18. 633–657.
Folli, Raffaella & Harley, Heidi. 2005. Flavors of v: Consuming results in Italian and English. In Kempchinsky, Paula & Slabakova, Roumyana (eds.), Aspectual inquiries, 95–120. Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/1-4020-3033-9_5
Folli, Raffaella & Harley, Heidi. 2007. Causation, obligation and argument structure: On the nature of little v. Linguistic Inquiry 38(2). 197–238. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2007.38.2.197
Gärdenfors, Peter. 2014. The geometry of meaning: Semantics based on conceptual spaces. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9629.001.0001
Giorgi, Alessandra & Longobardi, Giuseppe. 1991. The syntax of noun phrases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/sl.16.1.11nap
Goldschmidt, Anja & Zwarts, Joost. 2016. Hitting the nail on the head: Force vectors in verb semantics. Proceedings of SALT 26. 433–450. DOI: http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v26i0.3780
Grimshaw, Jane. 1990. Argument structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Halle, Morris & Marantz, Alec. 1993. Distributed Morphology and the pieces of inflection. In Hale, Kenneth & Keyser, Samuel J. (eds.), The view from building 20, 111–176. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Harley, Heidi. 1995. Subjects, events and licensing. MIT doctoral dissertation.
Harley, Heidi. 2007. The bipartite structure of verbs cross-linguistically, or why Mary can’t exhibit John her paintings. Talk presented at the ABRALIN Congres, UFMG, Belo Horizonte.
Harley, Heidi. 2008. On the causative construction. In Miyagawa, Shigeru & Saito, Mamoru (eds.), Handbook of Japanese linguistics, 20–53, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harley, Heidi. 2009. The morphology of nominalizations and the syntax of vP. In Giannakidou, Anastasia & Rathert, Monika (eds.), Quantification, definiteness, and nominalization, 320–342. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harley, Heidi. 2013a. External arguments and the Mirror Principle: On the distinctness of Voice and v. Lingua 125. 34–57. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2012.09.010
Harley, Heidi. 2013b. The ‘bundling’ hypothesis and the disparate functions of little v. Keynote talk at Little v Workshop, Leiden.
Harley, Heidi & Noyer, Rolf. 1999. State-of-the-article: Distributed Morphology. GLOT International 4 (4). 3–9.
Harley, Heidi & Noyer, Rolf. 2000. Formal versus encyclopedic properties of vocabulary: Evidence from nominalizations. In Peeters, Bert (ed.), The lexicon-encyclopedia interface, 349–374. Amsterdam: Elsevier. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1163/9780585474465_014
Higginbotham, James. 1983. Logical form, binding and nominals. Linguistic Inquiry 14. 395–420.
Ilkhanipour, Negin. 2015. Modal adjectives in Persian. Tehran: Nashr-e-Markaz.
Ilkhanipour, Negin. 2016. Tense and modality in the nominal domain. Linguistica 56(1). 143–160. DOI: http://doi.org/10.4312/linguistica.56.1.143-160
Ilkhanipour, Negin & Sugawara, Ayaka. 2016. On the semantics and syntax of Persian ‘become’. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 22(1). 148–157. http://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol22/iss1/17
Kratzer, Angelika. 1989. Stage-level and individual-level predicates. In Bach, Emon & Kratzer, Angelika & Partee, Barbara (eds.), Papers on quantification, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Rooryck, Johan & Zaring, Laurie (eds.), Phrase structure and the lexicon, 109–137. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8617-7_5
Langacker, Ronald W. 1991. Concept, image, and symbol: The cognitive basis of grammar. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Langacker, Ronald W. 2009. Investigations in cognitive grammar. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110214369
Larson, Richard. 1988. On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19. 335–391.
Lecarme, Jacqueline. 1996. Tense in the nominal system: The Somali DP. In Lecarme, Jacqueline & Lowenstamm, Jean & Shlonsky, Ur (eds.), Studies in Afroasiatic grammar, 159–178. The Hague: Holland Academic Graphics.
Lecarme, Jacqueline. 2004. Tense in nominals. In Guéron, Jacqueline & Lecarme, Jacqueline (eds.), The syntax of time, 440–475. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/6598.003.0019
Lecarme, Jacqueline. 2008. Tense and Modality in Nominals. In Guéron, Jacqueline & Lecarme, Jacqueline (eds.), Time and modality, 195–225. Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-8354-9_9
Lewis, David. 1973. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lewis, David. 1986. Philosophical papers: Volume II. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/0195036468.001.0001
Lewis, David. 2000. Causation as influence. In Collins, John & Hall, Ned & Paul, L.A. (eds.), Causation and counterfactuals, 75–106. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/1752.003.0004
Longobardi, Giuseppe. 2001. The structure of DPs: Some principles, parameters and problems. In Baltin, Mark & Colins, Chris (eds.), The handbook of syntactic theory, 562–603. Oxford: Blackwell. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1002/9780470756416.ch18
Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: Don’t try morphological analysis in the privacy of your own lexicon. University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 4. 201–225.
Marantz, Alec. 2000. Words. Ms., MIT.
Marantz, Alec. 2006. Phases and Words. Ms., MIT.
Merchant, Jason. 2013. Voice and ellipsis. Linguistic Inquiry 44(1). 77–108. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00120
Müller-Reichau, Olav. 2006. Sorting the world: On the relevance of the kind-level/object-level distinction to referential semantics. Universität Leipzig doctoral dissertation.
Musan, Renate. 1995. On the temporal interpretation of noun phrases. MIT doctoral dissertation.
Musan, Renate. 1997. Tense, predicates, and lifetime effects. Natural Language Semantics 5. 271–301. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008281017969
Musan, Renate. 1999. Temporal interpretation and information-status of noun phrases. Linguistics and Philosophy 22. 621–661. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1005435423259
Nordlinger, Rachel & Sadler, Louisa. 2003. The syntax and semantics of tensed nominals. In Butt, Miriam & King, Tracy H. (eds.), Proceedings of LFG03 Conference, 328–346. State University of NewYork at Albany.
Nordlinger, Rachel & Sadler, Louisa. 2004a. Nominal tense in cross-linguistic perspective. Language 80(4). 776–806. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2004.0219
Nordlinger, Rachel & Sadler, Louisa. 2004b. Tense beyond the verb: Encoding clausal tense/aspect/mood on nominal dependents. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 22. 597–641. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1023/B:NALA.0000027720.41506.fe
Panagiotidis, Phoevos. 2009. The nature of nP (and vP): From roots to nouns (and verbs). Talk presented at the Workshop on Bare Nouns, Université Paris Diderot (Paris VII).
Panagiotidis, Phoevos. 2011. Categorial features and categorizers. The Linguistic Review 28(3). 365–386. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/tlir.2011.010
Panagiotidis, Phoevos. 2013. Roots and categories. Lectures at Stony Brook University.
Panagiotidis, Phoevos. 2015. Categorial features: A generative theory of word class categories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139811927
Panagiotidis, Phoevos. 2020. On the nature of roots: Content, form, identification. Evolutionary Linguistic Theory 2(1). 56–83. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/elt.00015.pan
Pearl, Judea. 2000. Causality: Models, reasoning and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Picallo, M. Carme. 1991. Nominals and nominalizations in Catalan. Probus 3. 279–316. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/prbs.1991.3.3.279
Prasada, Sandeep. 2008. Aspects of a fully psychological theory of sortal representation. Ms., CUNY.
Pylkkänen, Liina. 2002. Introducing arguments. MIT doctoral dissertation.
Ramchand, Gillian. 2008. Verb meaning and the lexicon: A first phase syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511486319
Ramchand, Gillian. 2013. The event domain. Keynote talk at Little v Workshop, Leiden.
Sadler, Louisa & Nordlinger, Rachel. 2001. Nominal tense with nominal scope: A preliminary sketch. In Butt, Miriam & King, Tracy H. (eds.), Proceedings of LFG01 Conference. University of Hongkong, Hongkong.
Saeed, John I. 2009. Semantics (3rd ed.). Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.53079-7
Salmon, Wesley. 1984. Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9780691221489
Salmon, Wesley. 1994. Causality without counterfactuals. Philosophy of Science 61. 297–312. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1086/289801
Sanders, Ted & Sweetser, Eve. 2009. Introduction: Causality in language and cognition – what causal connectives and causal verbs reveal about the way we think. In Sanders, Ted & Sweetser, Eve (eds.), Causal categories in discourse and cognition, 1–18. Walter de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110224429.1
Schoorlemmer, Maaike. 2001. Dutch nominalized infinitives as non-identical twins. UiL OTS Working Paper uil-ots-01005-CL/TL. Utrecht University.
Schoorlemmer, Maaike. 2002. Adjectives and adverbs in Dutch nominalized infinitives. Paper presented at the TIN Dag Workshop, Utrecht.
Scott, Gary-John. 2002. Stacked adjectival modification and the structure of nominal phrases. In Cinque, Guglielmo (ed.), Functional structure in DP and IP: The cartography of syntactic structures, vol. 1, 91–120. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780195148794.003.0004
Shultz, T.R. 1982. Rules of causal attribution. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 47. 1–51. DOI: http://doi.org/10.2307/1165893
Sichel, Ivy. 2007. Agent exclusivity in nominalization. Paper presented at the Workshop on Bare nouns and nominalizations, Stuttgart.
Siloni, Tal. 1997. Noun phrases and nominalizations: The syntax of DPs. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8863-8
Simons, Peter. 1987. Parts: A study in ontology. Oxford: Clarendon Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.2307/2215517
Sloman, Steven. 2005. Causal models: How people think about the world and its alternatives. New York: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195183115.001.0001
Sloman, Steven A. & Lagnado, David. 2015. Causality in thought. Annual Review of Psychology 66. 223–247. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-psych-010814-015135
Smith, Carlota S. 2005. Time with and without tense. The International Round Table on Tense and Modality, Paris.
Swanson, Eric. 2012. The language of causation. In Russell, Gillian & Fara, Delia Graff (eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of language, 716–728. New York and London: Routledge.
Talmy, Leonard. 1988. Force dynamics in language and cognition. Cognitive Science 12. 49–100. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog1201_2
Tonhauser, Judith. 2006. The temporal semantics of noun phrases: Evidence from Guaraní. Stanford University doctoral dissertation.
Tonhauser, Judith. 2007. What is nominal tense? A case study of Paraguayan Guaraní. In Becker, Michael & McKenzie, Andrew. Proceedings of Semantics of Under-represented Languages (SULA) III. Amherst, MA: GLSA Publications.
Tonhauser, Judith. 2011. Temporal reference in Paraguayan Guaraní, a tenseless language. Linguistics and Philosophy 34. 257–303. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-011-9097-2
Travis, Lisa. 2013. Little v as domain/phase delimiter. Keynote talk at Little v Workshop, Leiden.
Uriagereka, Juan. 1999. Warps: Some thoughts on categorization. Theoretical Linguistics 25. 31–73. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/thli.1999.25.1.31
Vendler, Zeno. 1957. Verbs and times. The Philosophical Review 66. 143–160. DOI: http://doi.org/10.2307/2182371
Walsh, Clare R. & Sloman, Steven A. 2011. The meaning of cause and prevent: The role of causal mechanism. Mind & Language 26(1). 21–52. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.2010.01409.x
Wechsler, Stephen. 2005. What is right and wrong about little v. In Vulchanova, Mila & Åfarli, Tor A. (eds.), Grammar and beyond – Essays in honour of Lars Hellan, 179–195. Oslo: Novus Press.
Wolff, Phillip. 2003. Direct causation in the linguistic coding and individuation of causal events. Cognition 88. 1–48. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(03)00004-0
Wolff, Phillip. 2007. Representing causation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 136(1). 82–111. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1037/0096-3445.136.1.82
Wolff, Phillip. 2014. Causal pluralism and force dynamics. In Copley, Bridget & Martin, Fabienne (eds.), Causation in grammatical structures, 100–119. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199672073.003.0005
Wolff, Phillip & Barbey, Aron K. & Hausknecht, Matthew. 2010. For want of a nail: How absences cause events. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 139(2). 191–221. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1037/a0018129
Wolff, Phillip & Klettke, Bianca & Ventura, Tatyana & Song, Grace. 2005. Categories of causation across cultures. In Ahn, Woo-kyoung & Goldstone, Robert & Love, Bradley & Markman, Arthur & Wolff, Phillip (eds.), Categorization inside and outside of the lab: Festschrift in honor of Douglas L. Medin, 29–48. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Wolff, Phillip & Song, Grace. 2003. Models of causation and the semantics of causal verbs. Cognitive Psychology 47. 276–332. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0285(03)00036-7
Wolff, Phillip & Zettergren, Matthew. 2002. A vector model of causal meaning. In Proceedings of the twenty-fourth annual conference of the Cognitive Science Society, 944–949. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. https://escholarship.org/uc/item/1qm8q0rt. DOI: http://doi.org/10.4324/9781315782379-197
Woodward, James. 2004. Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/0195155270.001.0001
Wunderlich, Dieter. 1996. Lexical categories. Theoretical Linguistics 22(1/2). 1–48. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/thli.1996.22.1-2.1
Yatsushiro, Kazuko & Alexiadou, Artemis. 2020. The acquisition of argument-role in nominalizations. BUCLD 44: Proceedings of the 44th annual Boston University Conference on language development, 749–758.