1 Introduction
German allows the inversion of possessive PPs, as seen in (1a). It has previously been observed by Gallmann & Lindauer (1994) that this inversion is banned inside the complement of PPs (see (1b)). We collected reliable data that show that this inversion is ungrammatical in dative contexts, too (see (2)). These restrictions contrast prepositional possessors with other kinds of possessors in German which can be inversed in these contexts (see (1c) or (2c)).
- (1)
- a.
- Von
- of
- Conny
- Conny
- der
- the.NOM
- Hund
- dog
- heißt
- is.named
- Motte.
- Motte
- ‘Conny’s dog is called Motte.’
- b.
- *Ohne
- without
- von
- of
- Conny
- Conny
- den
- the.ACC
- Hund
- dog
- ist
- is
- es
- it
- langweilig.
- boring
- intended: ‘It is boring without Conny’s dog.’
- c.
- Ohne
- without
- Conny-s
- Conny-GEN
- Hund
- dog
- ist
- is
- es
- it
- langweilig.’
- boring
- ‘It is boring without Conny’s dog.’
- (2)
- a.
- *Von
- of
- Conny
- Conny
- dem
- the.DAT
- Hund
- dog
- gefällt
- is.pleased
- das
- that
- nicht.
- not
- intended: ‘Conny’s dog is not pleased about that.’
- b.
- Dem
- the.DAT
- Hund
- dog
- von
- of
- Conny
- Conny
- gefällt
- is.pleased
- das
- that
- nicht.
- not
- ‘Conny’s dog is not pleased about that.’
- c.
- Conny-s
- Conny-GEN
- Hund
- dog.DAT
- gefällt
- is.pleased
- das
- that
- nicht.’
- not
- ‘Conny’s dog is not pleased about that.’
In the following paper, we will show that this restriction follows directly in an analysis based on feature-driven Merge in a Minimalist framework. As the wide-spread constraint Merge-before-Move (Castillo et al. 1999; Frampton & Gutmann 1999; Chomsky 2000; Müller & Sternefeld; Hornstein 2001; 2009; Boeckx et al. 2010; Drummond 2011; Weisser 2015) enforces the higher P head to check the structure-buildung [•P•] feature, movement of the possessive PP is blocked. This paper is structured as follows. The relevant data is presented in Section 2. In Section 3, we propose a new analysis. Before concluding in Section 5, we discuss further issues of our proposal in Section 4.
2 Prepositional possession in German
In German, there are four different constructions that encode possession (Georgi & Salzmann 2011): The possessor may appear in genitive case, as in (3a). Furthermore, there is the prenominal genitive construction in (3b) and the double possessive construction in (3c). In this paper, however, we will focus on the construction in (3d) including a possessor preceded by the preposition von (‘of’).
- (3)
- a.
- das
- the
- Auto
- car
- meines
- my.GEN
- Vater-s
- father-GEN
- ‘the car of my father’
- b.
- Peter-s
- Peter-GEN
- Auto
- car
- ‘Peter’s car’
- c.
- mein-em
- my-DAT
- Vater
- father
- sein
- his
- Auto
- car
- ‘my father’s car’
- d.
- das
- the
- Auto
- car
- von
- of
- meinem
- my
- Vater
- father
- ‘the car of my father’
In non-standard German, the construction allows possessee and possessive PP to swap their positions, as seen in (4). The order of possessee and von-possessor in (4a) is the standard word order, which is widely accepted among German native speakers. In (4b), however, the constituents appear in reverse order.
- (4)
- a.
- Die
- the.NOM
- Frau
- wife
- von
- of
- Max
- Max
- hat
- has
- einen
- a
- Film
- movie
- gesehen.
- seen
- b.
- Von
- of
- Max
- Max
- die
- the.NOM
- Frau
- wife
- hat
- has
- einen
- a
- Film
- movie
- gesehen.
- seen
- ‘Max’ wife has seen a movie.’
Gallmann & Lindauer (1994) observed that the inversion cannot take place if the DP is inside a PP, as seen in (5b).1
- (5)
- a.
- Ohne
- without
- die
- the.ACC
- Frau
- wife
- von
- of
- Max
- Max
- bin
- am
- ich
- I
- ins
- to
- Kino
- cinema
- gegangen.
- gone
- b.
- *Ohne
- without
- von
- of
- Max
- Max
- die
- the.ACC
- Frau
- wife
- bin
- am
- ich
- I
- ins
- to
- Kino
- cinema
- gegangen.
- gone
- intended: ‘I went to the cinema without Max’ wife.’
A small-scale grammaticality judgment task in which we asked 49 native speakers of German to rate sentences from 1 (perfectly grammatical) to 6 (ungrammatical) showed that the inverse order is ungrammatical in dative contexts, too. While the construction allows the possessee to bear accusative case (see (6a)), dative possessees lead to ungrammaticality, as seen in (6b)–(6d). Note that this restriction is independent of the position of the constituent (prefield in (6c) vs. midfield in (6d)) or the status of the dative (lexical dative in (6b) vs. structural dative in (6c)).23
- (6)
- a.
- Ich
- I
- habe
- have
- von
- of
- Maria
- Mary
- den
- the.ACC
- Freund
- friend
- im
- in
- Kino
- cinema
- getroffen.
- met
- ‘I met Mary’s boyfriend in cinema.’
- b.
- *Von
- of
- Hans
- Hans
- der
- the.DAT
- Frau
- wife
- habe
- have
- ich
- I
- geholfen.
- helped
- intended: ‘I helped Hans’ wife.’
- c.
- *Von
- of
- Hans
- Hans
- der
- the.DAT
- Frau
- wife
- habe
- have
- ich
- I
- mein
- my
- Auto
- car
- geliehen.
- lent
- intended: ‘I have lent my car to Hans’ wife.’
- d.
- *Ich
- I
- habe
- have
- von
- of
- Hans
- Hans
- der
- the.DAT
- Frau
- wife
- mein
- my
- Auto
- car
- geliehen.
- lent
- intended: ‘I have lent my car to Hans’ wife.’
An anonymous reviewer pointed out that the grammaticality of (6b) increases when Hans is heavily stressed. Assuming that stress correlates with focus, we follow Fanselow (2002); Frey (2006) and Frey (2010) that the stressed PP has been moved to a designated focus position. Thus, the example in (7a) is structurally different from the example in (6b) as the possessive PP in (7a) has been scrambled out of the DP giving rise to the grammaticality of split DPs in (7b). In contrast, the possessor in (6b) in SpecDP remains in the DP.4
- (7)
- a.
- Von
- of
- HANS
- Hans
- der
- the
- Frau
- wife
- habe
- have
- ich
- I
- geholfen.
- helped
- b.
- Von
- of
- HANS
- Hans
- habe
- have
- ich
- I
- der
- the
- Frau
- wife
- geholfen.
- helped
- ‘I helped Hans’ wife.’
Moreover, the following examples show that other possessive constructions are not subject to these blocking effects and may be used with datives (see (8)) and after prepositions ((9)).
- (8)
- a.
- Dem
- the.DAT
- Auto
- car
- meine-s
- my-GEN
- Vater-s
- father-GEN
- fehlt
- lacks
- ein
- a
- Reifen.
- tire
- b.
- Peter-s
- Peter-GEN
- Auto
- car
- fehlt
- lacks
- ein
- a
- Reifen.
- tire
- c.
- Meine-m
- my-DAT
- Vater
- father
- seine-m
- his-DAT
- Auto
- car
- fehlt
- lacks
- ein
- a
- Reifen.
- tire
- ‘Peter’s car lacks a tire.’
- (9)
- a.
- Mit
- with
- dem
- the.DAT
- Auto
- car
- meine-s
- my-GEN
- Vater-s
- father-GEN
- bin
- am
- ich
- I
- nach
- to
- Berlin
- Berlin
- gefahren.
- gone
- b.
- Mit
- with
- Peter-s
- Peter-GEN
- Auto
- car
- bin
- am
- ich
- I
- nach
- to
- Berlin
- Berlin
- gefahren.
- gone
- c.
- Mit
- with
- meine-m
- my-DAT
- Vater
- father
- seine-m
- his-DAT
- Auto
- car
- bin
- am
- ich
- I
- nach
- to
- Berlin
- Berlin
- gefahren.
- gone
- ‘I went to Berlin with Peter’s car.’
From the data we have seen in this section, we can draw the generalization that the the inversion of prepositional modifiers is ungrammatical PP-internally, as previously observed by Gallmann & Lindauer (1994), as well as in dative contexts. As already pointed out by Gallmann & Lindauer (1994), these restrictions are not captured by previous analyses of this phenomenon, such as Bhatt (1990) or Fortmann (1996). Even though they suggest movement analyses within a Government and Binding framework, they fail to derive the blocking effect in the complement of PPs since the trigger for movement within G&B does not arise from features but from the relation of a moved XP and its trace. Hence, the goal of this paper is to present an analysis of German PP-inversion that can account for the restrictions that this construction is imposed on. In the following section, we will show that our proposal analyzes the ban on PP-internal PP-movement as an instance of a more general constraint on movement, the Internal Inversion Constraint, which arises from the constraint known as Merge-before-Move.
3 Proposal
For the following analysis, we will adopt a Minimalist framework with feature-driven Merge, i.e. Merge and Move (or: base-Merge and re-Merge) can only take place if they are triggered by a structure-building feature [•X•] (Heck & Müller 2003; 2007). This assumption is based on the last resort condition given in (10).
(10) | Last Resort (Abels 2003) |
A constituent α may only be merged, i.e. base-merge or re-merged, if that leads to the immediate satisfaction of a previously unsatisfiable feature. |
Another assumption made her, is that the inversion is triggered by an optional feature [•P•] which is the lowest feature in an ordered feature bundle as proposed by Georgi & Müller (2010). In this analysis, this feature bundle is on D, such that D has the featural specification [•N• ≻ •P•].5 The feature introduces a prepositional modifier and triggers movement of a PP to SpecDP. If the DP is not embeddded in a PP, the derivation thus proceeds as follows. In the first step, D satisfies its [•N•] feature by merging with the NP. At this point of the derivation (see (6-a)), the remaining [•P•] feature on D has not been satisfied. This can now be achieved ONLY by moving the possesssive PP to SpecDP, as seen in (11).
(11) | Inversion of possessive PPs | |||
a. | b. |
In the next step, we will see that this inversion cannot take place in the complement of PPs. Let us assume that we are at the point of the derivation where a complex NP has been merged with D. The next feature to be satisfied is the [•P•] feature on D. If the next head in the numeration is also a P head, [•P•] on D can be satisfied either by moving the possessive PP to SpecDP or by merging the next head in the numeration.6 Due to the constraint Merge-before-Move in (12) (Castillo et al. 1999; Frampton & Gutmann 1999; Chomsky 2000; Müller & Sternefeld 2001; Hornstein 2001; 2009; Boeckx et al. 2010; Drummond 2011; Weisser 2015), the next head of the numeration is merged which blocks the movement of the possessive PP to SpecDP as the movement trigger has already been checked.7
(12) | Merge before Move |
Suppose that the derivation has reached stage Σn, and Σn+1 is a legitimate instance of Merge, and Σ’n+1 is a legitimate instance of Move. Then, Σn+1 is to be preferred over Σ’n+1. |
(13) | No PP-internal PP-inversion | |||
a. | b. |
The constraint on movement that is responsible for the PP-internal blocking effect is summarized in (14) as the Internal Inversion Constraint. This constraint does not need to be stipulated, since it follows from the more general Merge-over-Move constraint.
(14) | Internal Inversion Constraint | |
Movement of an XP into SpecYP is banned if | ||
a. | this YP is selected by another X head and | |
b. | X and XP are of the same category. |
Meinunger (2000); Bayer et al. (2001); McFadden (2004); Rezac (2008), among others, have previously shown that datives and PPs form a natural class which has lead to the assumption that datives are actually PPs with a silent P head. Bayer et al. (2001), for instance, argue that all datives in German are actually embedded in a larger KasP which may be headed by a silent element or an overt P. One of their arguments comes from topic drop, where neither datives nor PPs can be dropped while nominatives and accusatives can, as seen in (15).
- (15)
- Bayer et al. (2001)
- a.
- *[]
- denke
- think
- ich
- I
- die
- the
- ganze
- whole
- Zeit.
- time
- intended: ‘I am thinking about [] the whole time’ [] = [PP an]
- b.
- *[]
- würde
- would
- ich
- I
- nicht
- not
- vertrauen.
- trust
- intended: ‘I wouldn’t trust [].’ [] = DAT
- c.
- []
- hab
- have
- ich
- I
- gestern
- yesterday
- im
- in
- Park
- park
- getroffen.
- met
- ‘I met [] yesterday in the park.’ [] = ACC
We have seen that our approach makes reference to categorial features, in contrast to previous analyses by Bhatt (1990); Fortmann (1996) and Georgi & Müller (2010). Hence, our analysis automatically covers the fact that prepositional modifiers show case restrictions (see the data (16), repeated from Section 2) under the assumption that datives are actually PPs. This being the case, it is logical consequence that both datives and PPs are subject to the Internal Inversion Constraint.
- (16)
- a.
- Von
- of
- Maria
- Mary
- den
- the.ACC
- Bruder
- brother
- habe
- have
- ich
- I
- in
- in
- der
- the
- Stadt
- town
- gesehen.
- seen
- ‘I saw my Mary’s brother in town.’
- b.
- *Von
- of
- Hans
- Hans
- der
- the.DAT
- Frau
- wife
- habe
- have
- ich
- I
- geholfen.
- helped
- intended: ‘I helped Hans’ wife.
- c.
- *Von
- of
- Hans
- Hans
- der
- the.DAT
- Frau
- wife
- habe
- have
- ich
- I
- mein
- my
- Auto
- car
- geliehen.
- lent
- intended:’I have lent my car to Hans’ wife.’
Moreover, the fact that the Internal Inversion Constraint is sensitive to categorial features predicts that the blocking effect should arise not only with possessives PPs but with other prepositional modifiers, as well. As seen in (17), this prediction is borne out.
- (17)
- a.
- Mit
- with
- dem
- the
- Hund
- dog
- die
- the.NOM
- Frau
- woman
- sitzt
- sits
- im
- in
- Gefängnis.
- jail
- ‘The woman with the dog is in jail.’
- b.
- *Mit
- with
- dem
- the
- Hund
- dog
- der
- the.DAT
- Frau
- woman
- ist
- is
- der
- the
- Ausbruch
- escape
- gelungen.
- succeeded
- intended: ‘The woman with the dog succeeded in escaping.’
In this section, we have seen that the restrictions of prenominal possessive PPs follow automatically from a [•P•] feature on D and the constraint Merge-before-Move. Moreover, it can easily be explained why only prepositional modifiers are subject to this restriction. The competition between the embedded PP and the next head in the numeration only arises as they are of the same lexical category. Since other kinds of possessors are non-prepositional, no blocking effect is expected.
4 Outlook
In this section, we will discuss some open questions and challenges for our account, before providing two putative examples from Archi nominalizations and Swiss German embedded V1 clauses. These could be seen as more general consequences of the proposed Internal Inversion Constraint.
At this point, we want to discuss a rather unconventional issue of the otherwise simple account that we put forward in this paper. As the D head bears a [•P•] feature and the next higher P head bears a [•D•] feature, our approach presupposes reciprocal subcategorization. This automatically leads to the question which of the two heads projects. Chomsky (2013) proposes a Labeling algorithm (see (18)) that allows a head to project if it merges with a phrase. In his view, a head is not defined as a constituent that subcategorizes but negatively as a syntactic object that is not the result of Merge. In our analysis, it thus follows that P would still be the projecting head which clearly solves the problem of reciprocal subcategorization.8
(18) | Labeling algorithm (LA) (Chomsky 2013) | |
a. | Suppose a syntactic object SO = {H, XP}, H is a head and XP is not a head. Then LA will select H as a label. | |
b. | A head is a syntactic object that is not of the form {X, Y} and thus not constructed by Merge. |
In section 3, we proposed the Internal Inversion Constraint that follows directly from the basic assumptions of feature-driven syntax and Merge-before-Move. If the Internal Inversion Constraint holds for all categories, we should expect similar blocking phenomena in other languages. Even though the distribution of similar blocking effects exceeds the scope of this article, we want to mention two possible instances of the Internal Inversion Constraint in other languages.
As Lötscher (1997) and Dürscheid & Hefti (2006) point out, one remarkable property of Swiss German syntax are embedded V1-clauses usually being headed by predicative adjectives or nouns (see (19)). The frequency of V1-clauses headed by verbs remains unclear in the literature, however, Lötscher (1997) mentions that the acceptability of V1-clauses strongly increases if they are headed by adjectives. This can be explained by means of the Internal Inversion Constraint such that V-to-C movement is blocked in clauses that are embedded under verbs but not under adjectives and nouns.
- (19)
- Lötscher (1997)
- S’isch
- it.is
- schaad,
- unfortunate
- isch
- is
- es
- it
- scho
- already
- Friitig.
- Friday
- lit: ‘It is unfortunate that it is already Friday.’
Another possible instance of the Internal Inversion Constraint is found in Archi (Nakh-Dagestanian, Russia). In this language, scrambling is allowed in main clauses, but not in nominalized clauses (Bond et al. 2016).9 They note that in nominalized clauses “[t]he genitive possessor […] can appear only in the very beginning or the very end of the clause, but not between the absolutive and the verb (whereas the ergative can take this position).” (Bond et al. 2016, 66). This blocking effect can be explained in terms of the Internal Inversion Constraint under the assumption that nominalized clauses are headed by a silent D head which blocks movement of a DP to a higher position.
5 Conclusion
In this paper, we have clarified and extended the empirical base of prepositional possessors in German. We have proposed an analysis of the inversion of prepositional modifiers in German. We have shown that the restriction against PP-internal PP-inversion follows from two basic assumptions of feature-driven syntax, namely the Last Resort condition and Merge-before-Move. If a head in the numeration and a lower phrase in the structure compete to check a structure-building feature, Merge will always be preferred, which leads to a blocking effect. This effect can be generalized as the Internal Inversion Constraint which makes clear and falsifiable predictions for other domains in syntax.
Notes
- Note that the ungrammaticality in (5b) does not simply arise from a general ban against preposition clusters. As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, prepositions may indeed follow other prepositions if both prepositions are base-merged, as seen in (i). This supports our claim that the ungrammaticality arises due to the interaction of Merge and Move.
- (i)
- Messi
- Messi
- traf
- scored
- von
- from
- hinter
- behind
- dem
- the
- Tor.
- goal
- lit. ‘Messi scored from behind the goal.’
- Note that inversion is also ungrammatical in genitive contexts, as shown in (ii). However, we specifically decided not to focus on genitive constructions in this paper since the empirical basis of this construction is somewhat unclear as genitive case is part of a high register in German while our construction in restricted to non-standard German.
- (ii)
- *Wir
- we
- wollen
- want
- heute
- today
- von
- of
- meiner
- my
- Frau
- wife
- des
- the.GEN
- Bruders
- brother
- gedenken.
- remember
- intended: ‘Today we want to remember the brother of my wife.’
- As a reviewer points out, in some cases the quantifier all(e) can intervene between the preposed PP and the rest of the DP. Intriguingly, no material can intervene between the quantifier and the determiner head. This is expected, if the quantifier forms a complex head with the determiner, cf. Pafel (1994).
- (iii)
- [von
- of
- Peter
- Peter
- [ [D
- all
- all
- die]
- the
- Freunde]]
- friends
- ‘all of Peter’s friends’
- This assumption might seem controversial due to the fact that German is considered to be a V2 language. However, Müller (2005); Winkler (2014) and Wiese & Müller (2018) show that the German prefield may be filled by two constituents under certain conditions. The question whether these conditions are met in the case of (7) is beyond the main scope and focus of this paper which is why we would like to leave this question open for further research. [^]
- As an anonymous reviewer points out, optionality of PP fronting requires optionality of the [•P•] on D. This can be achieved by including two versions of each D head in the lexicon. This would predict languages, where some determiners only occur with either a dominating preposition or an inverted PP in their complement. We are not sure if such a language is attested and to the best of our knowledge, this has not yet been thoroughly investigated. Nevertheless, nothing hinges on this choice in our account. [^]
- This assumption requires that D has access to the head in the numeration. This is not possible under the assumption that the DPs are phases and numerations are phase-based. As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, giving up the phasehood of the DP is not an innocent assumption, even though it has been proposed earlier by Matushansky (2005). Rather, we would like to question the assumption of phase-sized subnumerations as its original motivation by Chomsky (1995) has already been disputed by Abels (2012), among others. [^]
- An anonymous reviewer pointed out that the derivation in (11) results in a DP while the derivation in (13) results in a PP. However, the resulting phrases never compete for the same position in the clause since the differences result from different syntactic numerations, i.e. the derivation in (13) results in a PP because the next head in the numeration is P while the next head in (11) can be any other head apart from P. Thus, different numerations lead to different syntactic derivations making our analysis in fact trans-derivational. [^]
- Reciprocal subcategorization is not unheard of in Germanic linguistics. Sternefeld (2006) discusses auxiliary selection as a potential example of reciprocal subcategorization. The auxiliary selects for the morphological form of the verb, namely the participle, while the verb has idiosyncratic lexical information about the auxiliary that is selected. [^]
- As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, this blocking effect may also result from the observation that nominalized clauses are smaller than independent clauses and may therefore lack landing sites that are crucial for scrambling (see Lefebvre & Muysken 1988 for examples from Quechua). [^]
Abbreviations
ACC = accusative, GEN = genitive, NOM = nominative, DAT = dative
Acknowledgements
For invaluable feedback at various stages of this work, we wish to thank Andrew Murphy, Gereon Müller, Imke Driemel, Martin Salzmann, Mira Grubić, as well as three anonymous reviewers for Glossa. An earlier version of this work was presented to the audience of GGS 43 at Georg-August-Universität Göttingen whom we would like to thank for their feedback. This work was completed as part of DFG research training group Interaction of grammatical building blocks (GRK 2011).
Competing Interests
The authors have no competing interests to declare.
References
Abels, Klaus. 2003. Successive cyclicity, anti-locality, and adposition stranding. Storrs, CT: University of Connecticut dissertation.
Abels, Klaus. 2012. Phases: An essay on cyclicity in syntax. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110284225
Bayer, Josef, Markus Bader & Michael Meng. 2001. Morphological underspecification meets oblique case: Syntactic and processing effects in German. Lingua 111(4–7). 465–514. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/S0024-3841(00)00041-3
Bhatt, Christa. 1990. Die syntaktische Struktur der Nominalphrase im Deutschen. Tübingen: Narr.
Boeckx, Cedric, Norbert Hornstein & Jairo Nunes. 2010. Control as movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511761997
Bond, Oliver, Greville G. Corbett, Marina Chumakina & Dunstan Brown. 2016. Archi: Complexities of agreement in cross-theoretical perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198747291.001.0001
Castillo, Juan Carlos, John Drury & Kleanthes K. Grohmann. 1999. Merge over move and the extended projection principle. University of Maryland working papers in linguistics 8. 63–103.
Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In Roger Martin, David Michaels & Juan Uriagereka (eds.), Step by step, 89–156. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 2013. Problems of projection. Lingua 130. 33–49. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2012.12.003
Drummond, Alex. 2011. Merge over move and Romance obviation effects. Talk given at 85th Annual Meeting of the Linguistic Society of America.
Dürscheid, Christa & Inga Hefti. 2006. Syntaktische Merkmale des Schweizer Standarddeutsch. In Christa Dürscheid & Martin Businger (eds.), Schweizer Standarddeutsch. Beiträge zur Varietätenlinguistik, 131–161. Tübingen: Narr.
Fanselow, Gisbert. 2002. Quirky subjects and other specifiers. In Ingrid Kaufmann & Barbara Stiebels (eds.), More than words, 227–250. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783050081274-009
Fortmann, Christian. 1996. Konstituentenbewegung in der DP-Struktur: Zur funktionalen Analyse der Nominalphrase im Deutschen. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110955323
Frampton, John & Sam Gutmann. 1999. Cyclic computation. Syntax 2(1). 1–27. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9612.00012
Frey, Werner. 2006. Contrast and movement to the German prefield. In Valéria Molnár & Susanne Winkler (eds.), The architecture of focus, 235–265. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110922011.235
Frey, Werner. 2010. Ā-Movement and conventional implicatures: About the grammatical encoding of emphasis in German. Lingua 120(6). 1416–1435. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2008.09.016
Gallmann, Peter & Thomas Lindauer. 1994. Funktionale Kategorien in Nominalphrasen. Beiträge zur Geschichte der deutschen Sprache und Literatur (PBB) 116(1). 1–27.
Georgi, Doreen & Gereon Müller. 2010. Noun-phrase structure by reprojection. Syntax 13(1). 1–36. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9612.2009.00132.x
Georgi, Doreen & Martin Salzmann. 2011. DP-internal double agreement is not double Agree: Consequences of Agree-based case assignment within DP. Lingua 121(14). 2069–2088. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2011.07.010
Heck, Fabian & Gereon Müller. 2003. Derivational optimization of whmovement. Linguistic Analysis 33(1). 97–148.
Heck, Fabian & Gereon Müller. 2007. Extremely local optimization. In Proceedings of the 26th WECOL, 170–183. Fresno, CA: Department of Linguistics, University of Fresno.
Hornstein, Norbert. 2001. Move. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hornstein, Norbert. 2009. A theory of syntax: Minimal operations and Universal Grammar. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lefebvre, Claire & Pieter Muysken. 1988. Mixed categories: Nominalizations in Quechua. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.
Lötscher, Andreas. 1997. Guet sind Si doo–Verbstellungsprobleme bei Ergänzungssätzen im Schweizerdeutschen. In Arno Ruoff & Peter Löffelad (eds.), Syntax und Stilistik der Alltagssprache: Beiträge der 12. Arbeitstagung zur alemannischen Dialektologie, 85–95. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.
Matushansky, Ora. 2005. Going through a phase. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 49. 157–181.
McFadden, Thomas. 2004. The position of morphological case in the derivation. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania dissertation.
Meinunger, André. 2000. Syntactic aspects of topic and comment. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.38
Müller, Gereon & Wolfgang Sternefeld. 2001. The rise of competition in syntax: A synopsis. In Gereon Müller & Wolfgang Sternefeld (eds.), Competition in syntax, 1–68. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110829068.1
Müller, Stefan. 2005. Zur Analyse der scheinbar mehrfachen Vorfeldbesetzung. Linguistische Berichte 203. 29–62.
Pafel, Jürgen. 1994. Zur syntaktischen Struktur nominaler Quantoren. Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 13(2). 236–275. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/zfsw.1994.13.2.236
Rezac, Milan. 2008. Phi-agree and theta-related case. In Daniel Harbour, David Adger & Susana Béjar (eds.), Phi theory: Phi-features across interfaces and modules, 83–129. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sternefeld, Wolfgang. 2006. Syntax: eine morphologisch motivierte generative Beschreibung des Deutschen. Tübingen: Stauffenburg.
Weisser, Philipp. 2015. Derived coordination: A minimalist perspective on clause chains, converbs and asymmetric coordination. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110443578
Wiese, Heike & Hans G. Müller. 2018. The hidden life of V3: An overlooked word order variant on verb-second. In Mailin Antomo & Sonja Müller (eds.), Non-canonical verb positioning in main clauses, 201–224. Hamburg: Helmut Buske Verlag.
Winkler, Julia. 2014. Verbdrittstellung im Deutschen: eine wettbewerbstheoretische Analyse. Berlin: WVB, Wiss. Verlag.