1 Introduction
Natural languages exhibit words or expressions that cannot freely occur in any configurations. For instance, English temporal adverb yet can only appear in negative contexts, such as in the scope of sentential negation or a negative indefinite as shown in (1a) and (1b), but is not allowed in simple affirmative contexts as demonstrated in (1c).
(1) | a. | Max has not finished yet. |
b. | Nobody has finished yet. | |
c. | *Mary has finished yet. |
Words or expressions that show a constrained distribution only in negative contexts are called Negative Polarity Items (NPIs) (cf. Ladusaw 1979). Yet is an NPI; other well-studied examples of NPIs involve English any-terms. As shown in (2), any-terms can survive in a wide range of negative contexts that are categorised as downward entailing (DE) in the literature (Fauconnier 1975; 1978; 1980; Ladusaw 1979). Examples of DE-contexts are in the scope of sentential negation, negative indefinites, or semi-negative expressions like few, the restriction of a universal quantifier, conditional clauses, etc.1 However, contexts that do not exhibit DE-ness, such as the simple past tense or in the scope of an epistemic modal adverb, do not sanction any-terms, as shown in (3).
(2) | a. | Max did not kiss anybody yesterday. |
b. | Nobody bought anything for Max’s birthday. | |
c. | Few students have read any papers for the lecture today. | |
d. | Every parent that prepared anything for the party can park free of charge. | |
e. | If Mary has seen any robins yesterday, she would tell Max. |
(3) | a. | *Max saw any girls yesterday. |
b. | *Mary has probably brought anything for Max’s birthday. |
NPIs form a cross-linguistic phenomenon (see Haspelmath 1997 and Horn 1989 for a non-exhaustive overview) and are attested in Mandarin Chinese as well. An example is shenme ‘a/some’. As observed for all NPIs, shenme exhibits a limited distribution in certain negative environments only (e.g. Huang Cheng-Teh 1982; Li Ye-Hui 1992; Cheng Lai-Shan 1994; Lin Jo-Wang 1996; 1998). Recently, Lin Jing et al. (2014) and Xie Zhi-Guo (2007) have demonstrated that this NPI is in fact attested in the whole array of nonveridical contexts, a superset of the set of DE contexts.
Informally speaking, nonveridical contexts are contexts that do not entail the truth of an embedded proposition, such as conditional clauses, questions (wh- or polar), subjunctive modal contexts, and imperfectives. Given its broad distribution in all kinds of nonveridical contexts, Lin Jing et al. (2014), following Zwarts’ typology of NPIs in terms of strengths (1981; 1986; 1995), categorise Mandarin shenme as a prototypical superweak NPI, restricted by nonveridicality only. Adopting Giannakidou (1998; 2011), Lin Jing et al. (2014) further argue that shenme is a superweak NPI because it is a referentially deficient quantifier, due to the presence of a dependent variable (explained in more detail below in Section 2).
The existence of NPIs such as the superweak NPI shenme in Mandarin gives rise to a learnability challenge for language-acquiring children. In the absence of negative evidence, such as corrective feedback or explicit instructions on its ungrammaticality in contexts that are not nonveridical, how are Mandarin children able to detect shenme’s distributional constraint based on positive evidence only?
Nonetheless, the acquisition of NPIs has attracted little attention in the literature so far – let alone that of the superweak NPI shenme in Mandarin Chinese. Research on the learnability of NPIs is merely restricted to English any (Tieu Lyn 2010; 2013; 2015; Tieu Lyn & Lidz 2016), Dutch hoeven ‘need’ (Koster & van der Wal 1996; van der Wal 1996; Lin Jing et al. 2015), Dutch meer ‘more’ (van der Wal 1996), and Mandarin Chinese renhe ‘any’ (Huang Ai-Jun & Crain 2014). This paper therefore explores the learnability of the NPI shenme by means of an experiment with an elicited imitation task.
Data obtained from 88 monolingual Mandarin children in the elicited imitation task (2; 11 – 4; 09; M = 3; 11; SD = 0; 6; 44 girls) give rise to the following developmental patterns. First, as early as the age of 2; 11, Mandarin children have already acquired shenme as a wh-word in wh-questions. Second, when they are older, children are developing their knowledge underlying shenme’s appearance in a wider range of nonveridical contexts than merely in wh-questions as well. Last but not least, children – independent of their age – are aware of shenme’s distributional constraint that it cannot survive in veridical contexts like the perfect tense.
By taking different factors into account, such as input, children’s semantic knowledge of (non)veridicality, and development of their working memory, I interpret the attested patterns as indicating a learning path in which Mandarin children reanalyse shenme as a non-referential quantifier after they first analyse it as a mere wh-quantifier in the initial phase. By analysing both the participants’ imitation and non-imitation responses, I argue that in the absence of negative evidence, children are able to detect the restricted distribution of NPIs. Their solution to the learnability problem of the NPI is to employ a widening learning strategy, in which they start with a strict analysis, and weaken it to a less strict, generalising analysis later on (cf. Manzini & Wexler 1987; Snyder 2008; see also van der Wal 1996).
I organise the paper as follows. Section 2 briefly demonstrates the restricted distribution of Mandarin shenme to nonveridical contexts, its learnability problem, and some previous acquisition research. Section 3 introduces the current experiment, including method, design, participants and scoring. Results of the experiment are presented and interpreted in Section 4, followed by discussion in Section 5, and conclusion in Section 6.
2 Background
Shenme is traditionally viewed as a wh-word similar to English what (see (4)), which also allows non-interrogative, existential interpretations comparable with English a(n) or some when appearing in certain non-wh contexts. Examples of such contexts are in the scope of sentential negation, conditional clauses, subjunctive configurations introduced by epistemic modal adverbs, polar questions, etc. (see (5a) to (5e) respectively) (Huang Cheng-Teh 1982; Li Ye-Hui 1992; Cheng Lai-Shan 1994; Lin Jo-Wang 1996; 1998; among many others).
- (4)
- Mali
- Mary
- zuotian
- yesterday
- mai-le
- buy-PERF
- shenme
- shenme
- shu
- book
- ne?
- Q-MARKER
- ‘What kind of book has Mary bought yesterday?’
- (5)
- a.
- Mali
- Mary
- zuotian
- yesterday
- mei
- not
- mai
- buy
- shenme
- shenme
- shu.
- book
- ‘Mary did not buy (a) book(s) yesterday.’
- b.
- Ruguo
- if
- Mali
- Mary
- zuotian
- yesterday
- mai-le
- buy-PERF
- shenme
- shenme
- shu
- book
- ta
- she
- yiding
- definitely
- hui
- will
- gaosu
- tell
- wo.
- me
- ‘If Mary bought a book yesterday she will definitely let me know.’
- c.
- Mali
- Mary
- zuotian
- yesterday
- haoxiang
- probably
- mai-le
- buy-PERF
- shenme
- shenme
- shu.
- book
- ‘Mary has probably bought a book yesterday.’
- d.
- Makesi
- Max
- zuotian
- yesterday
- gei
- for
- Mali
- Mary
- mai-le
- buy-PERF
- shenme
- shenme
- shu
- book
- me?
- Q-MARKER
- ‘Has Max bought (a/some) book(s) for Mary yesterday?’
The Chinese literature has argued that shenme – when it is not assigned a question usage – exhibits NPI-like behaviour, since it is ungrammatical when appearing in simple affirmative contexts such as in the perfect tense, or in the complement clause of a factive predicate like know (Li Ye-Hui 1992; Cheng Lai-Shan 1994; Lin Jo-Wang 1996; Xie Zhi-Guo 2007; among others). This is shown in (6).
- (6)
- a.
- *Makesi
- Max
- zuotian
- yesterday
- mai-le
- buy-PERF
- shenme
- shenme
- shu.
- book
- Intended: ‘Max has bought (a) book(s) yesterday.’
- b.
- *Wo
- I
- zhidao
- know
- Mali
- Mary
- zuotian
- yesterday
- mai-le
- buy-PERF
- shenme
- shenme
- shu.
- book
- Intended: ‘I know that Mary has bought (a) book(s) yesterday.’
Recently, it has been proposed that shenme is an indefinite NPI allowed only in so-called nonveridical contexts irrespective of its wh- or non-wh usages (Xie Zhi-Guo 2007; Lin Jing et al. 2014; Giannakidou to appear; Giannakidou & Lin Jing 2016). Nonveridicality is defined in terms of truth (Zwarts 1986; 1998):
- (7)
- A propositional operator F is veridical, iff Fp entails p: otherwise F is nonveridical.
Informally, nonveridical contexts can be interpreted as those that do not entail the truth of an embedded proposition. The complement clause of non-factive verbs such as guess, for instance, is nonveridical, since the truth of the proposition (8a) is not entailed by (8b). In the same vein, polar questions and epistemic uncertainty contexts are nonveridical, since both (8c) and (8d) do not necessarily entail (8a).
(8) | a. | Max kissed a girl yesterday. |
b. | I guess that Max kissed a girl yesterday. | |
c. | Did Max kiss a girl yesterday? | |
d. | Perhaps Max kissed a girl yesterday. |
A veridical context, on the other hand, is a context in which the truth of a proposition is entailed. For instance, the complement clause of factive predicates such as know in (9b) is veridical, as it necessarily entails the truth of its embedded proposition (9a).
(9) | a. | Max kissed a girl yesterday. |
b. | I know that Max kissed a girl yesterday. |
Lin Jing et al. (2014) examine all the contexts that sanction shenme in Mandarin Chinese, including wh-questions, and show that they are all nonveridical, as none of them entails the truth of an embedded proposition. Crucially, the authors also demonstrate that the contexts that do not favour shenme all turn out to be veridical.
Under the nonveridicality theory of polarity licensing (Zwarts 1995; 1998; Giannakidou 1997; 1998; 2002; 2011; Giannakidou & Zwarts 1998), nonveridical contexts represent even weaker negative environments than DE-contexts. In fact, nonveridical contexts are the weakest type of negative configurations in natural languages that may license NPIs (Giannakidou 1997; 1998; 2002; 2011). Given that English any-terms, restricted to DE-contexts, are categorised as weak NPIs in the typology of polarity items in terms of strengths (Zwarts 1981; 1986; 1995; see also van der Wouden 1994),2 Lin Jing et al. (2014) conclude that shenme is a prototypical superweak NPI. Following Giannakidou’s work on NPI-hood (Giannakidou 1998; 2011; Giannakidou & Quer 2013), the authors further argue that shenme is restricted by nonveridicality because it contains a dependent variable. Since dependent variables cannot introduce a discourse referent, unlike free or independent variables (cf. Giannakidou 2011), NPIs like shenme, which are argued to contain such a variable, are referentially deficient and thus survive in semantic configurations in which they are not forced to refer: nonveridical contexts (see also Giannakidou & Lin Jing 2016).
In fact, the non-referential approach to shenme echoes earlier claims in the Chinese literature on this NPI. For instance, Li Ye-Hui (1992) proposes that shenme is only acceptable in contexts where “the truth value of the proposition is not positively fixed in a definite manner” (Li Ye-Hui 1992: 134); Lin Jo-Wang (1998) argues that shenme appears when the existence of a referent satisfying its description given by the context is not entailed, i.e. the Non-Entailment-of-Existence Condition in his framework.
The restricted distribution of the NPI shenme to some but not all kinds of semantic configurations gives rise to a learnability problem. Based merely on positive evidence containing utterances like those in (4) and (5), how are Mandarin-acquiring children able to draw the adult-like conclusion that shenme cannot introduce any discourse referent and hence is subject to restricted distribution to nonveridical contexts? After all, absence of ungrammatical constructions with shenme in veridical contexts in the input, such as those in (6), does not necessarily entail shenme’s non-referentiality.
The learnability of the Mandarin NPI shenme, however, has attracted little attention. There are only a few studies that are somewhat related to this topic. Huang Ai-Jun (2014) and Zhou Peng (2011) report that children are able to distinguish the interrogative usage from the non-interrogative usage of Mandarin wh-words such as shenme around the age of four. Huang Ai-Jun & Crain (2014) find that children do not show target-like performance when confronted with shenme appearing in the scope of sentential negation until the age of eight. But these studies do not provide an answer to the learnability problem, nor do these studies explore the development of children’s knowledge of the non-referential NPI over time – as they focus on the different usages of shenme by children of different ages. The only research thus far that tackles the learnability of the Mandarin NPI shenme is Lin Jing et al. (2014), in which the authors investigate the development of children’s knowledge of the NPI through corpus research in the CHILDES database (MacWinney 2009).
Lin Jing et al.’s corpus exploration analyses spontaneous speech data of more than 40 monolingual Mandarin children aged between one and five years, taken from a total of 734 CHAT files of three subcorpora in the CHILDES database (MacWhinney 2009): Beijing 2 (Tardif 1993; 1996), Zhou 1 and Zhou 2 (Zhou Jing 2004a; b). Based on the distributional patterns of shenme in child Mandarin development, the authors hypothesise that there are two developmental stages in the acquisition of the NPI. Children start using shenme as a mere question word in wh-questions, but after the age of four they also use shenme in a variety of other nonveridical contexts. More importantly, the authors do not find that Mandarin children overuse the NPI in veridical contexts. Assuming that each developmental stage represents a unique analysis of the target NPI in child language development, the authors conclude that Mandarin children start with a wh-analysis of shenme, and reanalyse shenme as a superweak NPI shortly after the age of four.
Lin Jing et al.’s CHILDES study provides a first glance into the learnability of the Mandarin NPI, but is restricted to the observation of spontaneous production only. But what children produce in their spontaneous speech does not always equal the exact range of their acquired linguistic knowledge. Bearing this in mind, it becomes questionable whether the absence of utterances containing shenme in veridical contexts in child language indeed indicates children’s awareness of shenme’s distributional constraint. In the same vein, the authors do not find that older children spontaneously use shenme in, e.g. polar questions, a nonveridical context in which the NPI is allowed in adult language (i.e. (5d)). Is such absence of evidence problematic for the proposed reanalysis of shenme that generates its appearance in the whole array of nonveridical environments? The methodological shortcoming of the previous corpus research thus motivates the current experiment.
Since shenme is a prototypical superweak NPI, which is of a different strength compared to the NPIs previously investigated (e.g. English any, Dutch hoeven, and Mandarin renhe), the current exploration of the acquisition of shenme can provide the literature with a typologically comparative view of NPI acquisition. As NPIs belong to the category of words or expressions that have restricted distributions, the current investigation can moreover shed light on how language learners acquire distributionally constrained items in general.
3 The experiment
3.1 Method
An elicited imitation task was carried out to investigate children’s knowledge of the superweak NPI shenme in Mandarin. An elicited imitation task is a research method that is often employed in different linguistic domains to assess acquisition by children below the age of six, such as (morpho-)syntax and semantics (Carrow 1974; Montgomery et al. 1978; Scholl & Ryan 1980; Keller-Cohen 1981; Fujiki & Brinton 1987; Lust et al. 1996; Panitsa 2001; among others). Van der Wal (1996), one of the first studies to address the learnability of NPIs, also employed the elicited imitation task. I therefore followed van der Wal (1996) in using this experimental method.3
In an elicited imitation task, children are required to listen carefully to pre-recorded stimuli first, and then to repeat the stimuli as precisely as they can (Lust et al. 1996; Vinther 2002; Eisenbeiss 2010; among others). When repeating a stimulus, children are claimed to make use of the grammatical rules they have established so far to reconstruct their own mental representation of the stimulus before “repeating” it (Chomsky 1964; Scholl & Ryan 1980; Keenan & Hawkins 1987; Panitsa 2001; Eisenbeiss 2010). If a stimulus is in agreement with the children’s own grammar, they repeat the stimulus immediately after hearing it (Scholl & Ryan 1980); if, on the other hand, a stimulus is not compatible with their grasp of the grammar of the target language, they correct it in accordance with their own grammatical system, give an irrelevant response such as I don’t know, or do not give a response at all (Keeney & Wolfe 1972; Brown 1973; Panitsa 2001; Vinther 2002). In the current research, this means that children only provide an imitation response if the appearance of shenme in the manipulated context of a stimulus is in agreement with the analysis of shenme that they have established thus far.
As an elicited imitation task requires children to repeat pre-recorded stimuli, working memory turns out to be of crucial importance in explaining their imitation performance (Hamayan et al. 1977; Montgomery et al. 1978; Gallimore & Tharp 1981; Fujiki & Brinton 1983; Lust et al. 1996; Eisenbeiss 2010; among others). Therefore, the length of stimuli needs to be controlled, in order to avoid children giving a repetition response from memory alone, without first establishing their own mental representation of a stimulus (e.g. Montgomery et al. 1978). Stimuli have to be sufficiently long to override children’s memory capacity, but short enough for comprehension, because children must be able to reconstruct their own mental representations of the stimuli without omitting too many words.
As suggested by Montgomery et al. (1978), for instance, stimuli containing six to seven words are short and thus easy for children between four and six years old, whereas those containing nine to ten words are of a medium length and are more difficult for children of the same age range, and stimuli containing twelve to thirteen words are of a maximum length. The current experiment did not opt to use the maximum length of twelve to thirteen words, because otherwise the stimuli would be too difficult for the three-year-olds to comprehend, reconstruct, and produce. To decide between using either the short or the medium length, two pilot experiments were carried out. Results of the two pilot studies (3; 01 – 4; 11, N = 19) showed that the short length of six to seven words was too easy for both the three- and four-year-olds, as they were able to repeat literally every single word of the stimuli, and sometimes even the intonation; whereas the children’s imitation performance was more target-like while confronted with stimuli containing nine to ten words. Therefore, the stimuli length, in terms of words, was set at ten. In order to compare the imitation performance by participants of different ages, the stimuli length was kept equal for all participants. However, under the assumption that working memory increases with age, this may mean that the length of ten words is just too short to override older participants’ working memory capacity, yielding better imitation performance by older participants when confronted with ungrammatical stimuli.
3.2 Design
The experiment manipulated five kinds of nonveridical contexts as licensing conditions for shenme, to examine the range of children’s knowledge of the licensing of the NPI. These contexts are (i) negative contexts introduced by sentential negation, (ii) conditional clauses, (iii) epistemic uncertainty contexts introduced by modal adverbs such as keneng ‘probably’, (iv) polar questions, and (v) wh-questions. To investigate whether children are aware of shenme’s distributional constraint that it cannot survive in veridical contexts, the experiment also included an unlicensed test condition by placing shenme in the perfect tense.
Each of the above-mentioned (un)licensed condition contained four items. This led to 24 test stimuli in total. Additionally, to neutralise the effect that every test stimulus involved the same word shenme, 18 fillers were added, of which four contained a word order error caused by a post-positioned restriction of the universal quantifier dou ‘all’.4 An overview of the current experimental design is given in Appendix C. Examples of each test and filler condition are provided in Appendix D.
As mentioned earlier, all test and filler stimuli were controlled for the same length of ten words. Crucially, all the manipulated licensing structures are systematically and/or frequently attested in spontaneous speech data of Mandarin three-year-olds (see Appendix B).5 This means that Mandarin three-year-olds have no difficulties using various licensing structures without shenme in their spontaneous speech, which strongly suggests that Mandarin children have already acquired the manipulated licensing structures at age three, at least. This will exclude the lack of knowledge of diverse sentence structures involved in the experiment as an explanation for possible poor imitation performance. Nonetheless, one may still question to what extent participants’ imitation performance may be influenced by different structural complexities involved in different test conditions. Following Montgomery et al. (1978), I assume that structural complexity is far less important than sentence length when explaining children’s imitation performance in elicited imitation tasks.
To keep participants concentrated and interested in the experiment, visual support was employed by presenting them with a picture of familiar cartoon figures on a laptop screen before each stimulus. All stimuli were developed after selecting or designing the pictures, with the hope of ensuring that each picture supported the corresponding stimulus as much as possible. Participants first saw a picture on a laptop screen, immediately after which they heard a corresponding audio stimulus. The experiment lasted an average of fifteen minutes per participant.
3.3 Participants and procedure
A total of 88 monolingual children participated in the current experiment (2; 11 – 4; 09; M = 3; 11; SD = 0; 6; 44 girls).6 They were recruited via two kindergartens in the Liaoning province, which is a Mandarin-speaking area in China. The experiment was conducted individually and took place in a quiet (class)room in the kindergartens.
Two experimenters were present during the experiment. One experimenter first invited the child from a class for a game. She then introduced the four figures in the experiment, and explained how the game would proceed and what the child was expected to do. Each child was presented with four trials to get familiar with both the experimenter and the experiment. When the child proved to be able to understand what was expected of it after the trials, the experiment started. The other experimenter recorded the responses and filled in answer sheets.
3.4 Data categorisation and scoring
Responses to the stimuli were divided into two main categories: imitation and non-imitation. In principle, imitation responses refer to instances in which the participants repeated the manipulated stimuli. However, since the length of the stimuli was designed so that the participants needed to first establish their own mental representations of the stimuli, it was hardly ever the case that they were able to repeat every word unit in a stimulus. Therefore, responses were considered imitation responses when participants produced a manipulated shenme noun phrase (e.g. shenme dangao ‘a cake’ or shenme wanju ‘a toy’), in a manipulated licensing condition (e.g. in polar questions).
Based on these criteria, both (12b) and (12c) were categorised as instances of imitation of the stimulus (12a). Although both (12b) and (12c) did not contain all lexical units employed in the stimulus, both responses do contain the manipulated shenme noun phrase (namely shenme gushi shu ‘a storybook’) in the manipulated licensing condition, which is an epistemic uncertainty context, introduced by the modal adverb keneng ‘probably’.
- (12)
- a.
- Tiaotiaohu
- Tiger
- he
- with
- Weinixiong
- Winnie the Pooh
- keneng
- probably
- zhengzai
- PROG
- kan
- read
- shenme
- shenme
- gushi
- story
- shu.
- book
- ‘Tiger and Winnie the Pooh are probably reading a storybook.’
- b.
- Tiaotiaohu
- Tiger
- keneng
- probably
- zai
- PROG
- kan
- read
- shenme
- shenme
- gushi
- story
- shu.
- book
- ‘Tiger is probably reading a storybook.’
- c.
- Tiaotiaohu
- Tiger
- Weinixiong
- Winnie the Pooh
- keneng
- probably
- kan
- read
- shenme
- shenme
- gushi
- story
- shu.
- book
- ‘Tiger, Winnie the Pooh probably read a storybook.’
Other responses were regarded as non-imitation. If the participants did not give a response at all, or provided an irrelevant response such as Mei ting jian ‘(I’ve) not heard (the stimulus)’ or Bu zhidao ‘(I’ve) no idea’, an instance of non-imitation was counted. If the participants reconstructed a stimulus and gave an own version of it, by replacing the manipulated shenme noun phrase by its bare or plain counterpart, for example, an instance of non-imitation was counted as well. This is illustrated in (13) as response to (12a).7
- (13)
- Tiaotiaohu
- Tiger
- he
- with
- Weinixiong
- Winnie the Pooh
- keneng
- probably
- zhengzai
- PROG
- kan
- read
- (yi-ge)
- (one-CL)
- gushi
- story
- shu.
- book
- ‘Tiger, Winnie the Pooh probably read a storybook.’
To be able to perform logistic regression analyses, each imitation response was assigned a value of 1, and each non-imitation response was assigned a value of 0. More on the regression models will be reported in the next section.
4 Results and interpretation
In order to assess children’s knowledge of the licensing of shenme at different ages, I performed mixed-effect logistic regression analyses in R, based on the raw imitation scores. To model the development of the participants’ knowledge underlying shenme’s appearance in different kinds of (non)veridical contexts, a regression analysis was performed for each of the six manipulated test conditions. The ages of the participants were modelled as a fixed factor, and individual participants and test items were modelled as two random factors. These three factors were combined to predict the participants’ imitation scores in the current experiment. This regression design, conducted on the cross-sectional data, made it possible to generalise over the development of children’s knowledge of the NPI shenme in different (non)veridical contexts.
The results of the regression analyses are presented in Figure 1 (see Appendix E for model summaries). The x-axis represents the ages of participants, whereas the y-axis indicates the imitation probabilities predicted by the regression models. The interpolation lines demonstrate the mean values of the predicted probabilities.
Two developmental patterns can be distinguished based on whether a significant age effect is attested in the participants’ imitation performance. One pattern concerns the test condition of wh-questions, which displays a fairly flat interpolation line. On average, the participants are predicted to show a repetition probability of 0.91 (SD = 0.03) throughout the whole investigated age range from 2; 11 to 4; 09. No significant difference between the imitation performances of the participants of different ages is attested (cf. Appendix E: I). Given the rationale behind an elicited imitation task (cf. Subsection 3.1), the pattern attested for the condition of wh-questions strongly suggest that Mandarin speaking children have acquired the knowledge that shenme can appear as a wh-word in wh-interrogatives already before age three (see Fan Li 2012 and Lin Jing et al. 2014 for similar findings).
Compared to the wh-question condition, the other test conditions clearly display a different pattern. Instead of a fairly flat interpolation line, the other test conditions all turn out to exhibit a rising interpolation line. Moreover, a significant age effect is attested in each of these non-wh test conditions (cf. Appendix E: II to VI): the participants are predicted to be able to repeat the relevant stimuli significantly more often when they are older. Since the manipulated (non)veridical contexts turn out to be frequently and systematically attested already with Mandarin speaking three-year-olds (cf. Subsection 3.2; see also Appendix B), the significant improvement in the participant’s imitation performance does not seem to be a consequence of an increase in the participants’ vocabulary or syntactic knowledge required for the manipulated non-wh test conditions. Therefore, it is assumed that the significant increase in the five non-wh conditions indicates a significant change in the participant’s underlying knowledge of shenme. That is, the participants are developing their knowledge of shenme, which allows the NPI in various non-wh environments in addition to wh-interrogatives.
The assumption made above leads to an expectation that the younger participants, i.e. those aged between 2; 11 and 3; 06, exhibit fairly poor imitation performance in the non-wh test conditions – as they are assumed to be just starting to develop the relevant knowledge. But this is not what the regression models predict. When confronted with shenme appearing in polar questions, conditional clauses, epistemic uncertainty contexts, and the perfect tense, these participants are predicted to repeat the relevant stimuli between 11% and 32% of the time; and in the test condition of negative contexts, they are even predicted to give repetition responses 48% of the time. The relevant results are given in Table 1.
Experimental conditions | Predicted imitation probabilities | |
---|---|---|
Mean | SD | |
Negative contexts | 0.48 | 0.25 |
Polar questions | 0.32 | 0.18 |
Conditional clauses | 0.25 | 0.18 |
Epistemic uncertainty contexts | 0.11 | 0.14 |
Perfect tense | 0.11 | 0.07 |
The imitation performance of the younger children in the test conditions of polar questions, conditional clauses, epistemic uncertainty contexts, and perfect tense may be explained by some memory effect, which seems to be at play in elicited imitation tasks in general (cf. Subsection 3.1). Yet, their imitation probability of 0.48 in the negative condition does not seem to suggest some working memory effect only. If we look at the standard deviations (SD) of the results in the table above, it turns out that the condition of negative contexts has the largest SD. This indicates larger individual differences in this test condition compared to the other non-wh test conditions. This may lead to the assumption that some of the younger participants have already acquired the knowledge underlying shenme’s appearance in the scope of sentential negation. This assumption seems to be supported by the individual results: 16 out of the 26 younger participants exhibit an imitation probability of at least 0.52, of which nine show an imitation probability of 0.71 or even higher.
If from age 2; 11, the participants start developing their knowledge underlying shenme’s appearance in a wider range of semantic environments than merely wh-questions, at what age have they acquired the relevant knowledge? A closer look at the regression results shows that the participants above age 4; 06 (N = 9) exhibit a predicted imitation probability of at least 0.70 in three out of the five manipulated non-wh environments, specifically the test conditions of negative contexts, conditional clauses, and polar questions (see Table 2 for the relevant data). Thus, it can be assumed that the participants have acquired the knowledge that shenme can also appear in various non-wh contexts around age 4; 06.
Experimental conditions | Predicted imitation probabilities | |
---|---|---|
Mean | SD | |
Negative contexts | 0.88 | 0.11 |
Conditional clauses | 0.81 | 0.16 |
Polar questions | 0.70 | 0.17 |
Epistemic uncertainty contexts | 0.44 | 0.24 |
Perfect tense | 0.31 | 0.17 |
However, the assumption that the participants have already acquired the knowledge underlying shenme’s occurrence in different kinds of non-wh contexts around age 4; 06, gives rise to two further questions. Since epistemic uncertainty contexts belong to the same semantic category as negative contexts, conditional clauses, and polar questions (they are all non-wh nonveridical), why are the older participants predicted to give repetition responses to the relevant stimuli merely 44% of the time? The most straightforward way to understand this is to assume that the older participants have not yet acquired the lexical knowledge required in the corresponding test conditions. However, as will be shown in the next section, such a vocabulary-based account does not seem to be on the right track; instead, an explanation based on a methodological shortcoming of the experiment will be suggested.
Another question concerns the older participants’ imitation performance when confronted with shenme in the perfect tense. From the perspective of adult speakers, shenme’s occurrence in the perfect tense is ungrammatical (cf. Section 1 and 2). The older participants’ imitation probability of 0.31 in this condition is therefore unexpected. They seem to have undergone a development away from adult-likeness, which leads to overuse of shenme in non-licensing environments. Are the older participants then unable to detect shenme’s distributional constraint? I argue that there is no development away from adult-likeness. The improvement in the participants’ imitation performance in the perfect tense condition could be a consequence of their increasing working memory capacity, as I will discuss in the next section.
To summarise, the results obtained in the experiment suggest a learning process, which can be described as follows. As early as age 2; 11, children have already acquired the knowledge that shenme can appear in wh-interrogatives. After age 2; 11, children start developing their knowledge of shenme, which allows it to appear in a number of non-wh nonveridical contexts as well. Around age 4; 06, children have developed the knowledge underlying shenme’s appearance in various nonveridical environments, including wh-interrogatives. The development hypothesised here leads to further questions. What is children’s initial knowledge of shenme, and where does this knowledge come from? What does children’s knowledge consist of after age 4; 06, and what is the development between 2; 11 and 4; 06, which may give rise to this knowledge? All these questions will be addressed in the next section. The older participants’ imitation performance with the epistemic uncertainty stimuli and the perfect tense stimuli will be discussed as well.
5 Discussion
5.1 Shenme is a mere wh-quantifier before 2; 11
Mandarin children acquire the knowledge underlying shenme’s occurrence in wh-interrogatives as early as age 2; 11. Following the previous corpus investigation by Lin Jing et al. (2014), I assume that before this age, children analyse shenme as a wh-quantifier. Since the data presented in Section 4 suggest that children start developing their knowledge underlying shenme’s occurrence in non-wh nonveridical environments after age 2; 11, I moreover assume – in line with Lin Jing et al. – that children’s initial knowledge of shenme only contains the wh-analysis. The data presented in Section 4 suggest that children start developing their knowledge underlying shenme’s occurrence in non-wh nonveridical environments after age 2; 11. But where does this analysis come from?
In order to answer this question, a distribution-based learning approach is adopted, which was originally proposed for category learning in early language acquisition (Cartwright & Brent 1997; Redington et al. 1998; Mintz 2002; Mintz et al. 2002). Following this approach, I assume that children’s first attempt to analyse the superweak NPI shenme relies merely on their investigation of the distributional properties of input data they received and processed thus far. As reported in Lin Jing et al. (2014), shenme is attested in wh-questions in more than 97% of the input. Given its overwhelming occurrence as a question word in the input, it is far from surprising that Mandarin children initially analyse shenme as a mere wh-quantifier and do so before age 2; 11.
5.2 Shenme is a referentially deficient quantifier after 4; 06
As suggested in Section 4, around age 4; 06 Mandarin children seem to have acquired the knowledge underlying shenme’s occurrence in a wider range of nonveridical environments than wh-interrogatives only. What would this knowledge consist of? Two approaches may be possible in this respect. One approach is to assume that the child’s knowledge of shenme after age 4; 06 consists of multiple analyses, which are established via distribution-based learning, as is assumed for the development of the initial knowledge of shenme. In particular, this would mean that children have a wh-analysis for shenme’s occurrence in wh-interrogatives, a “negative” analysis for its occurrence in the scope of sentential negation, a “conditional” analysis for its appearance in conditional clauses, etc. Another approach is to assume that the child’s knowledge of shenme after age 4; 06 contains just one generalising analysis (cf. Lin Jing et al. 2014), that is, shenme is a non-referential quantifier in late child Mandarin, which is restricted to the whole array of nonveridical environments, covering all those contexts mentioned above. The two possible approaches to the child’s knowledge of shenme after age 4; 06 can be represented in Figure 2.
The multiple analyses approach has two advantages. First, the initial analysis of shenme as a mere wh-word is entirely maintainable. Children do not need to undergo any reanalysis process, but only add additional analyses explaining shenme’s appearance in more types of semantic contexts, such as conditional clauses or polar questions. Second, the multiple analyses approach does not require Mandarin children to acquire the semantic knowledge of (non)veridicality, or shenme’s referential deficiency. What children need to acquire merely involves superficial occurrences of shenme in a variety of semantic configurations. They do not have to detect the common semantic property underlying the different licensing conditions for shenme; nor do they have to unravel the reason why shenme is subject to limited distribution in certain but not all semantic environments.
But this approach is confronted with two challenges. First, how can new, specific analyses be established? In the child-directed speech, shenme is attested in conditional clauses or polar questions only 0.3% of the time, and 0.4% of the time in epistemic uncertainty contexts.8 Given the extremely small amounts of input containing shenme licensed in various semantic configurations that are not wh-questions, it is questionable that Mandarin children receive sufficient input to be able to establish the corresponding analysis in a distribution-based learning model.
A second problem concerns generalisability. As the multiple analyses approach basically assumes that the child’s knowledge of shenme after age 4; 06 contains specific analyses, each of which only explains shenme’s occurrence in one particular type of nonveridical context, it would be a coincidence to observe a distributional pattern of the NPI in all kinds of nonveridical environments in adult Mandarin Chinese (cf. Xie Zhi-Guo 2007; Lin Jing et al. 2014; see also Section 2). Moreover, this approach does not entail that all speakers acquire the full set of possible licensing conditions for shenme, and the distributional patterns of the NPI by individual speakers are expected to influence acquisition. Since the child is assumed to establish each specific analysis based on input evidence only (e.g. if a child does not hear shenme in conditional clauses, he or she will not establish the corresponding analysis), and does not require any insight into the underlying semantic property of the corresponding context, the multiple analyses approach predicts the acquisition of shenme to be successive, individually distinct, and dependant on the distribution in the input. This implies the existence of variation among adult Mandarin speakers with respect to the set of possible licensing conditions for shenme.
However, this does not seem to challenge the single analysis approach. In this approach, shenme is treated as a non-referential quantifier in late child Mandarin. This non-referential analysis generates a distribution of superweak NPIs restricted to nonveridical contexts only, as is observed in adult language use (see again Section 2). The single analysis approach hypothesised as such relates shenme’s limited distribution in nonveridical environments to its non-referentiality, and therefore does not easily allow individual variation. In this scenario, the fact that shenme is restricted to a unified set of nonveridical contexts in adult Mandarin is not attributed to coincidence either. Therefore, I adopt the single analysis approach because of its generalisability. Under this approach, shenme is analysed as a referentially deficient quantifier. But how do Mandarin children develop this non-referential analysis of shenme from their initial assumption that shenme is a mere wh-quantifier? What is the contribution of language input, children’s nonveridical vocabulary, etc., in this respect?
5.3 Between 2; 11 and 4; 06: From a wh- to a referentially deficient quantifier
The development of children’s knowledge of shenme as hypothesised above can be schematically presented in Figure 3. Before age 2; 11 children initially analyse shenme as a mere wh-quantifier, whereas after age 4; 06 they reanalyse shenme as a referentially deficient quantifier. This subsection will explore a possible reanalysis pathway, which may give rise to the establishment of the non-referential analysis of shenme around age 4; 06.
As discussed above, children’s initial assumption of shenme as a mere wh-word is triggered by the overwhelming occurrence of the NPI in wh-questions in the input, i.e. more than 97% of the time (see also Appendix A). Let us assume that when a child utters or hears shenme in a wh-question, he or she has the same semantic analysis of the question quantifier involved as their parents. Otherwise, how could the communication between parents and children proceed or be successful? Thus, when a child asks Mama chi le shenme shuiguo ne? ‘What kind of fruit did mama eat?’, for example, he or she is assumed to analyse shenme as containing a dependent variable. This means that the child has acquired the knowledge that shenme cannot be assigned a fixed value in the discourse, unlike free variables (Giannakidou 2011; Giannakidou & Quer 2013); instead, it introduces a set of possible edible things that the mother has probably eaten (cf. Hamblin 1973). This means that once children have established the wh-analysis of shenme, they also have access to the knowledge that shenme contains a dependent variable, and hence is referentially deficient.
In fact, the presence of a dependent variable not only generates a distribution of shenme in wh-questions; it also gives rise to its distribution in all kinds of nonveridical environments, e.g. the complement clause of non-factive verbs, polar questions, and conditional clauses. This is because nonveridical contexts (both wh- and non-wh ones) do not necessarily require the existence of a discourse referent, and hence sanction a lexical item that contains a dependent variable (cf. Giannakidou 2011; see also Section 2). The awareness of the presence of a dependent variable in shenme then becomes a sufficient condition for children to extend shenme’s distribution to the whole array of nonveridical environments. Thus, it is possible that children come up with an updated assumption that shenme is subject to a distributional pattern in all kinds of nonveridical contexts – including wh-interrogatives – due to its non-referentiality. This assumption, however, requires support from the language input.
As reported earlier (see also Appendix A), more than 97% of the input contains shenme’s occurrence in wh-interrogatives, and in the remaining input data shenme is attested in a number of non-wh nonveridical contexts, such as epistemic uncertainty contexts (0.3%), imperfectives (0.3%), polar questions (0.4%), etc. Although the input in which shenme appears in non-wh nonveridical contexts amounts to only 2.3%, it does support the assumption that shenme is subject to a distributional pattern in various nonveridical contexts (and thus not merely in wh-questions) due to the presence of a dependent variable. This leads children to reanalyse shenme as a referentially deficient quantifier, which is restricted by nonveridicality.
What is hypothesised above provides a possible explanation of how Mandarin children reach this generalisation, by means of reanalysis from their initial narrow assumption that shenme is a mere wh-word. In the reanalysis process as sketched above, language input seems to play an important role. Moreover, two kinds of semantic knowledge appear to be crucial as well.
First, before establishing the non-referential reanalysis, children are required to have acquired the knowledge hat shenme contains a dependent variable that cannot introduce a discourse referent. Without the acquisition of the presence of a dependent variable in shenme, children would not be able to come to the assumption that shenme may be subject to a distributional pattern in the whole array of nonveridical environments, as only dependent variables can be restricted by nonveridicality due to non-referentiality (cf. Section 2). As assumed above, children seem to have acquired the knowledge of the presence of a dependent variable in shenme when they are able to exchange wh-questions containing shenme with, for instance, their parents; but this requires further investigation.
Second, children need to have acquired nonveridicality before they can obtain any insight into the interplay between nonveridicality and non-referentiality to establish the reanalysis of shenme. However, little research has been reported on the acquisition of (non)veridicality. Nonetheless, given that nonveridicality is defined in relation to a set of worlds epistemically accessible to the speaker (cf. Giannakidou 2011; see also Giannakidou & Quer 2013), it can be assumed that nonveridicality represents the possibility of talking about different possible worlds, including the actual one. Thus, the development of Theory of Mind (ToM) may be argued to be relevant to children’s knowledge on (non)veridicality. There is evidence, for instance, for the acquisition of the basis of ToM as early as age three, such as the difference between know (veridical knowledge) and plan (nonveridical intension), as well as the difference between explanation for veridical past and prediction for nonveridical future (Wellman & Estes 1986; Wellman & Woolley 1990; Leekam 1993; among others). Such findings from the development of ToM suggest that three-year-olds may already be able to distinguish nonveridical contexts from veridical ones, as they know that only nonveridical contexts do not entail the truth of an embedded proposition. The acquisition of (non)veridicality goes beyond the scope of this paper, and is therefore left for future exploration.
The hypothesised reanalysis process indicates that Mandarin children acquire the superweak NPI shenme via a wh-analysis. The transition from a wh-quantifier to a referentially deficient quantifier in acquisition is in line with Giannakidou’s treatment of superweak NPIs (1998; 2002; 2010; 2011), which explains NPI-hood by referential deficiency – a consequence of the presence of a dependent variable. The reanalysis process of shenme can therefore be considered a modifying process that is based on input evidence within the same category of lexical deficient quantifiers, in particular, from wh- to non-referential quantifiers.
5.4 Poor imitation performance with epistemic uncertainty stimuli after 4; 06
As discussed above, after age 4; 06, Mandarin children have developed the non-referential analysis of shenme, which generalises its appearance to various nonveridical environments, including wh-questions. The question now arises as to why the reanalysis does not allow the older participants (i.e. those above age 4; 06; N = 9) to repeat shenme in epistemic uncertainty contexts – a kind of nonveridical context – as often as in the other non-wh nonveridical contexts manipulated in the experiment (see again Section 4). Before presenting possible explanations for the older children’s poor imitation performance with the epistemic uncertainty stimuli, let us first look at what these older participants do when they do not give an imitation response to the epistemic uncertainty stimuli. An overview of relevant data is presented in Table 3.
Type of responses | Count (%) | |
---|---|---|
Imitation | 15 (41.7%) | |
Non-imitation | change past perfect to progressive | 10 (27.8%) |
change the stimuli into wh-questions | 7 (19.4%) | |
remove shenme from responses | 3 (2.2%) | |
no responses | 1 (1.7%) | |
Total | 36 |
The frequency data presented in Table 3 show that the older participants, when they do not give imitation responses, mainly employ two kinds of strategies to reconstruct the manipulated stimuli containing shenme appearing in epistemic uncertainty contexts. These strategies are: changing the aspect of the stimuli from past perfect to progressive (47.6% of the time; 10 out of 21), or changing the stimuli into wh-questions by, for instance, adding a Q-marker (33.3% of the time; 7 out of 21). An example of the epistemic uncertainty stimuli is given in (14); and examples of children’s responses to stimuli such as (14), in which these two strategies are employed, are given in (15a) and (15b), respectively.
- (14)
- Tiaotiaohu
- Tiger
- he
- with
- Weinixiong
- Winnie the Pooh
- keneng
- possibly
- zhengzai
- PROG
- kan
- read
- shenme
- shenme
- gushi
- story
- shu.
- book
- ‘Tiger and Winnie the Pooh are possibly reading a storybook.’
- (15)
- a.
- Tiaotiaohu
- Tiger
- he
- with
- Weinixiong
- Winnie the Pooh
- zhengzai
- PROG
- kan
- read
- shenme
- shenme
- gushi
- story
- shu.
- book
- ‘Tiger and Winnie the Pooh are reading a storybook.’
- b.
- Tiaotiaohu
- Tiger
- he
- with
- Weinixiong
- Winnie
- keneng
- the Pooh
- zhengzai
- possibly PROG
- kan
- read
- shenme
- shenme
- gushi
- story
- shu
- book
- ne?
- Q MARKER
- ‘What kind of storybook are Tiger and Winnie the Pooh possibly reading?’
The two types of reconstruction strategies suggest that the participants’ knowledge of shenme at older ages does not seem to allow it in the scope of epistemic modal adverbs such as haoxiang ‘probably’, or keneng ‘possibly’. The most straightforward way to understand this is to assume that the older participants have not yet acquired the lexical knowledge required in the corresponding test conditions. If they do not know how to linguistically express epistemic uncertainty, namely if they have not yet acquired how to say e.g. probably in Mandarin Chinese, it logically follows that they would not be able to repeat the stimuli containing shenme licenced by such epistemic modal operators. As mentioned in Subsection 3.2 (see also Appendix B), however, Mandarin three-year-olds are already able to use epistemic modal adverbs frequently and systematically in their spontaneous speech. Thus, the vocabulary-based explanation does not seem to be on the right track.
Another possible explanation is that the experiment contained a discrepancy between the manipulated stimuli and the corresponding visual support in terms of epistemic (un)certainty. Take again (14) as an example. Before hearing this stimulus, which conveys an epistemic uncertainty activity, the participants were presented a picture on a laptop screen in which Tiger and Winnie the Pooh are reading a storybook, which visually represents a factual event. Thus, the visual support did not in fact support the epistemic uncertainty stimuli.9 This may have resulted in the older participants’ poor imitation performance in the relevant test condition.10
5.5 Unable to detect shenme’s distributional constraint?
Finally, let us look at the older participants’ imitation performance when confronted with shenme in the perfect tense. The question that arose from the interpretation of the regression results (i.e. in Section 4) is whether the participants are unable to detect the distributional constraint of shenme. Not being able to detect this constraint would account for the increase in imitation probabilities in the perfect tense condition predicted for the older participants. By discussing the production data obtained from the four-year-olds, I will argue in this subsection that their imitation performance in the perfect tense condition should be explained as a consequence of their increased working memory capacity.
As mentioned in Subsection 3.1, the choice of the same stimuli length for all participants, independent of their ages, may result in better imitation performance by the older participants – under the assumption that children’s working memory increases with their age. Yet, the current experiment did not contain an objective measurement of the participants’ working memory capacity. This makes it difficult to examine to what extent this capacity may have influenced their imitation performance. However, when looking at the production data from the four-year-olds (N = 45), there seems to be indirect evidence that there is an effect of expanding working memory capacity. It concerns an asymmetry between the (un)grammaticality of these participants’ responses to the grammatical and the ungrammatical stimuli. The relevant data are given in Table 4.
Grammatical stimuli | Ungrammatical stimuli | |
---|---|---|
Grammatical response | 854 (94.9%) | 103 (57.2%) |
Ungrammatical response | 18 (2%) | 65 (36.1%) |
No response | 13 (1.4%) | 6 (3.3%) |
Incomplete response | 15 (1.7%) | 6 (3.3%) |
Total | 900 | 180 |
When the four-year-olds are confronted with the ungrammatical stimuli containing shenme in the perfect tense, two response types are most frequent. On the one hand, ungrammatical responses (36.1%; 65 out of 180) signal imitation performance on the ungrammatical stimuli. On the other, grammatical responses, in which children correct the ungrammatical stimuli (57.2%; 103 out of 180), signal underlying knowledge of shenme’s possible contexts. This pattern differs strongly from what we can observe with grammatical stimuli: in response to grammatical utterances, children almost always give grammatical responses (94.9%; 854 out of 900). This significant asymmetry leads to the generalisation that the children only overuse shenme in non-licensing conditions if the stimuli are themselves ungrammatical (χ2 (3, N = 1080) = 256.308, p = .000). This asymmetry suggests that shenme’s appearance in veridical contexts such as the perfect tense is not in agreement with the older participants’ knowledge of shenme; otherwise, they would also systematically produce shenme in non-licensing environments in their responses to the grammatical stimuli. This excludes the possibility that Mandarin children are unable to detect shenme’s distributional constraint.
Further evidence for the ungrammaticality of shenme appearing in the perfect tense in late child Mandarin involves the strategies that the four-year-olds employ to correct ungrammatical stimuli. Among the 103 non-imitation responses to the ungrammatical stimuli (namely the grammatical responses to the stimuli in the unlicensed test condition in Table 4), three main correction strategies are distinguished: substituting shenme by its bare or plain counterpart (i.e. 72.8%; 75 out of 103), changing the ungrammatical stimuli into an epistemic uncertainty context by adding a modal adverb like haoxiang ‘probably’ (i.e. 8.7%; 9 out of 103), and transforming the ungrammatical stimuli into a wh-question, for instance by adding a Q-marker (i.e. 10.7%; 11 out of 103). These strategies demonstrate that the four-year-olds are aware of shenme’s distributional constraint, since they either remove shenme from perfect tenses or make the veridical contexts nonveridical.
It is important to note that the CHILDES data reported in Lin Jing et al. (2014; see also Section 2) already reveal that monolingual Mandarin children do not overgeneralise shenme to veridical contexts in their spontaneous speech. The two kinds of production data – obtained from both experimental and corpus research – converge: they both show that children are able to acquire the restricted distribution of shenme in the target language.
The explanation based on working memory capacity, however, gives rise to a crucial question for understanding the significant improvement in the participants’ imitation performance in the four non-wh test conditions. To what extent does it represent a development in the participants’ underlying knowledge of shenme, rather than merely reflecting their increased working memory capacity? Here, I adopt Eisenbeiss (2010) and argue that, although working memory capacity is one of the factors that can affect children’s performance in an elicited imitation task, it cannot explain the differences between different test conditions observed for the same participants. The effects of working memory should be similar for the same participant, independent of test conditions. This means that, if only working memory is at play in participants’ imitation performance, no significant differences should be found across different test conditions. However, results of a repeated measure ANOVA confirm that this is not the case, as a significant within-subject effect is attested for the four-year-olds (F(5, 1074) = 47.882, p = .000). Thus, working memory is not the only factor that underlies the participants’ good imitation performance in different test conditions at older ages.
6 Conclusions
By analysing the imitation performance of 88 monolingual Mandarin children (2; 11 – 4; 09; M = 3; 11; SD = 0; 6; 44 girls) in an elicited imitation task, I examined the learnability of the superweak NPI shenme in Mandarin Chinese, which is only allowed to appear in nonveridical contexts, including wh-questions. Following a previous corpus investigation of shenme’s learnability by Lin Jing et al. (2014), I argued for an acquisition pathway in which Mandarin children initially analyse shenme as a mere wh-quantifier and reanalyse it as a referentially deficient quantifier later on. The mere wh-analysis generates shenme’s occurrence in wh-questions only, whereas the non-referential analysis gives rise to shenme’s distribution as a superweak NPI in the whole array of nonveridical contexts – including wh-questions. When is the reanalysis of shenme established? Based on their corpus data, Lin Jing et al. argue that this takes place shortly after the age of four; the regression results reported in this paper, however, seemed to suggest that the reanalysis of shenme is developed around age 4; 06. As for how the reanalysis of shenme is established, I hypothesised the following. By first analysing shenme as a mere wh-word, which is triggered by massive occurrence of shenme in wh-questions in the input, Mandarin children are able to establish that shenme contains a dependent variable. The knowledge of the presence of a dependent variable in shenme, in combination with input data that features shenme in non-wh but nonveridical contexts, enables Mandarin children to acquire the non-referentiality of shenme later on.
The learning path proposed in this paper leads to the conclusion that in the absence of negative evidence, such as corrective feedback or explicit instructions on NPIs’ ungrammaticality in non-licensing conditions, children are able to detect their distributional constraints. Their solution to the learnability problem of NPIs such as shenme, then, is to employ a widening learning strategy in which they start with a strict assumption or analysis and weaken it to a less strict and generalising one at a later stage in acquisition (cf. Manzini & Wexler 1987; Snyder 2008).
Additional Files
The additional files for this article can be found as follows:
Abbreviations
ADJ = adjectiviser, CL = classifier, GEN = genitive marker, OV = object-verb, PERF = perfect tense marker, PL = plural marker, PROG = progressive marker, Q MARKER = question marker, REL = relative clause marker, VO = verb-object
Notes
- Downward entailing contexts are defined based on their logico-semantic behaviour. For every arbitrary X, Y: if f (X ∪ Y) ⇒ f (X) and/or f (X ∪ Y) ⇒ f (Y), then the function f is downward entailing. This definition is adapted from van der Wouden (1997). Informally speaking, downward entailing contexts are those contexts in which the entailment relation goes from set to subset (see also Fauconnier 1975; 1978; 1980). [^]
- The strength of NPIs is categorised depending on the type of negative contexts in which it can and cannot be licensed (Zwarts 1986; 1995; 1998; Nam 1994; van der Wouden 1997; Hoeksema 2000). The nonveridicality theory of polarity licensing (cf. Giannakidou & Zwarts 1999) distinguishes four types of negative environments based on their logico-semantic behaviours: anti-morphic contexts, anti-additive contexts, downward entailing (DE) contexts and nonveridical contexts (see van der Wouden 1997 for the relevant definitions and examples). This gives rise to NPIs of four different strengths: superstrong NPIs restricted by anti-morphicity; strong NPIs licensed by anti-additivity; weak NPIs attested in DE-contexts only; and superweak NPIs requiring nonveridicality as sufficient licensing property (see Zwarts 1981; 1986; Nam 1994). [^]
- One of the anonymous reviewers suggests a grammaticality judgement task to approach children’s knowledge of the licensing of shenme. I did not opt for this method because children under age five are not able to give an explicit grammatical judgment on NPI-licensing, as reported by van der Wal (1996). [^]
- Mandarin dou ‘all’ is a universal quantifier that quantifies over a phrase or a clause that precedes it (Lee Hun-Tak 1986; Chiu Bonnie 1990; Cheng Lai-Shan 1995; Lin Jo-Wang 1998; Wu Jian-Xin 1999; Pan HaiHua 2006). This means that the restriction of this universal precedes rather than follows it, different from other universal quantifiers in Mandarin, like meige ‘every’, or their English or Dutch counterparts. Thus, a post-positioned restriction of dou gives rise to a violation of word order. [^]
- Data were collected in three Mandarin subcorpora in the CHILDES database (MacWhinney 2009): Beijing 2 (Tardif 1993; 1996), Zhou 1 and Zhou 2 (Zhou Jing 2004a; b). [^]
- The experiment has been approved by the Ethics Committee of the Amsterdam Institute of Humanities Research (AIHR, University of Amsterdam), with reference number of 2013–12. [^]
- Generally speaking, non-imitation responses in a well-designed elicited imitation task suggest that the child has not yet developed a grammar that is compatible with the manipulated stimuli (cf. Section 3.1). As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, a child might in theory still give responses like (13a) and (13b), which do not contain the target NPI shenme, although he or she has already established the grammar that allows shenme to appear in the corresponding licensing condition. Given the rationale of elicited imitation tasks, the question why the child would not give target-like responses like (12) then arises – if his or her grammar does generate shenme in that licensing context. My interpretation of such performance would be that the child does not prefer to use shenme in the corresponding context, or does not feel comfortable with such sentences containing shenme. I would take this as evidence that the child is not yet confident with the target-like analysis of the NPI, which could be newly developed by the child. [^]
- Relevant data are collected in the child-directed speech in three Mandarin corpora in the CHILDES database (MacWhinney 2009), namely Beijing 2 (Tardif 1993; 1996), Zhou 1, and Zhou 2 (Zhou Jing 2004a; b); see further Appendix A. [^]
- One of the anonymous reviewers points out that the hypothesised discrepancy may be present not only in the epistemic (un)certainty condition but also in other manipulated conditions. However, if this were the case, the discrepancy would result in poor repetition performance by the older participants’ in all the conditions in the experiment. But this is not what the results, as presented in Figure 1, seem to suggest. [^]
- The discrepancy between the visual support and the audio stimuli in terms of epistemic (un)certainty would bother the younger participants as well; however, since the younger children showed poor imitation performance in a number of non-wh nonveridical conditions (cf. Table 1 in Section 4), it is hard to pinpoint whether it is this discrepancy that explains their low repetition probabilities when confronted with the epistemic uncertainty stimuli. [^]
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Fred Weerman and Hedde Zeijlstra for their feedback during the preparations and revisions of the manuscript. I thank the anonymous reviewers for their useful comments, which helped to improve the article. I owe many thanks to Wei Liu, the director of Qiseguang Kindergarten in Dandong, China. Without her collaboration or the participation of Qiseguang, I would not have been able to collect all the data reported here. I want to say thank you to the little participants and their parents for their understanding and cooperation, and to Fang Fang and Feifei Sui for assistance during the data collection.
Competing Interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
References
Brown, Roger . (1973). A first language: The early stages. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.4159/harvard.9780674732469
Carrow, Elizabeth . (1974). A test using elicited imitations in assessing grammatical structure in children. Journal of Speech and Hearing Disorders 39 (4) : 437. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1044/jshd.3904.437
Cartwright, Timothy A.; Brent, Michael R. . (1997). Syntactic categorisation in early language acquisition: Formalizing the role of distributional analysis. Cognition 63 : 121. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(96)00793-7
Cheng, Lai-Shen . (1994). Wh-words as polarity items. Chinese Languages and Linguistics 2 : 615.
Cheng, Lai-Shen . (1995). On dou-quantification. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 4 : 197. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF01731509
Chiu, Bonnie . (1990). A case of quantifier floating in Mandarin Chinese. Paper presented at the second Northeast Conference on Chinese Linguistics (NECCL-2). Philadelphia University of Pennsylvania
Chomsky, Noam . (1964). Bellugi, Ursula, Brown, Roger Roger (eds.), Formal discussion. The acquisition of language: Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 29 (1) : 35. (Serial No 92).
Eisenbeiss, Sonja . (2010). Production methods in language acquisition research In: Blom, Elma, Unsworth, Sharon Sharon (eds.), Experimental methods. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 11.
Fan, Li . (2012). The interrogative and non-interrogative use of Mandarin wh-words in children at early age. TCSOL Studies 45 (1) : 85.
Fauconnier, Gilles . (1975). Pragmatic scales and logical structure. Linguistic inquiry 6 : 353.
Fauconnier, Gilles . (1978). Implication reversal in a natural language In: Guenthner, Franz, Schmidt, Siegfried J. Siegfried J. (eds.), Formal semantics and pragmatics for natural languages. Springer, pp. 289. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9775-2_10
Fauconnier, Gilles . (1980). Pragmatic entailment and questions In: Searle, John R., Kiefer, Ferenc; Ferenc and Bierwisch, Manfred Manfred (eds.), Speech act theory and pragmatics. Springer, pp. 57. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8964-1_3
Fujiki, Martin; Brinton, Bonnie . (1987). Elicited imitation revisited: A comparison with spontaneous language production. Language, Speech, and Hearing Services in Schools 18 : 301. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1044/0161-1461.1804.301
Gallimore, Ronald; Tharp, Roland G. . (1981). The interpretation of elicited sentence imitation in a standardized context. Language Learning 31 : 369. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-1770.1981.tb01390.x
Giannakidou, Anastasia . (1997). The landscape of polarity items. Groningen: University of Groningen.
Giannakidou, Anastasia . (1998). Polarity sensitivity as (non)veridical dependency. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1075/la.23
Giannakidou, Anastasia . (2002). Licensing and sensitivity in polarity items: From downward entailment to nonveridicality. Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS) 38 : 29.
Giannakidou, Anastasia . (2011). Negative polarity and positive polarity: Licensing, variation, and compositionality In: Maienborn, Claudia, von Heusinger, Klaus; Klaus and Portner, Paul Paul (eds.), The handbook of natural language meaning. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, pp. 1660.
Giannakidou, Anastasia; Zwarts, Frans . (1999). Temporal, aspectual operators and (non)veridicality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Giannakidou, Anastasia; Lin, Jing . (2016). The Mandarin NPI shenme is not exhaustive: A reply to Chierchia and Liao (2015). Ms.
Giannakidou, Anastasia; Quer, Josep . (2013). Exhaustive and non-exhaustive variation with anti-specific indefinites: Free choice and referential vagueness in Greek, Catalan, and Spanish. Lingua 16 : 120. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2012.12.005
Giannakidou, Anastasia . (). The myth of exhaustivity of all NPIs. Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS) 52 To appear.
Hamayan, Else; Saegert, Joel; Larudee, Paul . (1977). Elicited imitation in second language learners. Language and Speech 20 : 86.
Hamblin, Charles L. . (1973). Questions in Montague English. Foundations of Language 10 (1) : 41.
Haspelmath, Martin . (1997). Indefinite pronouns. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hoeksema, Jack . (2000). Negative polarity items: Triggering, scope and c-command In: Horn, Laurence R., Kato, Yasuhiko Yasuhiko (eds.), Negation and polarity: Syntactic and semantic perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 115.
Horn, Laurence R. . (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Huang, Ai-Jun . (2014). Acquisition of polarity-sensitive items in Mandarin Chinese. Language Acquisition 21 : 212. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10489223.2014.884573
Huang, Ai-Jun; Crain, Stephen . (2014). Polarity sensitive expressions in child Mandarin. Language Acquisition 21 : 339. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10489223.2014.884569
Huang, Cheng-Teh . (1982). Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar. dissertation. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Keenan, Edward L.; Hawkins, Sarah . (1987). The psychological validity of the accessibility hierarchy. Universal Grammar 15 : 60.
Keller-Cohen, Deborah . (1981). Elicited imitation in lexical development: Evidence from a study of temporal reference. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 10 (3) : 273. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF01067508
Kenney, Terrence J.; Wolfe, Jean . (1972). The acquisition of agreement in English. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 11 : 698. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0022-5371(72)80004-5
Koster, Charlotte; van der Wal, Sjoukje . (1996). Acquisition of negative polarity items In: Aldridge, Michelle (ed.), Child language. Clevedon, Avon: Multilingual Matters, Ltd., pp. 92.
Ladusaw, William . (1979). Negative polarity items as inherent scope relations. dissertation. Austin, TX: University of Texas at Austin.
Lee, Hun-Tak . (1986). Studies on quantification in Chinese. dissertation. California: University of California.
Leekam, Sue . (1993). Children’s understanding of mind In: Bennett, Mark (ed.), The development of social cognition: The child as psychologist. New York: Guilford Press, pp. 26.
Lin, Jing; Weerman, Fred; Zeijlstra, Hedde . (2014). Mandarin SHENME as a superweak NPI In: Hoeksema, Jack, Gilbers, Dicky Dicky (eds.), Black book: A festschrift in honor of Frans Zwarts. Groningen: University of Groningen, pp. 229.
Lin, Jing; Weerman, Fred; Zeijlstra, Hedde . (2015). Emerging NPIs: The acquisition of Dutch hoeven ‘need’. The Linguistic Review 32 (2) : 333. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/tlr-2014-0025
Lin, Jo-Wang . (1996). Polarity licensing and wh-phrase quantification in Chinese. dissertation. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts.
Lin, Jo-Wang . (1998). On existential polarity WH-phrases in Chinese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 7 : 219. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1008284513325
Li, Ye-Hui . (1992). Indefinite Wh in Mandarin Chinese. Journal of East Asian linguistics 1 : 125. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF00130234
Lust, Barbara; Flynn, Suzanne; Foley, Claire . (1996). What children know about what they say: Elicited imitation as a research method for assessing children’s syntax In: McDaniel, Dana, McKee, Cecile; Cecile and Cairns, Helen Smith Helen Smith (eds.), Methods for assessing children’s syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 55.
MacWhinney, Brian . (2009). The childes project. Tools for analyzing talk–electronic. edition 2
Manzini, M. Rita; Wexler, Kenneth . (1987). Parameters, binding theory, and learnability. Linguistic Inquiry 18 : 413.
Mintz, Toben H. . (2002). Category induction from distributional cues in an artificial language. Memory & Cognition 30 (5) : 678. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/BF03196424
Mintz, Toben H.; Newport, Elissa L.; Bever, Thomas G. . (2002). The distributional structure of grammatical categories in speech to young children. Cognitive Science 26 : 393. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog2604_1
Montgomery, Marcia M.; Montgomery, Allen A.; Stephens, M. Irene . (1978). Sentence repetition in preschoolers: Effects of length, complexity, and word familiarity. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 7 : 435. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF01068097
Nam, Seungho . (1994). Another type of negative polarity item In: Kanazawa, Makoto, Piñón, Christopher J. Christopher J. (eds.), Dynamic polarity and quantification. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications, pp. 3.
Pan, Hai-Hua . (2006). Focus, tripartite structure, and the semantic interpretation of Mandarin dou. Research and Exploration on Grammar 13 : 163.
Panitsa, Georgia . (2001). Aspects of aspect: Acquiring grammatical aspect in Modern Greek: The interaction of aspect with aspectual adverbials in children’s grammars. UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 13 : 405.
Redington, Martin; Crater, Nick; Finch, Steven . (1998). Distributional information: A powerful cue for acquiring syntactic categories. Cognitive Science 22 : 425. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog2204_2
Scholl, Dennis M.; Ryan, Ellen Bouchard . (1980). Development of metalinguistic performance in the early school years. Language and Speech 23 : 199.
Snyder, William . (2008). Children’s grammatical conservatism: Implications for linguistic theory In: Sano, Tetsuya, Endo, Mika; Mika and Isobe, Miwa; Miwa, Otaki, Koichi; Koichi, Sugisaki, Koji; Koji, Suzuki, Takeru Takeru (eds.), An enterprise in the cognitive science of language: A festschrift for Yukio Otsu. Tokyo: Hituzi Syobo, pp. 41.
Tardif, Twila Zoé . (1993). Adult-to-child speech and language acquisition in Mandarin Chinese. New Haven, CT: Yale University.
Tardif, Twila Zoé . (1996). Nouns are not always learned before verbs: Evidence from Mandarin speakers’ early vocabularies. Developmental psychology 32 : 492. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0012-1649.32.3.492
Tieu, Lyn . (2010). Franich, Katie, Keil, Lauren L.; Lauren L. and Iserman, Kate M.; Kate M., Chandlee, Jande Jande (eds.), The acquisition of NPI any in English: A case study. Online supplement to the Proceedings of the 34th Boston University Conference on Language Development (BUCLD).
Tieu, Lyn . (2013). Logic and grammar in child language: How children acquire the semantics of polarity sensitivity. dissertation. Storrs, CT: University of Connecticut.
Tieu, Lyn . (2015). Input vs. output in the acquisition of negative polarity: The curious case of any In: Larrivée, Pierre, Lee, Chungmin Chungmin (eds.), Language, cognition, and mind: negation and polarity: Experimental perspectives. Springer, 1 pp. 327.
Tieu, Lyn; Lidz, Jeffrey . (2016). Beyond NPI licensing: Children’s knowledge of the semantics of any. Language Acquisition 23 (4) : 311. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10489223.2016.1176172
van der Wal, Sjoukje . (1996). Negative polarity items and negation: Tandem acquisition. dissertation. Groningen: University of Groningen.
van der Wouden, Ton . (1997). Negative contexts: Collocation, polarity and multiple negation. London: Routledge.
Vinther, Thora . (2002). Elicited imitation: A brief overview. International Journal of Applied Linguistics 12 : 54. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1473-4192.00024
Wellman, Henry M.; Estes, David . (1986). Early understanding of mental entities: A reexamination of childhood realism. Child development 57 (4) : 910. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1130367
Wellman, Henry M.; Woolley, Jacqueline D. . (1990). From simple desires to ordinary beliefs: The early development of everyday psychology. Cognition 35 : 245. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0010-0277(90)90024-E
Wu, Jian-Xin . (1999). A minimal analysis of dou-quantification In: Ms. University of Maryland College Park.
Xie, Zhi-Guo . (2007). Nonveridicality and existential polarity wh-phrases in Mandarin. Chicago Linguistic Society (CLS) 43 (2) : 121.
Zhou, Jing . (2004a). The Zhou 1 corpus. The CHILDES database.
Zhou, Jing . (2004b). The Zhou 2 corpus. The CHILDES database.
Zhou, Peng . (2011). Interface conditions in child language: A view from Mandarin Chinese. Language Acquisition 18 : 202. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10489223.2011.580678
Zwarts, Frans . (1981). Negatief polaire uitdrukkingen I [negative polarity expressions I]. Glot 4 : 35.
Zwarts, Frans . (1986). Categoriale grammatica en algebraïsche semantiek: Een onderzoek naar negatie en polariteit in het nederlands [Categorical grammar and algebraic semantics: A study of negation and polarity in Dutch]. dissertation. Groningen: University of Groningen.
Zwarts, Frans . (1995). Nonveridical contexts. Linguistic Analysis 25 : 286.
Zwarts, Frans . (1998). Three types of polarity In: Hamm, Fritz, Hinrichs, Erhard Erhard (eds.), Plurality and quantification. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, pp. 177. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2706-8_5