1 Introduction
Most studies of partitives have focused on English or other European languages in which partitives are marked by a preposition equivalent to of in English. As exemplified in (1) and (2), the preposition of occurs between a definite DP and a quantifier or a quantifier plus measure noun in English partitive.
- (1)
- He ate two of my apples.
- (2)
- He drank two bottles of the wine.
The preposition of is claimed to play an important role in the partitive construction. It is assumed not only to express a partitive or PART-OF relation but also to be responsible for the Partitive Constraint that requires the complement of the preposition of to be definite (Barwise & Cooper 1981; Ladusaw 1982; Hoeksema 1984; 1996; Barker 1998; Ionin et al. 2006; inter alia). According to this approach, the partitive of distinguishes “real” partitives from like two bottles of wine and like two apples.
This paper will examine Korean quantifier constructions in order to investigate the typology of partitives. Korean is a classifier language in which a noun cannot directly combine with a numeral without a classifier, i.e., an item specifying a unit of measurement.1 Both count and mass nouns occur with a numeral quantifier, which is composed of a numeral and a classifier, as in (3) and (4). No structural difference exists between pseudo-partitives and quantitatives in Korean.
- (3)
- twu
- two
- kay-uy
- CL-GEN
- sakwa
- apple
- ‘two apples’
- (4)
- twu
- two
- pyeng-uy
- CL-GEN
- wain
- wine
- ‘two bottles of wine’
Partitive constructions have rarely been discussed in Korean linguistics, possibly due to the belief that a partitive meaning is expressed by a “separation construction” (Koptjevskaja-Tamm 2001) or a “semi-partitive” (Hoeksema 1984), which in English occurs with among and out of. In Korean separation constructions, a nominal referring to a ‘whole’ occurs as an adjunct, followed by cwung ‘among/between’ and the source-oriented locative particle eyse ‘from,’ as in (5).
- (5)
- haksayng
- student
- ney
- four
- myeng
- CL
- cwung-eyse
- among-from
- twu
- two
- myeng-i
- CL-NOM
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘Among the four students, two got hurt.’
Separation constructions are distinguishable from typical partitives in which a quantifier is used to pick out a part of a set or substance. Korean separation constructions do not require the presence of a quantifier to denote a part of a set. As in (6), a common or proper noun can occur with the partitive adjunct introduced by cwung-eyse ‘from among.’ Note that quantifier twu myeng ‘two CL’ in (5) can also occur with a noun, as in (7).
- (6)
- a.
- ku
- that
- haksayng-tul
- student-PL
- cwung-eyse
- among-from
- [hankuk
- [Korea
- haksayng]-i
- student]-NOM
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘Among those students, a Korean student got hurt.’
- b.
- ku
- that
- haksayng-tul
- student-PL
- cwung-eyse
- among-from
- [Cheli-wa
- [Cheli-CONJ
- Juni]-ka
- Juni]-NOM
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘Among those students, Cheli and Juni got hurt.’
- (7)
- ku
- that
- haksayng-tul
- student-PL
- cwung-eyse
- among-from
- [nam-haksayng
- [male-student
- twu
- two
- myeng]-i
- CL]-NOM
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘Among those students, two male students got hurt.’
Moreover, the Korean separation construction cannot be used to describe a part of the substance denoted by a mass noun, as in (8). The expression cwung-eyse ‘among-from’ is only compatible with a nominal denoting a set of individuated or distinct elements.2
- (8)
- ??Cheli-nun
- Cheli-TOP
- i
- this
- wain
- wine
- cwung-eyse
- among-from
- twu
- two
- can-ul
- CL-ACC
- massy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli drank two glasses of this wine.’
Now the question arises whether Korean has a partitive construction. Several scholars have claimed that Korean floating quantifier construction may be such a construction (Christina Kim 2005; Keun Shin 2007; Jong-Bok Kim 2013). Suppose there were a dozen apples on the table. Cheli ate two of them. In this situation, a Korean speaker could utter (9).
- (9)
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [thakca wi-ey
- [table above-LOC
- iss-te-n
- exit-RT-REL
- sakwa]-lul
- apple]-ACC
- (cayppali)
- (quickly)
- twu
- two
- kay
- CL
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli quickly ate two of the apples on the table.’
Sentence (9) is a floating quantifier construction in which the quantifier does not form a constituent with its preceding host nominal, as seen by the fact that the adverbial ‘quickly’ can occur between the numeral quantifier and the host.
Unlike separation constructions, proper names or common nouns cannot be used instead of floating quantifiers to signal a partitive interpretation, as in (10).3 Floating quantifiers can convey a partitive meaning with a mass noun, as in (11).4
- (10)
- a.
- *ku
- that
- haksayng-tul-i
- student-PL-NOM
- [Cheli-wa
- [Cheli-CONJ
- Juni]
- Juni]
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘Among those students, Cheli and Juni got hurt.’
- b.
- *ku
- that
- haksayng-tul-i
- student-PL-NOM
- [nam-haksayng
- [male-student
- (twu
- (two
- myeng)]
- CL)]
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘Among those students, (two) male students got hurt.’
- c.
- ku
- that
- haksayng-tul-i
- student-PL-NOM
- twu
- two
- myeng
- CL
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘Four of those students got hurt.’
- (11)
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- i
- this
- wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- [twu
- [two
- can]
- CL]
- massy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli drank two glasses of this wine.’
Korean floating quantifier constructions therefore correspond more closely to partitives in English and other European languages, in which a quantifier is used without a noun to refer to a part of a set of substance. Unlike English partitives, however, Korean floating quantifier constructions do not contain any overt marker expressing a PART-OF relation or corresponding to the preposition of. Furthermore, Korean floating quantifier constructions do not obey the Partitive Constraint. They can be interpreted in the manner of either English partitives or pseudo-partitives, as shown in (12).
- (12)
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- twu
- two
- can
- CL
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli drank two glasses of wine/two glasses of the wine.’
Close examination reveals that the distinction between partitives and non-partitives is signaled by the relative order between a quantifier and its associated nominal in Korean. As exemplified in (13), a numeral quantifier can either precede or follow its associated nominal. (13a) and (13b) will be referred to henceforth as prenominal quantifier construction and postnominal quantifier construction, respectively. Notice that floating quantifiers also follow their associated nominals.5 Unlike prenominal quantifier constructions, postnominal and floating quantifier constructions are partitive constructions (Keun Shin 2007).
- (13)
- a.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [twu
- [two
- kay-uy
- CL-GEN
- sakwa]-lul
- apple]-ACC
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli ate two apples.’
- b.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [sakwa
- [apple
- twu
- two
- kay]-lul
- CL]-ACC
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
Focusing on numeral quantifiers, this paper attempts to examine Korean partitive constructions and shed some light on the cross-linguistic variations in the partitive structure.
The organization of the paper is as follows: Section 2 will show that postnominal and floating quantifier constructions are partitive constructions and discuss their important characteristics, which cannot be accounted for under the assumption that a postnominal quantifier undergoes some syntactic movement in the floating quantifier construction. Section 3 will propose formal analyses for postnominal and floating quantifier construction. Based on my previous work (Keun Shin 2007; 2009), a postnominal quantifier will be analyzed as denoting a PART-OF relation and take either a definite DP or a kind-denoting DP as its argument. I will argue that a quantifier denoting a PART-OF relation is semantically construed with the DP argument of a verb via its composition with a verbal predicate in the floating quantifier construction. Section 4 will summarize the conclusions.
2 Characteristics of Korean partitive constructions
It is often claimed in the syntactic literature that postnominal and/or floating quantifier constructions are derived from prenominal quantifier constructions by syntactic movement (Wan Chae 1983; Young-Hee Kim 1983; Myung-Kwan Park & Keun-Won Sohn 1993; Kiyong Choi 2001; See Watanabe 2006 for Japanese, inter alia).6 In this section, I will show that postnominal and floating quantifier constructions are partitives whose properties cannot be accounted for under such a derivational analysis. I will also discuss the shortcomings of a uniform approach to postnominal and floating quantifier constructions.
2.1 Korean partitives: postnominal and floating quantifier constructions
In Korean, a head-final language, nouns follow their modifiers such as adjectives and genitives, and the word order among modifiers is flexible, as shown in (14). If modifiers are nouns, the genitive case -uy is often attached to them.
- (14)
- a.
- Emma-ka
- mom-NOM
- [[ai-uy]
- [[kid-GEN]
- [chakawun]
- [cold]
- son]-ul
- hand]-ACC
- cap-ass-ta.
- grab-PST-DEC
- ‘The mom grabbed the kid’s cold hand’
- b.
- Emma-ka
- mom-NOM
- [[chakawun]
- [[cold]
- [ai-uy]
- [kid-GEN]
- son]-ul
- hand]-ACC
- cap-ass-ta.
- grab-PST-DEC
Prenominal quantifiers pattern with other NP modifiers (Keun Shin 2007; 2009). Prenominal quantifiers also precede nouns, and they are marked with the genitive case. They can occur before or after adjectives, as in (15). Thus, they can be analyzed as NP modifiers, as in (16) (Keun Shin 2007; 2008; 2009).
- (15)
- a.
- ?Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [[chakawun]
- [[cold]
- [twu
- [two
- pyeng-uy]
- CL-GEN]
- wain]-ul
- wine ]-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli drank two bottles of cold wine.’
- b.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [[twu
- [[two
- pyeng-uy]
- CL-GEN]
- [chakawun]
- [cold]
- wain]-ul
- wine]-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- (16)
- [NP
- twu
- two
- -uy
- CL-GEN
- [NP]]
However, postnominal and floating quantifiers are different from prenominal quantifiers. They follow rather than precede their associated nominals, and genitive case is not attached to them. Of course, this word order difference and lack of genitive marking can be explained under syntactic derivational analyses assuming that prenominal and postnominal/floating quantifier constructions have the same underlying structures (Wan Chae 1983; Young-Hee Kim 1983; Myung-Kwan Park & Keun-Won Sohn 1993; Kiyong Choi 2001; See Watanabe 2006 for Japanese, inter alia). However, under such derivational accounts, we cannot expect that prenominal and postnominal/floating quantifier constructions differ in terms of what counts as the head of the structure, but as we see below, they do. In prenominal quantifier structures, the associated nominal is the head, while in postnominal/floating quantifier structures, the numeral quantifier serves as the head. This difference can be demonstrated by selectional restrictions differences. For example, (17a) is ungrammatical because [twu pyeng-uy wain] always refers to wine and the verb ‘break’ cannot take it as its argument. In the prenominal quantifier construction, the numeral quantifier is always interpreted as modifying the associated mass nominal. In the corresponding postnominal and floating quantifier constructions in (17b) and (17c), however, the verb ‘break’ imposes its selectional restrictions on the classifier of the numeral quantifier, which can be used as a common noun meaning ‘bottle.’ The object in (17b) and (17c) can be interpreted as ‘two bottles filled with wine.’
- (17)
- a.
- ??Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [twu pyeng-uy
- [two CL-GEN
- wain]-ul
- wine]-ACC
- kkayttuly-ess-ta.
- break-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli broke two bottles of wine.’
- b.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [wain
- [wine
- twu
- two
- pyeng]-ul
- CL]-ACC
- kkayttuly-ess-ta.
- break-PST-DEC
- c.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [wain]-ul
- [wine]-ACC
- [twu
- [two
- pyeng]
- CL]
- kkayttuly-ess-ta.
- break-PST-DEC
Postnominal/floating quantifier constructions also differ from prenominal quantifier constructions in terms of the monotonicity constraint (Nakanishi 2004; 2007; Keun Shin 2007; 2009). The monotonicity constraint was originally proposed to explain why different types of measure phrases occur in English pseudo-partitives and attributive measure constructions, as illustrated in (18) and (19) respectively (Krifka 1989; 1998; Schwarzschild 2002; 2006).
- (18)
- a.
- three liters of (the) water, three pounds of (the) grapes, three bottles of (the) water
- b.
- *fifty degrees-Celsius of (the) water, *one liter of (the) bottle, *six-carats of (the) gold
- (19)
- a.
- fifty degree-Celsius water, one-liter bottle, six-carat gold
- b.
- *three-liter water, *three-pound grape, *three-bottle water
A measure property is said to be monotonic if it tracks a part-whole relation in the domain given by the associated nominal (Schwarzschild 2002; 2006). Partitives and pseudo-partitives are formed with such a monotonic measure function. For example, the volume measurement in three liters of (the) water is monotonic: if the quantity of water is three liters, every proper subpart of the water has a volume less than three liters. On the other hand, the temperature measurement used in the attributive measure construction is a non-monotonic measure function. If the temperature of water is fifty degree-Celsius, it is not necessary that proper parts of it will have lower or higher temperatures than fifty degree-Celsius.
Unlike prenominal quantifier constructions, Korean postnominal and floating quantifier constructions are subject to the monotonicity constraint. For example, il lithe ‘one liter’ can occur in all three types of quantifier constructions, as in (20), whereas osip tossi ‘fifty degree-Celsius’ can occur only in prenominal quantifier constructions, as in (21). In other words, postnominal and floating quantifier constructions are monotonic constructions in which numeral quantifiers are required to track part-whole relations.
- (20)
- a.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [il
- [one
- lithe-uy
- liter-GEN
- mwul]-ul
- water]-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli drank one liter of water.’
- b.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [mwul
- [water
- il
- one
- lithe]-lul
- liter]-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- c.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [mwul]-ul
- [water]-ACC
- [il
- [one
- lithe]
- liter]
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- (21)
- a.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [osip
- [fifty
- tossi-uy
- degree-GEN
- mwul]-ul
- water]-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli drank fifty-degree water.’
- b.
- *Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [mwul
- [water
- osip
- fifty
- tossi]-lul
- degree]-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- c.
- *Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [mwul]-ul
- [water]-ACC
- [osip tossi]
- [fifty degree]
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
To sum up, postnominal and floating quantifier constructions structurally distinguish them from prenominal quantifier constructions. Unlike prenominal quantifiers, postnominal and floating quantifiers do not behave as NP modifiers. They can be interpreted as nominal heads on which a verb can exercise its selectional restrictions. Furthermore, both postnominal and floating quantifier constructions are partitive constructions that abide by the monotonicity constraint, distinct from prenominal quantifier constructions that are not constrained by it.
2.2 Differences between postnominal and floating quantifier constructions
Though postnominal and floating quantifier constructions are similar with respect to the monotonicity constraint, they also differ in important ways. One difference is that a floating quantifier forces a non-specific or indefinite reading in Korean, while this is not the case in postnominal quantifier constructions (Beom-Mo Kang 2002; Christina Kim 2005; Keun Shin 2008; Jong-Bok Kim 2013; See Watanabe 2006 for Japanese). In (22a), which is a postnominal quantifier construction, the object can refer to any two bicycles or two specific bicycles, but in (22b), with a floating quantifier, it can be interpreted only as indefinite.
- (22)
- a.
- Cheli-nun
- Cheli-TOP
- [cacenke
- [bicycle
- twu
- two
- tay]-lul
- CL]-ACC
- ssakey
- cheap
- sa-lyeko
- buy-intending
- ha-n-ta.
- do-PRE-DEC
- ‘Cheli intends to buy two bicycles/the two bicycles cheap.’
- b.
- Cheli-nun
- Cheli-TOP
- [cacenke]-lul
- [bicycle]-ACC
- ssakey
- cheap
- twu
- two
- tay
- CL
- sa-lyeko
- buy-intending
- ha-n-ta.
- do-PRE-DEC
- ‘Cheli intends buy two bicycles/#the two bicycles cheap.’
Note that the nominal associated with the floating quantifier is case-marked (cf. 22b), while case-marking is attached to the entire constituent including the quantifier in the postnominal construction (cf. 22a). Assuming that case-marked nominals are used as full-fledged DPs of argumental type, this implies that floating quantifiers combine with DPs, while postnominal quantifiers combine with NPs (Kiyong Choi 2001; Beom-Mo Kang 2002; Heejeong Ko 2007). Under this assumption, it has been claimed that the floating quantifier construction cannot have a specific reading because a floating quantifier is always associated with a kind-denoting DP (Beom-Mo Kang 2002; Keun Shin 2008).
However, this claim faces empirical problems. As mentioned earlier, a floating quantifier can occur with a specific or definite nominal. In fact, the object in (22b) can also be interpreted as ‘two of the bicycles’ in an appropriate context, referring to two bicycles out of the bicycles already mentioned or presupposed in the discourse. Furthermore, not only floating quantifiers but also postnominal quantifiers can occur with full DPs such as ku-ke ‘those,’ as in (23).
- (23)
- (Situation: Only three apples had been left in a refrigerator)
- a.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [ku-ke
- [that-thing
- twu
- two
- kay/sey kay]-lul
- CL/ three CL]-ACC
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli ate two of those/ those three (lit. the three of those).’
- b.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [ku-ke]-lul
- [that-thing]-ACC
- twu
- two
- kay/#sey
- CL/ three
- kay
- CL
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli ate two of those /#those three.’
Note that (23b), the object must be interpreted as indefinite despite the fact that the floating quantifier is associated with the definite DP ku-ke ‘that thing.’ This indefinite reading has to do with proper partitivity. In (23), sey kay ‘three CL’ refers to the improper part of denoting the set of three apples, and it is not felicitous in the floating quantifier construction. In other words, when a numeral quantifier occurs with a nominal denoting a specific set or substance, the postnominal quantifier construction can have either a proper partitive reading or an improper partitive reading, but the floating quantifier construction has only a proper partitive reading. In (23b), the floating quantifier must refer to some subpart of the nominal denotation, inducing the indefinite interpretation of the object.7
Sentences (24) and (25) also show that a proper partitive reading is obligatory for floating quantifier constructions (Jong-Bok Kim 2013).8 Sentence (24b) is pragmatically anomalous if it has a proper partitive reading. The proper partitive reading presupposes the existence of more than ten fingers and this is inconsistent with the common knowledge that a human possesses only ten fingers. Similarly, the oddness of sentence (25b) can be accounted for by the proper partitive constraint of a floating quantifier construction: the presupposition that Cheli has more than two parents does not conform to our commonly held beliefs. Indeed, (25b) becomes acceptable in a situation in which Cheli, after his marriage, calls his parents-in-law as well as his own parents as pwumonim ‘parents.’
- (24)
- a.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- kapcaki
- suddenly
- [sonkalak
- [finger
- yel
- ten
- kay]-lul
- CL]-ACC
- phyelchyepoi-ess-ta.
- spread out-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli spread out his ten fingers.’
- b.
- ??Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- sonkalak-ul
- finger-ACC
- kapcaki
- suddenly
- yel
- ten
- kay
- CL
- phyelchyepoi-ess-ta.
- spread out-PST-DEC
- (25)
- a.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [pwumonim
- [parent-ACC
- twu
- two
- pwun]-ul
- CL]-ACC
- han-tongan
- a while-during
- mosi-ko
- take care-CONJ
- sal-ass-ta.
- live-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli lived with his two parents and took care of them for a while.’
- b.
- ??Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- pwumonim-ul
- parent-ACC
- han-tongan
- a while-during
- twu
- two
- pwun
- CL
- mosi-ko
- take care-CONJ
- sal-ass-ta.
- live-PST-DEC
Christina Kim (2005) argues that the specificity difference between postnominal and floating quantifier constructions is due to the Specificity Condition of Chomsky (1973) and Fiengo & Higginbotham (1981), prohibiting the extraction out of specific DPs and accounting for the contrast between (26a) and (26b) below.
- (26)
- a.
- Who did you see a picture of?
- b.
- *Who did you see that picture of?
Under the assumption that the floating quantifier construction is derived from the postnominal quantifier construction by moving the numeral quantifier outside a DP and right-adjoining it to the DP, as in (27), Christina Kim (2005) proposes that the floating quantifier construction can have only a non-specific reading because a quantifier cannot extract out of a specific DP.9
- (27)
- [DP [DP [ku-kes ti ]-lul ] [twu kay]i]
The quantifier movement approach therefore captures the fact that a floating quantifier triggers a non-specific or proper partitive reading even when it is associated with the definite. Given that floating quantifiers are right-adjoined to the DP, this quantifier movement approach can also explain why floating quantifiers cannot precede the host DPs, as in (28).
- (28)
- a.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [sakwa]-lul
- [apple]-ACC
- twu
- two
- kay
- CL
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli ate two apples.’
- b.
- ??Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- twu
- two
- kay
- CL
- [sakwa]-lul
- [apple]-ACC
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
Considering that Korean is a head final language in which adjunction is to the left, however, the rightward adjunction of the floating quantifier in (27) seems to be very stipulative. It is also difficult to explain why floating quantifiers are only associated with arguments, not with adjuncts, as exemplified in (29). In (29), the numeral quantifier twu cang ‘two CL(sheet)’ is related to the adjunct nominal swuken ‘towel,’ and the floating quantifier construction is not acceptable. The contrast between (29a) and (29b) is puzzling if a floating quantifier is the constituent that moves on the right side of its associated DP.
- (29)
- a.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- thakca-lul
- table-ACC
- [swuken
- [towel
- twu
- two
- cang]-ulo
- CL]-INST
- takk-ass-ta.
- clean-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli cleaned the tables with two towels (quickly).’
- b.
- ??Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- thakca-lul
- table-ACC
- swuken-ulo
- towel-INST
- twu
- two
- cang
- CL
- takk-ass-ta.
- clean-PST-DEC
Christina Kim (2005) claims that a quantifier always forms a DP constituent with its associated case-marked nominal and cannot be separated from it. This claim is not empirically grounded. As in (30), an adverb can occur between a floating quantifier and the host nominal.
- (30)
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- sakwa-lul
- apple-ACC
- cayppali
- quickly
- twu
- two
- kay
- CL
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli ate two apples quickly.’
Heejeong Ko (2005; 2007) proposes an alternative adnominal approach. She claims that a floating quantifier is adjoined to the host DP but can be separated from it by moving the DP from the argument position and leaving the quantifier behind, as represented below.
- (31)
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [VP sakwa-luli
- apple-ACC
- [VP cayppali
- quickly
- [VP ti
- twu kay]
- two CL
- mek-ess-ta]]].
- eat-PST-DEC
This DP movement analysis can solve some problems with the above quantifier movement approach, but some problems continue to persist. Heejeong Ko (2005; 2007) also argues that a floating quantifier is a DP adjunct.10 Contrary to her claim, a floating quantifier never forms a syntactic constituent with the host DP. A floating quantifier and the host DP can neither be coordinated by the conjunction –(k)wa nor pseudo-clefted (Chung-Kon Shi 2000; Kiyong Choi 2001; Keun Shin 2006; 2007; Jong-Bok Kim 2013), unlike the postnominal quantifier and its associated DP, as exemplified in (32) and (33). Sentences (32a) and (33a) are wrongly predicted to be grammatical if a quantifier remains adjoined to the associated DP and does not undergo movement.
- (32)
- a.
- *Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [sakwa-lul
- [apple-ACC
- twu
- two
- kay]-wa
- CL]-CONJ
- [bay-lul
- [pear-ACC
- sey kay]
- three CL]
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli ate two apples and three pears.’
- b.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [sakwa
- [apple
- twu
- two
- kay]-wa
- CL]-CONJ
- [bay
- [pear
- sey kay]-lul
- three CL]-ACC
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- (33)
- a.
- *Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- mek-un
- eat-REL
- kes-un
- thing-TOP
- [sakwa-lul
- [apple-ACC
- twu
- two
- kay]-(i)-ta.
- CL]-(COP)-DEC
- ‘What Cheli ate is two apples.’
- b.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- mek-un
- eat-REL
- kes-un
- thing-TOP
- [sakwa
- [apple
- twu
- two
- kay]-(i)-ta.
- CL]-(COP)-DEC
In addition, the adnominal approach cannot explain why the floating quantifier fails to be related to the subject ‘guest’ even though they are immediately adjacent to each other in (34a). A floating quantifier must precede both the transitive verb and the object in order to be associated with the subject, as the contrast between (34b) and (34c) shows (Keun Shin 2006).11
- (34)
- a.
- ??wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- sonnim-i
- guest-NOM
- twu
- two
- pwun
- CL
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Two guests drank wine.’
- b.
- *sonnim-i
- guest-NOM
- wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- twu
- two
- pwun
- CL
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- c.
- sonnim-i
- guest-NOM
- twu
- two
- pwun
- CL
- wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
Another difference between postnominal and floating quantifier constructions is that floating quantifiers are not compatible with individual-level predicates that do not have episodic readings (See Fukushima 1991; Nakanishi 2007 for Japanese). As shown in (35a) and (36a), floating quantifier constructions can occur with the stage-level predicate ‘be sick,’ but not with the individual-level predicate ‘be smart.’ This semantic restriction is hard to capture under the assumption that a floating quantifier is a DP adjunct. Note that both types of predicates can occur in postnominal quantifier constructions, as in (35b) and (36b).
- (35)
- a.
- ??namhaksayng-i
- male student-NOM
- twu
- two
- myeng
- CL
- yengliha-ta.
- be smart-DEC
- ‘Two male students are smart.’
- b.
- [namhaksayng
- [male student
- twu
- two
- myeng]-i
- CL]-NOM
- yengliha-ta.
- be smart-DEC
- (36)
- a.
- namhaksayng-i
- male student-NOM
- twu
- two
- myeng
- CL
- aphu-ta.
- be sick-DEC
- ‘Two male students are sick.’
- b.
- [namhaksayng
- [male student
- twu
- two
- myeng]-i
- CL]-NOM
- aphu-ta.
- be sick-DEC
To summarize the discussion so far, unlike prenominal quantifier constructions, postnominal and floating quantifier constructions are partitive constructions that are subject to the monotonicity constraint. However, floating quantifier constructions also display several idiosyncratic properties that cannot be easily explained under the assumption that a floating quantifier adjoins to its host DP: (i) a floating quantifier does not form a syntactic constituent with the host DP; (ii) it obligatorily has an indefinite or proper partitive reading; (iii) it is only associated with the argument of a verbal predicate; (iv) it cannot be related to the subject in front of a transitive verb; (v) it imposes restrictions on verbal predicates.
3 Structures of Korean partitives
In this section, I will discuss how a partitive interpretation arises in the postnominal quantifier construction and explain how this construction can be also interpreted as a pseudo-partitive or a quantitative.12 Then I will extend this approach to floating quantifier constructions and account for the idiosyncratic properties of floating quantifiers discussed in the preceding section.
3.1 Postnominal quantifier constructions
Given that a numeral quantifier behaves as an NP modifier in the prenominal quantifier construction, it can be treated as a modifier of type ≪e, t>, <e, t ≫, as defined in (37) (Keun Shin 2007; 2009). In (37), OBJECT(x) = 2 means that x consists of 2 atoms which are inanimate objects.13
- (37)
- ⟦twu kay⟧= λPλx [P(x) ∧ OBJECT(x) = 2]
The prenominal quantifier in (37) corresponds to the English numeral quantifier two in the two apples, which is also analyzed to be of type ≪e, t>, <e, t ≫ (Verkuyl 1981; Krifka 1999; Landman 2003).
Postnominal quantifiers differ from prenominal quantifiers in that they occur with DPs and track part-whole relations, as we have seen in (20), (21) and (23). In my previous work (Keun Shin 2007; 2009), I proposed that in postnominal constructions, a numeral quantifier is of type <e, <e, t ≫, taking a DP of type e as its argument, as represented in (38).
- (38)
- ⟦twu kay⟧= λxλy [y ≤ x ∧ OBJECT(y) = 2]
The postnominal quantifier in (38) is different from the prenominal quantifier in (37) in two respects. First, the numeral quantifier in (38) turns an individual argument of e into a property of <e, t> which can be measured. This can be done by standard shifting functions parallel to ident or pred (Partee 1986; Chierchia 1998). Second, the postnominal quantifier in (38) expresses not only a quantity but also a PART-OF relation. It shifts a DP to a property that has a part-whole structure so that a measure can be used monotonically. Depending on the semantics of a classifier, therefore, ≤ expresses either an individual or material PART-OF relation. In (38), ≤ indicates an individual PART-OF relation because the classifier kay is used to count inanimate objects.
It may be worth mentioning that Korean postnominal quantifier corresponds to the combination of a numeral quantifier of type ≪e, t>, <e, t ≫ and the preposition of in English partitives and pseudo-partitives according to the claim that the preposition of denotes a PART-OF relation and has a type-shifting function in English partitives and pseudo-partitives: of converts a kind into a property in two bottles of wine (Carlson 1977; Chierchia 1998) and turns a definite DP denoting an individual into a property in two of the apples (Barwise & Cooper 1981; Ladusaw 1982; Barker 1998). Therefore, it can be assumed that Korean postnominal quantifier is derived from the prenominal quantifier by combining it with a null element corresponding to the partitive of.
In the postnominal quantifier construction, a numeral quantifier denoting a PART-OF relation takes a DP complement, forming a Classifier Phrase (CLP) headed by a classifier into which a cardinal number is incorporated, as illustrated in (39).
- (39)
When the postnominal quantifier combines with the kind-denoting sakwa ‘apple’ of type e in (40), it shifts ∩APPLE into a property and selects its subset, as translated in (40).14 (40) denotes a property that is true of subsets of the set of all apples in a world, which consist of two atoms.
- (40)
- ⟦sakwa twu kay⟧= λy [y ≤ ∩APPLE ∧ OBJECT(y) = 2]
The CLP of type <e, t> in (40) ultimately combines with D, and [DP sakwa twu kay] is interpreted as either ‘two apples’ or ‘the two apples,’ depending on the definiteness of D.
There is no or little meaning difference between the prenominal quantifier in (37) and the postnominal quantifier in (38) when the postnominal quantifier is associated with a kind-denoting DP and has a quantitative interpretation.15 Unlike the prenominal quantifier, however, the postnominal quantifier can combine with a definite DP. When sakwa ‘apple’ is a definite DP that is derived by means of the iota operator (ɩ) that maps a property to the largest individual satisfying that property in a given context, [CLP sakwa twu kay] can be interpreted as a partitive ‘two of the apples,’ as translated in (41).
- (41)
- ⟦sakwa twu kay⟧= λy [y ≤ ɩAPPLES ∧ OBJECT(y) = 2]
When a postnominal quantifier is associated with a mass noun, they can be interpreted as either English pseudo-partitive or partitive. For example, in (42), the object can be interpreted as ‘(the) two bottles of wine’ or ‘(the) two bottles of the wine.’ The object obtains a pseudo-partitive meaning if wain denotes a kind; it gets a partitive meaning if wain is a definite DP denoting a contextually given referent.
- (42)
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [wain
- [wine
- twu
- two
- pyeng]-ul
- CL]-ACC
- mas-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli broke (the) two bottles of (the) wine.’
In derivational analyses, the nominal is the head in both prenominal and postnominal structures, but in my analysis that assumes no movement, what is on the right edge is the head, and so prenominal and postnominal structures differ in headness. This approach can also capture the semantic difference between the prenominal and postnominal quantifier constructions below.
- (43)
- a.
- ??Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [twu
- [two
- pyeng-uy
- CL-GEN
- wain]-ul
- wine]-ACC
- kkayttuly-ess-ta.
- break-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli broke two bottles of wine.’
- b.
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- [wain
- [wine
- twu
- two
- pyeng]-ul
- CL]-ACC
- kkayttuly-ess-ta.
- break-PST-DEC
Under the assumption that a prenominal quantifier is an NP modifier, it is correctly predicted that a verb always imposes its selectional restrictions on the associated nominal, and the verb ‘break’ is not acceptable in (43a). In the postnominal quantifier construction, the numeral quantifier serves a syntactic head taking the DP ‘wine’ as its complement. Thus, it can be argued that (43b) is acceptable when pyeng is interpreted as a nominal head rather than a classifier head (Keun Shin 2007; 2009).
3.2 Floating quantifier constructions
Not only postnominal quantifier constructions but also floating quantifier constructions are partitive constructions in Korean in which a numeral quantifier is associated with a DP and expresses a PART-OF relation. As discussed in Section 2.2, however, floating quantifier constructions have several idiosyncratic properties that cannot be explained under the assumption that a quantifier forms a constituent with its associated nominal and undergoes a movement in a floating quantifier construction.
It is noted that a floating quantifier forms a constituent with a verb rather than its associated DP (Hong-Shik Yi 1996; Chung-Kon Shi 2000; Kiyong Choi 2001; Jong-Bok Kim 2013). They can be substituted by the pro-form kuleh-ta ‘do so-DEC,’ as shown in (44). (44) entails that two male students were absent.
- (44)
- yehaksayng-i
- female student-NOM
- twu
- two
- myeng
- CL
- kyelsek-hay-ss-ko,
- absence-do-PST-CONJ,
- namhaksayng-to
- male student-also
- kuleh-ta.
- do so-DEC
- ‘Two female students were absent, and two male students were absent too.’
By adopting Dowty & Brodie’s (1984) idea that a floating quantifier functions as an adverbial, I propose that Korean floating quantifier combines with a verbal predicate and relates a quantifier denoting a PART-OF relation to the argument of a verb.16 The Korean floating quantifier functions as a transitive verb (TV) modifier of ≪e, <e, t ≫, <e, <e, t ≫> or VP modifier of ≪e, t>, <e, t ≫, as defined in (45) where Ƥ is a variable of type <e, <e, t ≫.
- (45)
- a.
- TV modifier: ⟦twu kay⟧= λƤ λxλy∃z [[z ≤ x ∧ OBJECT(z) = 2] ∧ Ƥ(z)(y)]
- b.
- VP modifier: ⟦twu kay⟧= λPλx∃z [[z ≤ x ∧ OBJECT(z) = 2] ∧ P(z)]
Therefore, the floating quantifiers is not different from the postnominal quantifier in that it denotes a PART-OF relation of an entity. Their difference lies in how such a quantifier is construed with the DP: a floating quantifier is semantically associated with the DP via its composition with a verbal predicate.
A floating quantifier can be related to either a subject or an object, depending on whether it combines with a TV or a VP. For example, sentences (46) and (47) are translated as in (48) and (49) respectively.
- (46)
- (ku)
- (that)
- sakwa-ka
- apple-NOM
- twu
- two
- kay
- CL
- ssekk-ess-ta.
- be rotten-PST-DEC
- ‘Two of the apples were rotten.’
- (47)
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- (ku)
- (that)
- sakwa-lul
- apple-ACC
- twu
- two
- kay
- CL
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli ate two of the apples.’
- (48)
- a.
- ⟦ssekkta ⟧= λv[BE ROTTEN (v)]
- b.
- ⟦twu kay ssekkta ⟧= = λx∃z [z ≤ x ∧ OBJECT(z) = 2 ∧ BE ROTTEN (z)]
- c.
- ⟦sakwaka twu kay ssekkta ⟧= ∃z [z ≤ ɩAPPLE ∧ OBJECT(z) = 2 ∧ BE ROTTEN (z)]
- (49)
- a.
- ⟦mekta⟧= λvλw[EAT (v)(w)]
- b.
- ⟦twu kay mekta⟧= λxλy∃z [z ≤ x ∧ OBJECT(z) = 2 ∧ EAT (z)(y)]
- c.
- ⟦sakwalul twu kay mekta⟧= λy∃z [z ≤ ɩAPPLE ∧ OBJECT(z) = 2 ∧ EAT (z)(y)]
- d.
- ⟦Chelika sakwalul twu kay mekta ⟧= ∃z [z ≤ ɩAPPLE ∧ OBJECT(z) = 2 ∧ EAT (z)(CHELI)]
In (48) and (49), the floating quantifier combines with a verb, forming a complex predicate taking the host DP as its argument. It can be understood that the postnominal quantifier twu kay in (38), which is repeated in (50), saturates its internal argument position with sakwa ‘apple’ after it combines with a verb in the floating quantifier construction.
- (50)
- ⟦twu kay⟧= λxλy [y ≤ x ∧ OBJECT(y) = 2]
The meaning of the floating quantifier construction in (49) can therefore be conveyed by the corresponding postnominal quantifier construction.
One key difference between floating and postnominal quantifier constructions is that only a proper partitive reading is possible in floating quantifier constructions. According to the definitions in (45), when the floating quantifier combines with a verbal predicate, the argument of the verb, associated with the quantifier, is bound by the existential quantifier representing an indefinite interpretation. In other words, the floating quantifier requires that a partitive – the semantic combination of the DP and the quantifier – be interpreted as indefinite. There is a meaning difference between definite and indefinite partitives. Compare (51a) and (51b).
- (51)
- a.
- Bill’s daughters lived together. The three of them got married on the same day.
- b.
- Bill’s daughters lived together. Three of them got married on the same day.
In (51a), the definite partitive the three of them can express improper partitivity: Bill has three daughters and all of them got married on the same day. On the other hand, (51b) presupposes that Bill has at least four daughters. The indefinite partitive three of them must denote a proper part of the entity denoted by Bill’s daughters. If an indefinite partitive requires a proper partitive reading, it is predicted that the improper partitive reading is not felicitous in (49) because the partitive ‘two of the apples’ must be interpreted as indefinite.
Given that a floating quantifier relates a quantifier denoting a PART-OF relation to the argument of a verb, it is correctly predicted that a floating quantifier is only associated with the argument of a verb. Following the predicate-modifier approach, the numeral quantifier twu cang in (52) combines with the TV ‘clean,’ and hence it is semantically connected with the internal argument of a verb, i.e., ‘table,’ as translated in (53). Sentence (52) is not acceptable because cang ‘sheet’ is not an appropriate classifier for counting tables.
- (52)
- ??ku-ka
- he-NOM
- thakca-lul
- table-ACC
- swuken-ulo
- towel-INST
- twu cang
- two CL
- takk-ass-ta.
- clean-PST-DEC
- ‘He cleaned the tables with two towels.’
- (53)
- ⟦twu cang takk-ta⟧= λxλy∃z [z ≤ x ∧ SHEET(z) = 2 ∧ CLEAN (z)(y)]
Recall that a floating quantifier can be associated with the subject in a transitive sentence only when it precedes both the verb and the object (Keun Shin 2006):
- (54)
- a.
- sonnim-i
- guest-NOM
- twu pwun
- two CL
- ku
- that
- wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Two guests drank the wine.’
- b.
- *sonnim-i
- guest-NOM
- ku
- that
- wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- twu
- two
- pwun
- CL
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
This word order restriction can be explained under the assumption that a floating quantifier can combine with both TV and VP.17 A floating quantifier in front of a transitive verb is interpreted as a TV modifier. Hence, as illustrated in (49), the floating quantifier that combines with the transitive verb is associated with the unsaturated internal argument of the verb, i.e., the object. Sentence (54b) is ruled out since the non-human object ‘wine’ is not a suitable host for the numeral quantifier twu pwun that is used for counting humans. A floating quantifier must combine with a VP in order to relate the quantifier to the subject, as illustrated in (55). The predicate-modifier approach makes a correct prediction that the subject-associated floating quantifier must precede the object of a transitive verb.
- (55)
- a.
- ⟦masita⟧= λvλw[DRINK (v)(w)]
- b.
- ⟦wainul masita⟧= λw[DRINK (ɩWINE)(w)]
- c.
- ⟦twu pwun wainul masita⟧= λx∃z [z ≤ x ∧ PERSON(z) = 2 ∧ DRINK (ɩWINE)(z)]
- d.
- ⟦sonnimi twu pwun wainul masita⟧= ∃z [z ≤ ∩GUEST ∧ PERSON(z) = 2 ∧ DRINK (ɩWINE)(z)]
The predicate-modifier approach can also capture the fact that a floating quantifier always follows its associated DP in a sentence, as in (56). The key to explaining the ungrammaticality of (56) is that a floating quantifier is connected to the unsaturated argument of a verb.
- (56)
- ??sonnim-i
- guest-NOM
- twu
- two
- pyeng
- CL
- ku
- that
- wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Guests drank two bottles of that wine.’
A floating quantifier can be construed with the object when it combines with a transitive verb whose internal argument is not saturated. This means that the floating quantifier two pyeng preceding the object ‘that wine’ is associated with the external argument of the verb ‘drink’ by modifying the VP, as exemplified in (55). Sentence (56) is not felicitous because guests cannot be counted in terms of pyeng. (57) is the translation of sentence (56).
- (57)
- ∃z [z ≤ ∩GUEST ∧ BOTTLE(z) = 2 ∧ DRINK (ɩWINE)(z)]
The predicate-modifier analysis has a potential to explain restrictions on verbal predicates in floating quantifier constructions. Floating quantifier constructions sound odd when they contain an individual-level predicate that describes a permanent property of the subject.
- (58)
- ??namhaksayng-i
- male student-NOM
- twu
- two
- myeng
- CL
- yengliha-ta.
- be smart-DEC
- ‘Two male students are smart.’
Since a floating quantifier is a predicate-modifier, it seems plausible that a floating quantifier can have effects on the choice of the predicate. Kratzer (1995) argues that stage-level predicates and individual-level predicates differ in argument structure; stage-level predicates have an event argument, whereas individual-level predicates lack this argument. If an event argument is included in the argument structure of a verbal predicate, the resistance of individual-level predicates in floating quantifier constructions can be accounted for by claiming that a floating quantifier affects an event argument as well as a participant argument.
4 Conclusions
In Korean, the distinction between partitives and non-partitives are made by the relative order between a quantifier and its associated nominal. Unlike prenominal quantifier constructions, postnominal constructions are partitives in which numeral quantifiers track part-whole relations. Given that Korean is a head-final language, the word order between a quantifier and the nominal within a DP indicates that a postnominal quantifier does not function as an NP modifier but as a head denoting a PART-OF relation and taking a DP as its argument. Korean postnominal quantifier constructions can also be interpreted as pseudo-partitives, or quantitatives. I have argued that this is because a postnominal quantifier can be associated with a kind-denoting DP as well as a definite DP referring to a specific set or substance.
Korean floating quantifier constructions are also partitive constructions but display several idiosyncratic properties which cannot be easily captured under the assumption that a postnominal quantifier moves away from the associated nominal in the floating quantifier construction. By adopting Dowty & Brodie’s (1984) adverbial approach, I have proposed that Korean floating quantifier combines with a verb and relates a quantifier denoting a PART-OF relation to the argument of a verb. In other words, Korean floating quantifiers quantify over individual variables which are arguments of verbal predicates, forcing indefinite interpretations. This approach can explain why an indefinite or proper partitive reading is obligatory in the floating quantifier construction and other syntactic and semantic differences between postnominal and floating quantifier constructions.
Abbreviations
acc = accusative, cl = classifier, conj = conjunction, cop = copular, dec = declarative, gen = genitive, int = interrogative, pol = polite, pst = past, pl = plural, rel = relativizer or adnominal modifier, sh = subject honorific, top = topic
Notes
- Nouns referring to humans and body-parts can combine directly with numerals without classifiers. [^]
-
A mass noun can occur with cwung-eyse ‘among-from’
when the substance is interpreted as an object made up of discrete divisive
elements with the help of a classifier, as in (i)
- (i)
- ku-nun
- he-TOP
- wain
- wine
- tases
- five
- can
- CL
- cwung-eyse
- among-from
- twu can-ul
- two CL-ACC
- massy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘He drank two out of the five glasses of wine.’
- (10a) and (10b) may become acceptable when they are interpreted as appositive constructions in which ‘those students’ refers to ‘Cheli and Juni’ in (10a) and ‘two male students’ in (10b). [^]
-
Note that partitivity can express improper partitivity when partitives contain
universal quantifiers such as all of the students and
both of them. Korean separation constructions are not
compatible with universal quantifiers, unlike floating quantifier constructions,
as in (i) and (ii). This difference also shows that floating quantifier
constructions are more closely related to partitives than separation
constructions.
- (i)
- *ku
- that
- haksayng-tul
- student-PL
- cwung-eyse
- among-from
- [motwu/cenpwu]-ka
- [all/all]-NOM
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘(Lit.) Among those students, all got hurt.’
- (ii)
- ku
- that
- haksayng-tul-i
- student-PL-NOM
- [motwu/cenpwu](-ka)
- [all/all](-NOM)
- tachy-ess-ta.
- get hurt-PST-DEC
- ‘All of those students got hurt.’
- For convenience the term “postnominal quantifiers” will be reserved for postnominal non-floating quantifiers only. [^]
- Japanese has quantifier constructions corresponding to Korean prenominal, postnominal, and floating quantifier constructions. Previous studies cited in this paper include some important analyses of Japanese quantifier constructions. [^]
- The term “specific” is different from the one that Enç (1991) and Diesing (1992) use for partitive constructions. Diesing (1992) uses term “specific indefinites” for (indefinite) proper partitives such as [DP three of the students]. I am reserving the term “specific” for DP descriptions that are used by a speaker to refer to a particular entity specifically and can be characterized in terms of referentiality (Donnellan 1966; Fodor & Sag 1982). [^]
-
Cf. Jong-Bok Kim (2013) explains the
unacceptability of (24b) and (25b) by analyzing a floating quantifier as a focus
marker that introduces the quantity information as new information. He argues
that the floating quantifiers are not felicitous in (24b) and (25b) because the
information that the floating quantifier gives us is not new but is understood
by the conventional implicature. However, the floating quantifier construction
is felicitous even when the quantity information is already given in a
context:
- (i)
- A:
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- mwues-ul
- what-ACC
- sey
- three
- kay
- CL
- mek-ess-ni?
- eat-PST-INT
- ‘Cheli ate three of what?’
- B:
- Cheli-ka
- Cheli-NOM
- sakwa-lul
- apple-ACC
- sey
- three
- kay
- CL
- mek-ess-ta.
- eat-PST-DEC
- ‘Cheli ate three of the apples.’
-
Watanabe (2006) makes a similar claim. He
argues that a non-specific reading of the floating quantifier construction
results from the movement of a case-marked nominal to Spec of D [-specific], as
schematically illustrated in (i), under the assumption that the floating
quantifier construction is derived from the prenominal quantifier construction,
which is in turn derived from the postnominal quantifier construction.
- (i)
- [DP cacenke-luli [QP twu tay[Q’ ti [Q ] ] D[-specific] ]]
- To be precise, Heejeong Ko (2005; 2007) argues that caseless floating quantifiers are adnominal modifiers, while case-marked floating quantifiers are adverbials. This paper only focuses on caseless floating quantifiers. [^]
-
When a floating quantifier is associated with the subject, the object cannot
intervene between the quantifier and the host nominal, as in (34b). In contrast,
when a floating quantifier is associated with the object, the subject can occur
between the quantifier and the host, as in (i).
- (i)
- wain-ul
- wine-ACC
- sonnim-i
- guest-NOM
- twu
- two
- pyeng
- CL
- masy-ess-ta.
- drink-PST-DEC
- ‘Guests drank two bottles of wine.’
- My analysis of the postnominal quantifier presented in Section 3.1 is based on my previous work (Keun Shin 2007; 2009). [^]
- It is claimed that all nouns are mass nouns in a classifier language and this is why classifiers are required to combine numerals with nouns (Chierchia 1998; Nakanishi 2004; Kwon & Zribi-Hertz 2004). However, it is reported that there is a distinction between count and mass nouns in a classifier language (see Beom-Mo Kang 1994; Chonghyuck Kim 2008; Keun Shin 2009 for Korean). Krifka (1995) argues that non-classifier languages are different from classifier languages in terms of the semantics of numerals. In a non-classifier language like English, a numeral has a nominal argument position in the lexicon and directly combines with a noun; in a classifier language, a numeral lacks such a nominal argument position and it always requires the presence of a classifier to combine with a noun. Adopting Krifka’s claim, I assume that a numeral is incorporated into a classifier, forming a numeral quantifier in Korean (Keun Shin 2007). It should be also noted that different classifiers are used for different types of nouns. The classifier kay in (37) is used with a noun denoting an inanimate concrete object. It cannot occur only with human or other animate nouns. A classifier not only allows a numeral to combine with a noun, but also semantically interacts with a noun. [^]
- The kind-denoting ‘apple’ of type e is assumed to be derived from a property by Chierchia’s (1982; 1998) nominalization operator (∩) mapping a property to a kind individual. [^]
-
Prenominal quantifier constructions tend to be used in formal contexts or in
writings; they are hardly used in colloquial speech. For example, when the
speaker tries to buy 10 apples from a fruit store, she/he will use the
postnominal quantifier construction as below (Song-Hwa Han 1999). Prenominal quantifier construction is awkward in
this situation.
- (i)
- a.
- ??acwumma,
- missus,
- yel kay-uy
- ten CL-GEN
- sakwa
- apple
- cwu-sey-yo.
- give-SH-POL
- b.
- acwumma,
- missus,
- sakwa
- apple
- yel kay
- 10 CL
- cwu-sey-yo.
- give-SH-POL
- ‘Missus, please give me 10 apples.’
- Dowty & Brodie (1984) analyzed English floating quantifier all as an adverbial functor that relates a VP denotation to a DP denotation. [^]
- It should be noted that sentence (54b) becomes acceptable when the floating quantifier is focused (Beom-Mo Kang 2002; Heejeong Ko 2007; Jong-Bok Kim 2013). Steedman (1996) suggests that focus or particular information can induce a non-standard composition in a categorical grammar framework. If focus allows a floating quantifier of type ≪e, t>, <e, t ≫ to combine with a transitive verb via function composition – not via function application, it can explain how the focused quantifier twu pwun in (54b) can be associated with the external argument of the transitive verb. [^]
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Karlos Arregi, Abbas Bemamoun, Youngju Choi, and Peter Laserson for comments on an earlier version of this article. Special thanks to James Yoon for his valuable suggestions to improve the quality of the paper. I am also deeply grateful for the editors of this special issue and the anonymous reviewers for Glossa and Lingua. All remaining errors are mine.
Competing Interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
References
Barker, Chris . (1998). Partitives, double genitives and anti-uniqueness. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 16 (4) : 679. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1005917421076
Barwise, Jon; Cooper, Robin . (1981). Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (2) : 159. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00350139
Carlson, Gregory . (1977). Reference to kinds in English. dissertation. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts.
Chae, Wan . (1983). Kwuke swusa mich swulayngkwu-uy wyuhyengcek kochal [A study of numerals and numeral classifier constructions in Korean]. Language Research 19 (1) : 19.
Chierchia, Gennaro . (1982). Nominalization and Montague grammar: A semantics without types for natural languages. Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (3) : 303. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00351458
Chierchia, Gennaro . (1998). Reference to kinds across languages. Natural Language Semantics 6 : 339. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1008324218506
Choi, Kiyong . (2001). Hakwuke swulyangsa kwusenguy kwucowa uymi: pisokkyekhyengul cwungsimulo [The structure and interpretation of non-genitive numeral classifier constructions in Korean]. Language Research 37 (3) : 445.
Chomsky, Noam . (1973). Conditions on transformations In: Anderson, Stephen, Kiparsky, Paul Paul (eds.), A Festschrift for Morris Halle. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, pp. 263.
Diesing, Molly . (1992). Indefinites. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dowty, David; Brodie, Belinda . (1984). The semantics of “floated” quantifiers in a transformationless grammar. West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL). 3 : 75.
Enç, Mürvet . (1991). The semantics of specificity. Linguistic Inquiry 22 (1) : 1.
Fiengo, Robert; Higginbotham, James . (1981). Opacity in NP. Linguistic Analysis 7 (4) : 395.
Fukushima, Kazuhiko . (1991). Phrase structure grammar, Montague semantics, and floating quantifiers in Japanese. Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (6) : 581. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00631961
Gill, Kook-Hee . (2001). Floating quantifiers, case and scrambling. Harvard Studies in Korean Linguistics 9 : 328.
Han, Song-Hwa . (1999). Swusa-wa swulyangsakwu [numerals and numeral classifier phrases]. Sacen pyenchanhak yenkwu [Studies in lexicography] 9 (1) : 265.
Hoeksema, Jacob . (1984). Partitives In: Ms. University of Groningen.
Hoeksema, Jacob . (1996). Introduction In: Hoeksema, Jacob (ed.), Partitives. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, pp. 1.
Ionin, Tania; Matushansky, Ora; Ruys, Eddy . (2006). Parts of speech: Toward a unified semantics for partitives. North East Linguistics Society (NELS) 36 (1) : 357.
Kang, Beom-Mo . (1994). Plurality and other semantic aspects of common nouns in Korean. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 3 (1) : 1. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF01733148
Kang, Beom-Mo . (2002). Categories and meanings of Korean floating quantifiers – with some reference to Japanese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 11 (4) : 375. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1019967311110
Kim, Chonghyuck . (2008). Classifiers and plural marking. Japanese/Korean Linguistics 13 : 167.
Kim, Christina . (2005). Order and meaning: Numeral classifiers and specificity in Korean. West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL). 24 : 218.
Kim, Jong-Bok . (2013). Floated numeral classifiers in Korean: A non-derivational, functional account. Lingua 133 : 189. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2013.04.009
Kim, Young-Hee . (1983). Hankwuke seymswuthhwa kwumwun-uy thongsalon [Syntax of Korean numeral phrases]. dissertation. Seoul: Yonsei University.
Ko, Heejeong . (2005). Syntactic edges and linearization. dissertation. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Ko, Heejeong . (2007). Asymmetries in scrambling and cyclic linearization. Linguistic Inquiry 38 (1) : 29. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1162/ling.2007.38.1.49
Koptjevskaja-Tamm, Maria . (2001). “A piece of the cake” and “a cup of tea”: Partitive and pseudo-partitive nominal constructions in the Circum-Baltic languages In: Dahl, Östen, Koptjevskaja-Tamm, Maria Maria (eds.), The Circum-Baltic languages: Typology and contact. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2 pp. 523. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1075/slcs.55.11kop
Kratzer, Angelika . (1995). Stage-level and individual-level predicates In: Carlson, Gregory, Pelletier, Francis Francis (eds.), The generic book. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 125.
Krifka, Manfred . (1989). Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics In: Bartsch, Renate, van Benthem, Johan; Johan and van Emde, Boas Boas (eds.), Semantics and contextual expressions (Groningen-Amsterdam Studies in Semantics 11). Dordrecht: Foris Publications, pp. 75.
Krifka, Manfred . (1995). Common nouns: A contrastive analysis of Chinese and English In: Carlson, Gregory, Pelletier, Francis Francis (eds.), The generic book. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 398.
Krifka, Manfred . (1998). The origins of telicity In: Rothstein, Susan (ed.), Events and grammar. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 197. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3969-4_9
Krifka, Manfred . (1999). At least some determiners aren’t determiners In: Turner, Ken (ed.), The semantics/pragmatics interface from different points of view. Amsterdam: Elsevier, pp. 257.
Kwon, Song Nim; Zribi-Hertz, Ann . (2004). Bonami, Olivier, Hofherr, Patricia Patricia (eds.), Number from a syntactic perspective: Why plural marking looks ‘truer’ in French than in Korean. Empirical Issues in Formal Syntax and Semantics 5 : 133. http://www.cssp.cnrs.fr/eiss5/kwon-zribi-hertz/index_en.html
Ladusaw, William . (1982). Semantic constraints on the English partitive constructions. West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL). 1 : 231.
Landman, Fred . (2003). Predicate-argument mismatches and the adjectival theory of indefinites In: Coene, Martine, D’hulst, Yves Yves (eds.), From NP to DP: The syntax and semantics of Noun Phrases. Amsterdam: Benjamins, 1 pp. 211. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1075/la.55.10lan
Miyagawa, Shigeru; Arikawa, Koju . (2007). Locality in syntax and floating numeral quantifiers. Linguistic Inquiry 38 (4) : 645. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1162/ling.2007.38.4.645
Nakanishi, Kimiko . (2004). Domains of measurement: Formal properties of non-split/split quantifier constructions. dissertation. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania.
Nakanishi, Kimiko . (2007). Formal properties of measurement constructions. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Park, Myung-Kwan; Sohn, Keun-Won . (). Floating quantifiers, scrambling, and the ECP. Japanese/Korean linguistics 3 : 187.
Partee, Barbara . (1986). Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles In: Groenendijk, Jeroen, de Jongh, Dick; Dick and Stokhof, Martin Martin (eds.), Studies in discourse representation theory and the theory of generalized quantifiers. Dordrecht: Foris, pp. 115.
Schwarzschild, Roger . (2002). The grammar of measurement. Semantics and Linguistics Theory (SALT) 12 : 225. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.3765/salt.v12i0.2870
Schwarzschild, Roger . (2006). The role of dimensions in the syntax of noun phrases. Syntax 9 (1) : 67. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9612.2006.00083.x
Shi, Chung-Kon . (2000). The syntactic structure of quantifier phrase in Korean. Korean Journal of Linguistics 25 (1) : 73.
Shin, Keun Young . (2006). Non-case-marked floating quantifiers. Harvard Studies in Korean Linguistics 11 : 751.
Shin, Keun Young . (2007). Partitive structures. dissertation. Champaign, IL: The University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.
Shin, Keun Young . (2008). Quantified noun phrases in a head-final language. North East Linguistics Society (NELS) 37 (2) : 197.
Shin, Keun Young . (2009). Numeral quantifiers: NP modifiers and relational quantity nominals. Language Research 45 (1) : 131.
Steedman, Mark . (1996). Surface structure and interpretation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Verkuyl, Henk . (1981). Numerals and quantifiers in X-bar-syntax and their semantic interpretation In: Janssen, Theo, Stokhof, Martin; Martin and Groenendijk, Jeroen Jeroen (eds.), Formal methods in the study of language. Amsterdam: Mathematical Centre Tracts, pp. 567.
Watanabe, Arika . (2006). Functional projections of nominals in Japanese: Syntax of classifiers. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 24 (1) : 241. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11049-005-3042-4
Yi, Hong-Shik . (1996). Hyentay kwuke mwuncang-uy cwusengpwun yenku [A study on major sentence constituents in Korean]. dissertation. Seoul: Seoul National University.