1 Introduction
Adjunct control is the referential relation between the null (PRO) subject of a non-finite adjunct and its understood antecedent, as in the temporal adjunct in (1) or the rationale clause (RatC) in (2).
(1) | The windowi broke [after PROi being hit with a rock]. |
(2) | This booki was written [in order PROi to be read]. |
Adjunct control has received relatively little attention in the literature on control. Theories of the control dependency have been largely built around the properties of complement control, as exemplified in (3), and it has often been assumed (e.g. by Chomsky 1981; Farkas 1988; Hornstein 1999) that adjunct control will display the same properties, despite the fact that adjuncts and complement are quite different syntactically. For example, complements, but not adjuncts, are selected by the main verb, and adjuncts are islands to movement more often than complements are.
(3) | Harryi promised PROi to make himself/*oneself invisible. |
Where adjunct control is discussed, it is often assumed to require strict syntactic obligatory control (OC), parallel to complement control (Mohanan 1983; Clark 1990; Hornstein 1999; Pires 2007). For example, because PRO in adjuncts such as those in (4) can only be controlled by the matrix subject, it is argued that adjunct control must involve a syntactic dependency between PRO and its closest c-commanding potential antecedent. Even theories that do not rely on a syntactic binding relation for complement control (e.g. Culicover & Jackendoff 2001) do presume that control into at least some adjuncts is determined syntactically.1 Furthermore, many theories of control at least implicitly assume that OC and non-obligatory control (NOC), in which PRO is not bound by a syntactic antecedent, are in complementary distribution, NOC only obtaining if OC is blocked (Mohanan 1983; Clark 1990; Hornstein 1999; Pires 2007; McFadden & Sundaresan 2016). If this is the case, then inasmuch as an OC dependency in adjunct control structures is possible, it should be the only option.
(4) | a. | Roni talked to Harryj [before PROi/*j leaving the room]. |
b. | [PROi/*j Having washed himself/*herself], Harryi talked to Ginnyj. | |
c. | Harryi grew up [PROi/*j to be a famous wizard]. | |
d. | The balli fell, [only PROi/*j to be picked up again]. |
However, Landau (2017) argues that RatCs and temporal adjuncts are not restricted to OC. Although the control relation in the examples in (4) may indeed be OC, the examples in (5) demonstrate that NOC is also possible, since here PRO is understood to refer to someone who is not represented by an argument that could syntactically bind PRO.2 Temporal and rationale clauses are thus hybrid environments allowing both OC and NOC (see also Español-Echevarría 2000; Green in press).
(5) | a. | All preparations were made [before PRO inviting the senator to the hearing]. |
b. | The painting was on the wall [in order PRO to check how it would be received]. (Landau 2017: 98) |
Still, OC and NOC are not always equally available; speakers often prefer OC. The main goal of Landau (2017) was to demonstrate how the voice of the adjunct affects the type of control seen. Landau argued that passive adjuncts are restricted to OC, and that when the adjunct is in active voice, NOC is only possible when OC would lead to “semantic deviance,” meaning that it would make the sentence denote a bizarre or impossible situation. In a more recent talk, Landau (2018) revised these generalizations, arguing that NOC is possible only if PRO and its potential OC antecedent mismatch in [init] features, where an argument is [+init] if it is the “initiator” who intentionally brings about a situation (see Farkas 1988). Green (in press) questions the validity of these claims for temporal adjuncts, arguing that NOC does not require an active adjunct, semantic deviance of OC, or a mismatch in [init] features. Instead, it is claimed that OC and NOC are freely available in temporal adjuncts, but that performance biases in comprehension lead to a preference for OC. This is most clearly seen in (6), which allows both OC and NOC, without, arguably, changing the structure of the sentence, and in which PRO and its potential OC controller are both [–init].
(6) | The pooli was the perfect temperature [after PROi/j being in the sun all day]. |
Whatever the source of speakers’ preference for OC over NOC in adjuncts, it is clear that temporal and rationale adjuncts allow both in at least some contexts. This paper demonstrates that the same is true of many adjuncts, but that others are restricted to either OC or NOC. I outline assumptions that would have to be made in two frameworks, the Two-tiered Theory of Control (TTC) (Landau 2015) and the Movement Theory of Control (MTC) (Hornstein 1999; Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes 2010a), to accommodate adjunct control more fully. I argue that although both are able to partially explain the data, the MTC fares slightly better.
This paper proceeds as follows. In §2 I review and expand on the way Landau implements his hypothesis for RatCs and temporal adjuncts in the TTC. Section 3 discusses several other types of adjuncts, illustrating that only some display the same OC/NOC duality. Section 4 then outlines assumptions the TTC would have to make in order to explain the data, but argues that such assumptions are not justified. In §5, I propose an alternative explanation within the framework of the MTC that can account for some of the strict OC adjuncts that the TTC struggles with. Section 6 concludes.
2 The two-tiered theory of control
Landau situates his discussion of OC and NOC in adjuncts within the Two-tiered Theory of Control (TTC). This section provides a brief background on the theory, followed by an explanation of why temporal and rationale adjuncts allow both OC and NOC, while complements are restricted to OC.
2.1 Background on the TTC
The TTC rejects traditional formulations of OC and NOC, instead classifying control as either predicative or logophoric.3 In complements, logophoric control occurs with attitude predicates, and predicative control with non-attitude predicates. The term “predicative control” is used to describe the situation when a verb denotes a relation R between an individual x and a property p that entails R*(x, p(x)), where R* expresses essentially the same concept as R. For example, “x managed p” is true iff MANAGE*(x, p(x)). Due to the nature of predication, this results in OC. Predicative complement control is said to have a structure like (7). PRO is taken to be simply a variable, and the FinP represents a predicate that is “applied” by mediation of the matrix verb to the closest c-commanding argument.
(7) | Harry managed [FinP λx [Fin′ Fin [TP x to win]]]. |
Logophoric control, which appears only with attitude predicates, also involves a FinP predicate, but it is predicated of a pro situated in an additional layer of structure, as in (8).4 This pro represents a variable i, and logophoric control is instantiated as a relation between x and p(i), where i is restricted to the AUTHOR or ADDRESSEE of the context of evaluation. In complement control, this context is restricted by the matrix verb and the embedded C to include only the matrix attitude holder and their addressee; pro must therefore be associated with one of them, resulting in OC.
(8) | Harry intends [CP pro C+log [FinP λx [Fin′ Fin [TP x to win]]]]. |
Landau (2015), following E. Williams (1992), briefly suggests that adjuncts may also fall into these two categories. Landau (2017) furthers that suggestion, claiming that clausal adjuncts can adjoin with either a predicative or a logophoric structure, as illustrated in (9).
(9) | a. | OC adjuncts (predicative control): |
[PP before/in order [FinP λx [Fin′ Fin [TP x …]]]] | ||
b. | NOC adjuncts (logophoric control): | |
[PP before/in order [CP pro C+log [FinP λx [Fin′ Fin [TP x …]]]]] | ||
(modified from Landau 2017: 100) |
Predicative structures give rise to what is traditionally called OC, although if Landau is assuming a theory of predication similar to semantic theories of control, where the embedding verb mediates the predication, then it is unclear how this would apply to adjuncts. In adjunct control there is no mediating verb, and a semantic approach where the predication is mediated by the relation between the two clauses is unlikely, as there is nothing in the meaning of while, for example, that suggests that the two concurrent events should share a participant, much less one named by the subjects of the clauses.5 So it must be the case that the λ is passed up the tree, either through movement or through a complex series of function composition. Assuming that the predication relation does obtain, the antecedent of the variable corresponding to PRO will be limited to the closest c-commanding DP, resulting in OC. When an adjunct attaches with a logophoric structure, on the other hand, “PRO” is bound by the intermediate pro. But unlike in complement control, because the adjunct is not selected by a matrix verb, there is no restriction on the context of evaluation of the embedded clause, so pro is free to refer to the AUTHOR or ADDRESSEE of any relevant context, resulting in logophoric NOC.
2.2 Complements are restricted to OC, but adjuncts are not
Under the TTC, whether complement control will involve a predicative or logophoric structure is determined based on selectional restrictions of the embedding predicate. OC is ensured in non-attitude complements because the embedded clause is simply a predicate whose argument is instantiated by the closest c-commanding argument of the matrix clause. NOC is ruled out because the predication relation must be satisfied locally. Attitude predicates, on the other hand, select a logophoric complement and set the context of evaluation of that complement as the attitude context of the matrix event. This ensures that the controller will either be that event’s AUTHOR or its ADDRESSEE. Because PRO must be controlled by an argument of the matrix clause, logophoric control in complements is OC.6
Although Landau (2015; 2017) does not directly address why adjunct control differs from complement control in not being restricted to OC, the only apparent difference between the two is that complements, but not adjuncts, are selected by the main clause predicate. Because complements are selected to have either a predicative or logophoric structure, they are restricted to OC. But adjuncts, being unselected, can have either structure. When an adjunct has a predicative structure, the λ associated with PRO is “applied” to the closest c-commanding argument, which for temporal and rationale clauses is the subject of the clause hosting the adjunct. Assuming that the λ does somehow “apply” to the matrix subject, it will result in OC due to the nature of predication. Logophoric adjuncts show NOC because there is no selecting predicate to enforce a restriction on the context of evaluation of the embedded clause. The pro in the specifier of C that binds PRO is therefore free to refer to the AUTHOR or ADDRESSEE of any relevant context, including the utterance context (Landau 2015).
Landau (2017) discussed only RatCs and temporal adjuncts, and it was not his intent to give an argument about all types of adjunct control. But if the reason RatCs and temporal adjuncts allow both OC and NOC is that their structure is unselected by a matrix verb, then it seems logical that the same should be true of other adjuncts, since they, too, are unselected. With the exception of bare adjectives or participles, which Landau (2015: 97) mentions in a footnote may not project the functional structure needed to mediate NOC, any adjunct should be free to adjoin with either a predicative structure resulting in OC, or a logophoric one leading to NOC.
3 Other adjuncts
There are several types of adjuncts that exhibit control, each with distinct properties (see Huettner 1989; Landau 2013). This section briefly illustrates that although some adjuncts follow the pattern of RatCs and temporal adjuncts in allowing both OC and NOC, others are restricted to one or the other. The assumptions that would have to be made under the TTC to explain these differences will be discussed in §4.
3.1 Adjuncts allowing both OC and NOC
If RatCs and temporal adjuncts allow both OC and NOC because they are not selected, then all clausal control adjuncts, being similarly unselected, should exhibit the same duality. Here I discuss three adjuncts that confirm this prediction: response clauses, object-gap purpose clauses, and absolutive clauses. Although I provide evidence that both OC and NOC are possible, it is outside the scope of this paper to establish when speakers will prefer one over the other. For discussions on the contexts and constraints leading to OC and NOC in RatCs and temporal adjuncts, see Kawasaki (1993), Janke & Bailey (2017), Landau (2017), and Green (2018; in press).
3.1.1 Response clauses
One adjunct that has been largely ignored in the literature is illustrated in (10). Where mentioned, these adjuncts have been called reason clauses (Betancort, Carreiras & Acuña-Fariña 2006), rationale clauses (Hornstein 1999), justification clauses (Stromdahl 2018), or simply gerundival complements to for (A. Williams & Green 2017). For clarity, and to distinguish them from RatCs, which have also been called reason clauses (A. Williams 2015), I will call the adjuncts in (10) “response clauses.” The reason is that these adjuncts entail that the act of the main clause was meant as a response to what is described by the adjunct (A. Williams & Green 2017; see also Fillmore 1971; Fabricius-Hansen & Sæbø 2011).
(10) | a. | Harryi got a trophy [for PROi winning the tournament]. |
b. | They gave a trophy to Harryi [for PROi winning the tournament]. | |
c. | Mickey hugged Minniei [for PROi doing so well on the test]. |
Some responses clauses may be understood as conceptual “arguments” of what I will call blame-class verbs, such as blame, praise, and thank, as in (11). The meaning of the verb blame, for example, requires that there is either an explicit or implicit offense associated with the blame (Fillmore 1971). This is not the case with the response clauses in (10). But although their conceptual relationship to the main clause predicate may differ, I assume that the response clauses in either case have the same syntactic status.
(11) | a. | Harry blamed Snapei [for PROi breaking in]. |
b. | Hermione praised Harryi [for PROi being such a great wizard]. | |
c. | Harry thanked Roni [for PROi teaching him chess]. |
There is good evidence that response clauses allow logophoric NOC. In the sentences in (12), for example, controller choice is not limited to c-commanding arguments, as PRO is coreferential with an embedded possessor. If control of response clauses were strictly predicative OC, this should be impossible, since there is no way to form the necessary predication dependency between PRO and a non-c-commanding argument.
(12) | a. | I left them in heri locker [for PROi being so kind to me]. (Stromdahl 2018) |
b. | I put roses on the front porch of heri house [for PROi being so kind to me]. |
In addition, response clauses allow implicit control, which has been argued to be NOC (Manzini 1986; Kawasaki 1993; Landau 2017). In (13a), PRO may refer to the implicit recipient of the medal. Example (13b) shows the same thing, but uses a pronoun to remove the possibility that the response clause adjoins within the object DP.7
(13) | a. | They awarded a medal [for PRO winning the contest]. |
b. | They awarded it [for PRO winning the contest]. |
These examples illustrate that response clauses sometimes exhibit NOC. Importantly, there is also evidence that OC is sometimes possible. The ellipsis site in (14) includes a response clause. PRO in the elided clause requires “sloppy” interpretation (Ross 1967; 1969) under ellipsis, which is suggestive of OC (Pires 2007; Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes 2010a).
(14) | Jacki brought Sharon flowers [for PROi having worked so late], and Davidj did, too. |
(‘and Davidj brought Sharon flowers for hisj/*i having worked so late’) |
OC is is also seen in response clauses that allow inanimate controllers. It has been argued that NOC requires a [+human] interpretation for PRO (Clark 1990; Landau 2013), which, under the TTC, follows from the logophoric nature of NOC (Landau 2017). And yet PRO in each of the response clauses in (15) allows an inanimate controller, which can only be OC.
(15) | a. | The booki was praised [for PROi showing how, and under what circumstances, a religion grows].8 |
b. | I included this booki in the book fair [for PROi being so well written]. |
In sum, control in response clauses must sometimes be OC, as evidenced by the fact that inanimate controllers are possible, and sloppy identity is at least sometimes required under ellipsis. But there is also evidence that response clauses allow NOC: implicit and non-c-commanding controllers are sometimes possible. This is consistent with the generalization that adjuncts allow both OC and NOC, and the explanation of the duality of temporal and rationale clauses given above based on Landau (2015; 2017) can easily be extended to response clauses. Because they are not selected by the matrix verb, response clauses are free to adjoin with either a predicative or a logophoric structure.
3.1.2 Object-gap purpose clauses
Another adjunct that allows both OC and NOC is the object-gap purpose clause (OPC). Purpose clauses contain one obligatory gap that is coreferential with the theme argument of the host clause (Jones 1991; Kawasaki 1993; Whelpton 1995). In OPCs, this gap is in a non-subject position.9 The subject may contain an additional empty category (PRO), which is often coreferential with the indirect object of the main clause, if one is present (16a), or with the matrix subject otherwise (16b). Lexical subjects are also possible (16c).10
(16) | a. | Chandler bought Monicai a frying panj [PROi to cook with tj]. |
b. | Monicai bought a frying panj [PROi to cook with tj]. | |
c. | Chandler bought a frying panj [for Monica to cook with tj]. |
Several authors have claimed that the dependency between PRO in an OPC and its antecedent is OC (e.g. Nishigauchi 1984; Kawasaki 1993; Landau 2013; Hallman 2015). Evidence that OC is possible is that only sloppy identity is available under ellipsis in examples like (17a), which can only be used to say that Chandler got his frying pan with the intent of cooking with it himself. Also, PRO can only have a bound interpretation when controlled by an only-DP in (17b), which entails that no one else bought a frying pan with the intent that they themselves would cook with it; it is still true in a situation where both Monica and Chandler bought frying pans with the intent that Monica would cook with them. Here one is used as the antecedent in order to remove the possibility of a relative clause analysis (see footnote 10).
(17) | a. | Speaking of new frying pans, Monicai bought one [PROi to cook with t], and Chandlerk did, too. |
b. | Only Monicai bought one [PROi to cook with t]. |
Inanimate controllers are also possible (18), which again indicates OC.
(18) | a. | Nathan got his computeri a new graphics cardj [PROi to better display his games with tj]. |
b. | Nathan got his computeri onej [PROi to better display his games with tj]. |
But there is also strong evidence that NOC is sometimes possible. For example, PRO in an OPC can have a non-c-commanding or syntactically absent controller, as seen in (19), modified from Stromdahl (2018).
(19) | a. | I left iti in [herj mailbox] [PROj to look over ti once she returned from the Bahamas]. |
b. | Theyi’re kept in the overhead compartment [PRO to use ti in case of an emergency]. |
OPCs therefore allow both OC and NOC, similar to temporal and rationale adjuncts.
3.1.3 Absolutives
A final adjunct that allows both OC and NOC is the absolutive clause, which adjoins as a bare participial phrase, as in (20).
(20) | [PROi Having come this far], Ii can’t go back. |
Pires (2007) argues that absolutive adjuncts are OC based on several tests. For example, PRO’s controller in (21a) must c-command it, and (21b) only allows a sloppy interpretation of the elided PRO.
(21) | a. | [Peterj’s daughter]i went on to college, [PROi/*j being the best student in the class]. |
b. | [PROi Having kissed Mary at the door], Peteri left the party with some friends, and Bill did too. | |
‘and Billj left after hej/*Peter kissed Mary’ (Pires 2007 197) |
Inanimate controllers are also possible (22), giving further evidence for OC.
(22) | [PROi Having only been purchased yesterday], the dishwasheri is already broken. |
However, non-c-commanding controllers are possible given the right context, which indicates NOC. In (23) and (24), PRO can refer to the speaker. This is especially true when the adjunct is left-adjoined, but it is also possible, if slightly more marginal, when it is right-adjoined.
(23) | a. | [PRO Sitting in class that day], my eyes refused to stay open. |
b. | ?My eyes refused to stay open, [PRO sitting in class that day]. |
(24) | a. | [PRO Resting in the shade], the heat didn’t feel as oppressive. |
b. | ?The heat didn’t feel as oppressive, [PRO resting in the shade]. |
Absolutive clauses therefore also conform to the generalization that adjunct control allows both OC and NOC. Interestingly, though, Landau (2015: 97) mentions in a footnote that bare participles do not project the functional structure needed to support NOC. Although this was only mentioned in passing without additional support, if it is true that absolutives are too small to project a logophoric structure, then the NOC exhibited in (23)–(24) would be surprising. I will return to the issue of adjunct size and its interaction with OC/NOC in §4.2.
3.1.4 Summary of OC/NOC adjuncts
The evidence that response clauses, OPCs, and absolutives allow both OC and NOC is summarized in Table 1, along with a summary of evidence on RatCs and temporal adjuncts found in Landau (2017) and Green (2018). OC is seen when PRO in these adjuncts has an inanimate controller, and when sloppy readings under ellipsis or bound readings with control by an “only”-DP are required. NOC is found when these adjuncts allow PRO to co-refer with a non-c-commanding antecedent, or to refer to an entity not present in the sentence at all, in what I broadly term “implicit control”.
Adjunct | OC | NOC | ||
---|---|---|---|---|
inanimate controllers? | sloppy/bound required? | non-c-comm. controllers? | implicit control? | |
RatCs | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | |
Temporal | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | |
Response | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
OPCs | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
Absolutives | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
3.2 Adjunct restricted to NOC
The adjuncts discussed thus far pattern with RatCs and temporal adjuncts in allowing both OC and NOC, but the same is not true of other adjuncts, even though they too are unselected. I have found only one adjunct restricted to NOC: speaker-oriented adverbials (SOAs). SOAs represent the speaker’s evaluation of the proposition denoted by the main clause or the speaker’s degree of certainty about that proposition’s truth (Ernst 2009). They can surface as adverbs (25a), infinitive verb phrases (25b–c), or participial phrases (25d).
(25) | a. | Honestly, Jon would be better off without Mary. |
b. | [PRO To be clear/frank], Jon would be better off without Mary. | |
c. | [PRO To put it briefly], Jon would be better of without Mary. | |
d. | [PRO Judging from experience], Jon will be better off without Mary. |
PRO in (25b–d) refers to the speaker of the utterance. It cannot be coreferential with an argument of the main clause, unless that argument also refers to the speaker.11 These adjuncts must therefore be NOC. The same interpretation obtains if the adjuncts are adjoined to the right.
(26) | a. | Jon would be better off without Mary, honestly. |
b. | Jon would be better off without Mary, PRO to be honest. | |
c. | Jon will be better off without Mary, PRO judging from experience. |
Since PRO in SOAs can only correspond to the speaker, SOAs must require a logophoric structure, resulting in strict NOC. These adjuncts therefore do not conform to the generalization that adjunct control allows both OC and NOC. However, according to Cinque (1999), evaluative and evidential adverbs attach high in the structure, to functional projections well above the TP. If SOAs containing control structures also attach high, then no argument of the sentence would be in a position to c-command PRO, and predicative OC by an argument of the main clause would be impossible. The adjunct could in principle adjoin with either a predicative or a logophoric structure, but only logophoric NOC would lead to a convergent derivation. With a predicative structure, the predicate would have no argument to be applied to and would remain unsaturated. We will return to the TTC’s account of SOAs and potential problems in §4.2 and §5.3.1.
3.3 Adjuncts restricted to OC
There are also some adjuncts that are strictly OC. This section discusses goal clauses, subject-gap purpose clauses, and telic clauses.12
3.3.1 Goal clauses
One adjunct that only allows OC is the goal clause (Huettner 1989; Landau 2013), illustrated in (27).
(27) | a. | Maxi works hard [PROi to stay out of jail]. (Huettner 1989: 38) |
b. | Maxi works hard [PROi to avoid doing any work]. | |
c. | Sami always plays [PROi to win]. (Huettner 1989: 24) | |
d. | We cultivated the planti [PROi to be more nutritious]. |
Although similar on the surface to RatCs such as (28), goal clauses differ in meaning. According to Huettner (1989), the matrix clauses in (27) constitute doing, or attempting to do, what is in the adjunct. For example, under the goal clause interpretation of (27a), Max works hard at staying out of jail, even if he does not literally work hard. With the RatC in (28a), on the other hand, Max literally works hard at some unspecified job because otherwise he will end up in jail. This is further illustrated in the contrast between (27b) and (28b). If the infinitive is a goal clause, then Max puts great effort into avoiding work; but when the infinitive is a RatC, the sentence can only have the strange interpretation that Max literally works hard, because otherwise he would not be able to avoid work.
(28) | a. | Maxi works hard [(in order) PROi to stay out of jail]. |
b. | #Maxi works hard [(in order) PROi to avoid doing any work]. |
Goal clauses adjoined to an intransitive matrix clause as in (27) only allow subject control of PRO. Neither (27a) nor (27b), for example, can be used to mean that Max worked hard at someone else staying out of jail or avoiding work. This suggests that OC is involved. Further evidence for OC in goal clauses is that they allow inanimate controllers, as illustrated in (27d) and (29), and that sloppy identity is required under ellipsis (30).
(29) | Those pantsi are working hard [PROi to hold in that man’s flab]. |
(30) | Sami always plays [PROi to win], and his accomplice does, too. |
‘and his accomplicej always plays PROj/*i to win’ |
In contrast to RatCs and temporal adjuncts, goal clauses appear not to allow NOC. As the examples in (31) make plain, even when subject control is ruled out, and when the preceding context establishes an available logophoric antecedent, conditions that facilitate NOC in RatCs and temporal adjuncts (Landau 2017; Green in press), OC by a c-commanding argument of the next clause up is the only possible reading.
(31) | *Jonj noticed that hisj pantsi were working hard [PROj not to burst out of them]. |
Implicit control by a passive agent, which Landau (2017) argues is NOC, is also impossible. The goal clauses in (32) are limited to subject control, in contrast to the RatC in (33), which allows implicit control. Because the in order in RatCs is optional, the string in (32b) is ambiguous between containing a RatC or a goal clause. Crucially, though, if PRO is understood to refer to the implicit agent, only a RatC interpretation is possible. The sentence can only be interpreted as the answer to the question of why the plant was cultivated in general (as opposed to being left uncultivated). This is in contrast to the goal clause reading of (32a), in which the plant is specifically cultivated toward the goal of being nutritious, in answer to a more specific question about which goal the plant was cultivated for (among other possible cultivation outcomes). The difference, though subtle, is important.
(32) | a. | The planti was cultivated [PROi to be more nutritious]. |
b. | The planti was cultivated [PRO to gain more nutrition from iti]. | |
*‘The plant was cultivated toward the goal of gaining more nutrition from it.’ (Goal) | ||
‘The plant was cultivated generally because that might lead to more nutrition.’ (Rat) |
(33) | The planti was cultivated [in order PRO to gain more nutrition from iti]. |
If temporal and rationale adjuncts allow both OC and NOC simply because their structure is not selected by the matrix predicate, and if goal clauses are similarly unselected, then the strict OC behavior of goal clauses is unexpected.
3.3.2 Subject-gap purpose clauses
The next adjunct restricted to OC is the subject-gap purpose clause (SPC). SPCs such as the one in (34) are similar to OPCs, but without the post-verbal gap.13
(34) | Harry brought Hermionei along [PROi to deal with the security guards]. |
Jones (1991) categorizes SPCs as OC. And although he does not give a detailed analysis of them, Landau (2015) also states in passing that SPCs involve non-logophoric PRO, which can only be OC. Evidence that this is correct is that SPCs allow inanimate controllers (35), and that PRO requires a bound reading when controlled by an “only”-DP. Example (36) states that only that bookshelf was purchased with the intended purpose of its holding books; it is still true in a situation where the speaker bought other shelves, as long as they were not also meant to hold books.
(35) | a. | I bought the shelfi [PROi to hold books]. | (E. Williams 1992: 317) |
b. | I bought this blenderi [PROi to help me make split pea soup]. | (Landau 2015: 22) |
(36) | I bought [only this shelf]i [PROi to hold books]. |
SPCs do not allow implicit controllers, which would indicate the availability of NOC. The SPC in (37a) clearly allows control by the direct object of donate. But even though that object can be left implicit (37b), control by an implicit object is impossible; (37c) is ungrammatical as an SPC (although it could have a RatC interpretation, in which case the slave driver would control PRO).
(37) | a. | The slave driver donated three slavesi to the plantation [PROi to work in the fields]. |
b. | The slave driver donated to the plantation. | |
c. | *The slave driver donated to the plantation [PRO to work in the fields]. |
Implicit control could potentially be ruled out for other reasons, since even in adjuncts that allow implicit control in some instances, its availability can be restricted (Landau 2017; Green in press). However, non-c-commanding controllers are also ruled out, in contrast to what was seen for OPCs in (19), providing further evidence that NOC is impossible.
(38) | *I brought the prisoneri’s finger home with me [PROi to impress his fellow prisoners]. |
Like goal clauses, SPCs appear to counter the hypothesis that unselected adjuncts should allow both OC and NOC.
3.3.3 Telic clauses
A final adjunct that is restricted to OC is the telic clause, illustrated in (39), which express the outcome of the event of the main clause (Whelpton 2001).
(39) | a. | Harryi opened the letter, [only PROi to discover it wasn’t for him]. |
b. | The historic mansioni remained untouched by the wildfire, [only PROi to be destroyed by an earthquake three months later]. |
These adjuncts, also known as “outcome” clauses, have received little attention in the literature. Where they have been discussed, they have been classified as requiring OC by the matrix subject (Huettner 1989; Whelpton 1995; Landau 2013). That OC is possible is made evident by (39b), which has an inanimate controller, as well as by (40), which requires sloppy identity under ellipsis.
(40) | Harryi hid in the alley, [only PROi to be found a minute later], and Dudley did, too. |
‘and Dudleyj hid, only PROj/*i to be found, too’ |
That NOC is not permitted is demonstrated in (41). In each of these sentences, control by non-c-commanding arguments or implicit entities is impossible, despite the strange meanings subject control results in.
(41) | a. | #The meal was devoured, [only PRO to discover it was poisoned]. |
b. | #The side-door on the plane was opened [only PRO to realize that my parachute wasn’t fastened properly]. | |
c. | #The sun rose, [only PRO to find that ice now covered the camp]. | |
d. | #My parachute opened, [only PRO to realize that it was torn]. |
Since they allow inanimate controllers and require sloppy identity under ellipsis, and because they do not allow implicit or non-c-commanding controllers, telic clauses appear to require OC.
3.4 Interim summary
As summarized in Table 2, there is strong evidence that response clauses, OPCs, and absolutives follow the pattern of RatCs and temporal adjuncts in allowing both OC and NOC. However, SOAs are restricted to NOC, and goal clauses, SPCs, and telic clauses require OC.
Adjunct | OC | NOC | ||
---|---|---|---|---|
inanimate controllers? | sloppy/bound required? | non-c-comm. controllers? | implicit control? | |
RatCs | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | |
Temporal | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | |
Response | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
OPCs | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
Absolutives | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ |
SOAs | ✗ | (✗) | ✓ | ✓ |
Goal | ✓ | ✓ | ✗ | ✗ |
SPCs | ✓ | ✓ | ✗ | ✗ |
Telic | ✓ | ✓ | ✗ | ✗ |
4 The TTC and strict OC adjuncts
Landau (2017) demonstrates that RatCs and temporal adjuncts allow both OC and NOC, and I have argued that the same is true of response clauses, object-gap purpose clauses, and absolutive adjuncts. Under the TTC, this is expected, since adjuncts are unselected and should be free to adjoin with either a predicative (OC) or logophoric (NOC) structure. However, I have also argued that SOAs only allow NOC, and that goal clauses, SPCs, and telic clauses are all restricted to OC, despite the fact that they too, as adjuncts, are unselected.
As suggested in §3.2; SOAs may adjoin too high in the structure for predicative control by any argument of the host clause. This section attempts to address the challenge of strict OC adjuncts. Strict OC is only predicted if the structure and/or context of evaluation of the adjunct is selected by some element of the matrix clause, or if a logophoric structure is ruled out for independent reasons. Otherwise, the adjunct should be free to adjoin with either a predicative or logophoric structure. Accordingly, here I consider and reject two potential explanations for strict OC adjuncts within the TTC. First, perhaps what appear to be OC adjuncts are actually complements of the matrix verb. Second, perhaps strict OC adjuncts are too small to project the structure necessary for logophoric NOC. As neither of these solutions prove sufficient, I propose an alternative within the MTC in §5.
4.1 Strict OC “adjuncts” actually complements?
One way to explain the strict OC status of goal clauses, SPCs, and telic clauses is to say that they are in fact complements of the matrix verb, selected to have a predicative structure. Although tests of argumenthood are not infallible, if these clauses were complements of the verb, then we would expect them to sit lower in the structure than true adjuncts that allow both OC and NOC.
One diagnostic for attachment height is whether the adjunct can be stranded after a do so anaphor in ellipsis, which is standardly assumed to replace a vP (Aelbrecht & Harwood 2015). If strict OC “adjuncts” are actually complements, then they should not be able to be stranded when the vP is elided (Whelpton 1995; DeArmond & Hedberg 1998). Example (42) demonstrates that this is the case for goal clauses. Here, the goal clause must be included in the interpretation of do so.14 The intended interpretation of (42) is that Max puts great effort into avoiding work, and Billy puts great effort into avoiding confrontation.
(42) | *Max works hard [to avoid work] and Billy does so [to avoid confrontation]. |
This is distinct from the similar (43), which contains a RatC and has the meaning that Max literally works hard, and so does Billy. Unlike the goal clause in (42), the RatC in (43) adjoins outside the vP, and can therefore be excluded from the do so anaphor’s interpretation.
(43) | Max works hard (in order) to earn a living, and Billy does so (in order) to use up excess energy. |
SPCs have also been argued to be VP-internal (Jones 1991; Whelpton 1995; Landau 2013) and cannot be stranded outside do so without taking on a RatC interpretation (44).
(44) | a. | *Jon bought a shelf [to hold books], and Bill did so [to hold trophies]. |
b. | *Jon bought one [to hold books], and Bill did so [to hold trophies]. |
This contrasts with most adjuncts that allow both OC and NOC (henceforth ‘OC/NOC adjuncts’). RatCs, temporal adjuncts, response clauses, and absolutives may all be stranded after do so. This is illustrated for RatCs in (43) and the remaining adjuncts in (45).
(45) | a. | Harry left the classroom [before starting the exam], but Hermione only did so [after finishing it]. |
b. | Last month Billy’s mom washed the car for him [for working so hard in school], and yesterday his dad did so [for passing his exams]. | |
c. | Peter got into Harvard, [having been the best student in school], and, surprisingly, Bill did so, too, [having been the worst]. |
However, there are several problems with claiming that strict OC adjuncts are actually complements. First, this cannot be true of telic clauses, which are also strictly OC. In contrast to goal clauses and SPCs, telic clauses can be stranded after a do so anaphor (46). Whelpton (1995) argues that this is because telic clauses adjoin at the level of IP, which is well outside the selectional domain of the verb, making it impossible for telic clauses to actually be verbal complements.
(46) | ?Ute cooked beef for the dinner party, only to realize that her guests were vegetarian, and Nick did so too, only to realize that they were Hindu. (Whelpton 1995: 117) |
Furthermore, even the claim that goal clauses and SPCs are complements is untenable, in large part because these clauses are always optional, as (47) demonstrates.
(47) | a. | Sami plays (PROi to win). | Goal |
b. | I bought this shelfi (PROi to hold books). | SPC | |
c. | Harryi opened the letter (only PROi to discover it wasn’t for him). | Telic |
Still, perhaps these are are simply optional complements, similar to the complement of verbs like eat in (48) (Fillmore 1986).
(48) | I’ve already eaten (breakfast). |
This is still doubtful, though, since unlike eat, which implies a complement even when none is pronounced, there is no implication of a silent complement in any of the examples in (47) when the clause in question is absent. In addition, these clauses can appear with a wide range of matrix predicates, and it is unlikely that all of them take these clauses as optional complements, especially since a single matrix predicate can appear with more than one. If these adjuncts were actually complements, the verb bought in (49), for example, would have to select both an optional OPC and an optional telic clause. The same would have to be true for any verb that takes one or more of these clauses, which leads to positing a large number of otherwise unmotivated silent arguments.
(49) | I bought that shelf (to hold books) (only to return it the next day). |
On the other hand, it was noted in §3.1.1 that response clauses are sometimes understood as conceptual “arguments” of blame-class predicates. And yet response clauses still allow both OC and NOC. Therefore, stating that goal clauses, SPCs or telic clauses are strictly OC because they are conceptual arguments of the verb leads one to question why response clauses are not also strictly OC.
Furthermore, regardless of (non-)argumenthood, attachment height on its own cannot be the determining factor for whether an adjunct demonstrates strict OC. Although two of the strict OC adjuncts adjoin within the vP and most of the OC/NOC adjuncts adjoin above it, strict OC telic clauses adjoin above the vP (46), and as (50) demonstrates, OPCs, which allow both OC and NOC, adjoin low, within the vP.
(50) | *Chandler bought Monicai a frying panj [PROi to cook with tj], and Ross did so [PROi to hit people with tj]. |
As summarized in Table 3, due to OPCs and telic clauses, there is no clean distinction between attachment height and control status. Even disregarding these anomalies, there would be no good explanation for why low attachment should result in strict OC under the TTC.
Adjunct | Status | Height |
---|---|---|
RatCs | OC/NOC | above vP |
Temporal | OC/NOC | above vP |
Response | OC/NOC | above vP |
OPCs | OC/NOC | below vP |
Absolutives | OC/NOC | above vP |
SOAs | strict NOC | above TP |
Goal | strict OC | below vP |
SPCs | strict OC | below vP |
Telic | strict OC | above vP |
In sum, since telic clauses adjoin so high, they cannot be optional arguments of the verb. Low adjoining strict OC adjuncts also are unlikely to actually be verbal arguments, since they can appear with such a wide variety of matrix predicates, and because such “arguments” are not implied in the meaning of the predicate when it appears without one of these clauses. And even if the TTC had a reason why it should matter, attachment site on its own also cannot be the determining factor for strict OC.
4.2 Strict OC adjuncts too small for logophoric control?
Since strict OC adjuncts cannot be complements, the TTC requires some other explanation for why they are restricted to predicative control. Landau (2015: 97) hints in a footnote at one possibility, suggesting that nonclausal adjuncts including participles “do not project the functional structure needed to mediate NOC.” Perhaps the structure of strict OC adjuncts is simply too small to allow logophoric control, and they are restricted to the FinP structure in (51a). Adjuncts that allow both OC and NOC, on the other hand, would need to be able to optionally project a logophoric CP level, as in (51b).
(51) | a. | [FinP λx [Fin′ Fin [TP x …]]] | (OC) |
b. | [CP pro C+log [FinP λx [Fin′ Fin [TP x …]]]] | (NOC) |
Of the adjuncts that allow both OC and NOC, there is strong evidence that OPCs and RatCs can project a CP.15 In OPCs, the object gap has been argued to be the result of empty operator movement to the CP, as in (52) (Chomsky 1980; E. Williams 1980; 1992; Whelpton 2002).
(52) | I left itj in [heri mailbox] [CP Opj [PROi to look over tj]]. |
In addition, an overt complementizer is possible in OPCs, at least when there is also a lexical subject (53). The same is true of RatCs (54), suggesting that they, too, have a full CP structure.
(53) | I left iti in the mailbox [CP for her to look over ti]. |
(54) | Harry had to go to school [in order [CP for him to become a great wizard]]. |
In contrast, goal clauses and SPCs, two of the strict OC adjuncts, do not allow overt complementizers or lexical subjects (55). Although it does not result in ungrammaticality, including an overt complementizer and lexical subject forces the adjunct to take on a RatC interpretation. Perhaps, then, these adjuncts are indeed restricted to predicative OC simply because they do not project the necessary structure to support logophoric NOC.
(55) | a. | Max works hard [for his family to have food to eat]. | (*Goal) |
b. | I bought this blender [for it to help me make soup]. | (*Purpose) |
However, the same cannot be true of telic clauses. Because telic clauses allow an overt complementizer (56), they must be able to project a full CP. Because of this, the TTC would need some other explanation for why logophoric control is not allowed here, even though it is possible in other adjuncts that project CPs.
(56) | Harry hid in the alley, [only for the Dementors to find him a minute later]. |
Another problem for using clause size alone to determine control properties is found in absolutive adjuncts and some SOAs, as neither allows an overt complementizer without changing the meaning of the adjunct (57). Because absolutives adjoin as bare participles, and SOAs can as well, they are exactly the kind of adjunct that should be restricted to predicative OC. However, NOC is possible with absolutives, and is required with SOAs.
(57) | a. | [(*For/with me) sitting in class the day after the party], my eyes refused to stay open. |
b. | [(*For/with me) judging from experience], Jon would be better off without Mary. |
As stated above, SOAs may adjoin too high in the structure for predicative control, which requires c-command by the controller. However, if SOAs, as well as absolutives, do not project a CP level, then it is unclear how they would be able to support a logophoric NOC structure, regardless of whether OC is possible. Furthermore, if these adjuncts do allow NOC despite their small structure, then it is unclear why a small clause size should restrict goal clauses and SPCs from similarly permitting NOC.
The clause size evidence discussed in this section is summarized in Table 4. Because some smaller adjuncts (absolutives and SOAs) allow NOC, and some larger adjuncts (telic clauses) are restricted to OC, using clause size alone to determine whether logophoric control will be possible is problematic. If RatCs and temporal adjuncts can project a CP and therefore permit both OC and NOC, what restricts telic clauses from doing likewise? And if NOC occurs only when a logophoric CP is projected, how is it that absolutives and SOAs arrive at logophoric interpretations with smaller structures?
Adjunct | Status | CP? |
---|---|---|
RatCs | OC/NOC | ✓ |
OPCs | OC/NOC | ✓ |
Absolutives | OC/NOC | ✗ |
SOAs | strict NOC | ✗ |
Goal | strict OC | ✗ |
SPCs | strict OC | ✗ |
Telic | strict OC | ✓ |
4.3 Summary
Although Landau (2017) only discussed RatCs and temporal adjuncts, if extended to other adjuncts, his analysis of adjunct control predicts that all adjuncts should allow both OC and NOC. This account can therefore, of course, easily account for adjuncts where this is true. Difficulties arise, however, with adjuncts exhibiting only OC. These adjuncts cannot feasibly be selected as arguments of the matrix verb, and a claim that they simply have too small a structure to support a logophoric CP falls apart when considering telic clauses, which are strictly OC despite their larger structure, and absolutives and SOAs, which allow NOC despite their small structure.16
The following section discusses an alternative account of adjunct control within the MTC.
5 The movement theory of control
5.1 Background on the MTC
The Movement Theory of Control (MTC) (Hornstein 1999; Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes 2010a) is prototypical of many syntactic theories of control in that it establishes a specific syntactic dependency (in this case movement) between PRO and its antecedent in OC structures. OC differs from NOC in that in the former, what is traditionally labeled PRO is the trace of movement of the controller from the embedded to the matrix clause, while in the latter, PRO is the null pronominal pro.
A simplified derivation of OC in complements is given in (58). In this example, Jon moves from the subject position of the embedded buy to the subject position of the matrix want, receiving the θ-feature of both verbs. In this way, Jon is understood as both the wanter and the buyer.
(58) | Joni wants [Joni to buy a car]. |
OC in adjuncts is handled similarly, the only difference being that adjunct control requires sideward movement (Nunes 1995), in which an element moves from one syntactic object to the root of another within a single derivation, as illustrated in (59).
(59) | Derivation of adjunct control | |
(simplified from Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes 2010a: 88) | ||
a. | Applications of select, merge, and copy: | |
PP = [after John eating lunch] | ||
VP = [saw Mary] | ||
b. | Copying of John: | |
PP = [after John eating lunch] | ||
VP = [saw Mary] | ||
N = John | ||
c. | Merger of John and VP: | |
PP = [after John eating lunch] | ||
VP = [John saw Mary] | ||
d. | Applications of select, merge, and copy, plus deletion in phonological component: | |
TP = [John [vP [vP John saw Mary][PP after John eating lunch]]] |
The MTC as originally formulated does not distinguish between predicative and logophoric control in complements, the distinction that provided the major motivation for the TTC.17 As there is growing evidence for (at least) two different types of complement control, several approaches have argued for a hybrid theory involving complement control via movement in some cases, and via other mechanisms such as restructuring in others (see, e.g. Cinque 2006; Grano 2015; Sheehan 2018). Because control via restructuring is unlikely to be involved in adjuncts, I will put aside the issue of how the MTC can account for the different types of OC in complements, instead focusing on the derivation of OC via movement versus NOC via pronominalization in adjuncts.
5.1.1 OC preferred over NOC
According to Hornstein (1999; 2001; 2003), pronominalization resulting in NOC is more “costly” than OC by movement, and is only possible as a last-resort option when movement is blocked. However, the last-resort status of pronominalization as originally formulated is too strong, as it would rule out any case of NOC in adjuncts in favor of OC by the matrix subject, which could arise through sideward movement. Boeckx & Hornstein (2007) acknowledge a similar problem. If pronominalization were strictly last-resort, then (60a) should be ruled out due to the availability of (60b), which Hornstein & Kiguchi (2003) argue arises through movement.
(60) | a. | Johni said that [proi washing himselfi delighted Mary]. |
b. | John said that [PROi washing herselfi delighted Maryi]. |
To allow both sentences, Boeckx & Hornstein (2007) propose that pronominalization is only ruled out when movement could not establish the same interpretation (see also Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes 2010a). Thus, NOC is allowed even when OC is available, as long as NOC results in an interpretation that OC could not have.18 However, OC may also be preferred more generally. Boeckx & Hornstein assume that parsers are transparent with respect to grammars, meaning that if a grammar has a preference, then the parser will respect that preference. When a comprehender reaches a gap in the incremental processing of a sentence with a control structure, they will prefer to posit a trace of movement if possible rather than a null pronoun, all things being equal. The pronominalization and interpretation in (61b) is not ruled out by the grammar, but because parsers would prefer to posit a trace as the null subject of the adjunct, resulting in (61a).
(61) | a. | Johni kissed Maryj without PROi/*j getting embarrassed. |
b. | Johni kissed Maryj without pro*i/j getting embarrassed. |
There is therefore a difference between a derivation being ungrammatical because the grammatical system cannot produce it, and one that is unacceptable because parsers would never choose that derivation over a preferred alternative. The strong preference for OC in adjunct control is due in part to a grammatical constraint requiring OC if it is possible for a given interpretation, and in part due to a parsing preference for positing traces over null pronouns in incremental processing. This combination results in a general preference for OC over NOC.
Boeckx & Hornstein (2007) and Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes (2010a) argue that parsers are completely transparent to grammatical constraints, and that if it is possible to posit a trace in a given position, parsers must do so. This would explain why examples such as (62) only allow OC by the matrix subject, even when it results in a strange interpretation. Upon encountering the empty category in the adjunct, it is possible to posit a trace linked to the matrix subject, so parsers must do so.
(62) | #The banki was robbed [while PROi/*j being smart not to raise the alarm]. | |
(Landau 2017: 7) |
However, this does not explain why the same is not true in any of the examples in (63). Evidently, parsers are able to override the preference for a trace in at least some circumstances, even when a trace in the relevant position would be possible. This cannot be due to structural properties of the sentence alone, since the sentences in (63) permit either a trace (OC) or a pronominal (NOC) without changing the structure (see Green in press). Instead, structural, discourse, and processing factors all compete in determining the probability of OC or NOC.
(63) | a. | The presidenti was elected [without PROi/j considering his competence]. (Roeper 1987: 297) |
b. | The pooli was the perfect temperature [after PROi/j being in the hot sun all day]. | |
c. | The potatoesi were tastier [after PRO#i eating carrots]. |
An example of the interaction of such constraints is given in Boeckx & Hornstein (2007), where it was argued that NOC is available in (60a) despite the availability of OC in (60b) because at the point where the empty category is encountered, if parsers posited a trace, they would not yet be able to assign it a referent; the only positions that something could have moved to from that position come later in the sentence. The preference to quickly assign reference to dependent elements (Nicol & Swinney 1989; Badecker & Straub 2002) is in competition with the preference for a trace, resulting in the possibility of either a trace or a pronominal. Similar competition may be involved in NOC cases of adjunct control.
5.1.2 Difference between complements and OC/NOC adjuncts
The MTC assumes that OC is preferred over NOC due to a grammatical constraint that rules out NOC for any interpretation that could have arisen through movement, and to a parsing preference rules out NOC in general when OC is available. For some adjuncts, this preference can be overridden in the proper context. But the same is not true for complements. Why should complements and adjuncts differ in this respect under the MTC? The only difference in the derivation of complement control and adjunct control is that the former involves upward movement and the latter sideward movement. I propose that adjuncts are more likely to permit NOC than complements because sideward movement is for some reason more “costly” than upward movement. This would lead to the preference scale for the derivation of control represented in (64).19
(64) | Preference scale for derivations of control: |
upward OC ≫ sideward OC ≫ NOC via pronominalization |
The additional cost of sideward movement reduces the parser’s preference for traces over pros, which in turn makes it more likely that NOC will be permitted if contextual or other constraints favor it. But what is the source of the preferences in (64)? Why would sideward movement be more costly than upward movement? As discussed above, the preference for OC over NOC is in large part due to processing. This accounts for why NOC is lowest on the scale. Might the preference for upward versus sideward movement also be the result of processing biases? Perhaps sentences involving sideward movement are simply more difficult to process than sentences with upward movement. One reason why this might be the case begins with the fact that adjuncts are optional. Because they are optional, they may be less predictable. And if they are less predictable, a comprehender will have less of an expectation, at the matrix verb, of needing to form a control dependency, than when the verb selects a control complement. But even if this is true, why should online predictability have anything to do with what interpretations are licit or available offline? There is no logical connection here, so the effect would simply have to be stipulated. Unlike the preference for OC over NOC, this effect cannot be reduced to other known parsing preferences, such as the preference for local versus distant antecedents or the preference for syntactic versus discourse dependencies. Therefore, stating that (64) is due exclusively to processing preferences is tenuous.
It is also not immediately clear what grammatical constraints would result in (64). Both upward and sideward movement involve copy and re-merger of an element of the growing syntactic structure. Neither involves more steps or even different underlying operations that could lead to a greater cost. There is only one real difference between the two that could cause a cost difference: sideward movement involves copying an element from one tree and moving it to the root of another (65a), while upward movement involves copying from and re-merging to the same tree (65b).
(65) | a. | |
b. |
Perhaps sideward movement incurs a derivational penalty akin to the one that has been posited for moving out of islands (Chomsky 1972; Lasnik 2001). This could, perhaps, simply be the result of the fact that sideward movement requires forming a syntactic dependency between two separate workspaces, so to speak, in the derivation. Or it could have something to do with constraints on proper movement. Although I do not speculate further on the exact nature or source of this penalty, let us simply suppose by hypothesis that there is a penalty for moving an element from within one tree to the root of another, unconnected tree. Suppose, furthermore, that this penalty is weak,20 and does not cause the derivation to crash, but instead results in a lower “degree of grammaticality” or acceptability (Epstein 1990; see also Chomsky 1965; 1986; Lasnik & Saito 1984). Because both upward and sideward movement can lead to convergent derivations, both may result in grammatical strings; those involving sideward movement are simply lower on the scale between completely acceptable by the parser and completely unacceptable.
If this hypothesis is on the right track, the preference for upward OC versus sideward OC is due to a weak grammatical constraint against movement to a non-c-commanding position. Assuming there is some performance penalty associated with this grammatical violation, the lower grammatical status of sideward OC makes its appeal relative to NOC weaker than upward movement’s. This in turn leads to a greater probability of both OC and NOC being accepted in OC/NOC adjuncts than in complements, since adjuncts involve sideward movement, while in complements, movement is upward.
Admittedly, positing that sideward movement is more costly than upward movement is somewhat stipulative. But something like it as part of the scale in (64) would be required in order to capture the differing availability of NOC in complement and adjunct control under the MTC. And interestingly, the idea that sideward movement results in a greater likelihood of NOC has independent support in the examples from Boeckx & Hornstein (2007) in (60), repeated in (66). This structure allows both OC and NOC, and importantly, Boeckx & Hornstein argue that the OC derivation in (66b) involves sideward movement. This is consistent with the idea that OC derived from sideward movement is less strongly preferred to NOC than OC derived from upward movement is, and that this contributes to NOC also being possible.
(66) | a. | Johni said that [proi washing himselfi delighted Mary]. |
b. | John said that [PROi washing herselfi delighted Maryi]. |
Finally, Hornstein (2001) assumes an Uriagereka (1999)-style adjunction in which adjuncts are linearized and therefore become islands before being merged with the main clause (see also Nunes 2001). If this is the case for all adjuncts, then all cases of OC in adjuncts will necessarily involve sideward movement. And because sideward movement is “costly”, NOC through pronominalization should be possible in the right context. Under these assumptions, the MTC makes the incorrect prediction that all adjuncts should allow both OC and NOC. The MTC therefore does just as well as the TTC on adjuncts that allow both OC and NOC, while struggling with strict OC adjuncts. In the following section, I outline a proposal for how the MTC can deal with low-adjoining strict OC adjuncts.
5.2 The MTC and strict OC adjuncts
Goal clauses (67a), SPCs (67b), and telic clauses (67c) all exhibit strict OC.
(67) | a. | Maxi works hard [PROi to stay out of jail]. |
b. | I bought this blenderi [PROi to help me make split pea soup]. | |
c. | Harryi opened the letteri [only PROi to discover it wasn’t for him]. |
Under the version of the MTC outlined above, strict OC is only expected if upward movement from the “PRO” position to the controller position is possible. For adjuncts, upward movement requires two conditions. First, the adjunct must not (yet) be an island to movement, and second, it must adjoin lower than the base position of the controller. I will discuss each of these in turn.
First, according to Uriagereka (1999), Hornstein (2001), and Nunes (2001), the non-finite clauses in (67), as adjuncts, should be atomized (made a single syntactic atom) prior to or upon adjunction. If this is the case, upward movement after adjunction should be impossible. But there is evidence that immediate atomization does not automatically occur with adjunction: CED island effects (Huang 1982) in adjuncts are often weak or nonexistent (Truswell 2007; Sheehan 2013). This is true not only of strict OC adjuncts (68), but also of at least some OC/NOC adjuncts (69). Because movement out of adjuncts is sometimes possible, it cannot be the case that they are always atomized prior to adjunction.
(68) | a. | Whati did Max work hard [to do ti]? |
b. | Whati did you buy this blender [to help you make ti]? |
(69) | a. | Whati did you go to the store [in order to buy ti]? |
b. | Whati did you give Jake flowers [for doing ti]? |
Second, if adjuncts allow extraction, then upward movement for control may be possible as long as the base position of the controller in the matrix clause is higher than the adjunction point. SPCs and goal clauses each were demonstrated above to adjoin within the vP based on their obligatory inclusion in the interpretation of do so anaphors (telic clauses are an exception, and will be discussed in §5.3). Relevant examples are repeated in (70), each of which can only have a RatC interpretation, and is ungrammatical otherwise.
(70) | a. | Max works hard [to avoid work] and Billy does so [to avoid confrontation]. | (*Goal clause) |
b. | Jon bought a shelf [to hold books], and Bill did so [to hold trophies]. | (*SPC) |
This places goal clauses clearly under the merge position of the subject in spec-vP, whether they adjoin to an intermediate projection of v, as in (71a), or whether they adjoin to or within the VP, as in (71b).
(71) | a. | |
b. |
As for the SPC in (67b), which has control by the object, the controller is not base-generated in the vP, but as an object of V. Kratzer (1996), following Larson (1988), proposes that objects of verbs are base-generated as specifiers of V. If that is the case, and if adjuncts may still adjoin to the V′ level, as Whelpton (1995) argues, then these adjuncts too may adjoin lower than the base position of the controller, as in (72).
(72) |
Assuming that goal clauses and SPCs adjoin with structures similar to (71) and (72) and that adjuncts are not always atomized prior to adjunction, these clauses are in a position where upward movement from the controllee position to the controller position is possible.21 Because upward movement is possible, it will be strongly preferred to pronominalization, and NOC will be ruled out.
In contrast, OC in adjuncts that allow both OC and NOC involves sideward movement. RatCs, temporal adjuncts, response clauses, and absolutives all adjoin higher than strict OC adjuncts, outside the vP, as demonstrated by the fact that they can be stranded after do so.
(73) | a. | Malfoy took off on his broom [in order to show off] and Harry did so [in order to help Neville]. |
b. | Harry left the classroom [before starting the exam], but Hermione only did so [after finishing it]. | |
c. | Last month Billy’s mom washed the car for him [for working so hard in school], and yesterday his dad did so [for passing his exams]. | |
d. | Peter left the party [having danced with many partners], and Paul did so [having been rejected by everyone]. |
Because these adjuncts adjoin outside the vP, they are positioned higher than the base position of the matrix arguments. Therefore, the only way for movement to occur between the adjunct and the base position of the controller, whether the subject or the object, is through sideward movement, as illustrated in (74) for subject control. Because of this, the preference for OC is reduced, and NOC is also available in the right context.
(74) |
But as mentioned above, attachment height cannot be the sole determining factor. OPCs allow both OC and NOC, but cannot be stranded outside do so (75). They therefore adjoin lower than other OC/NOC adjuncts, in the same domain as the low-adjoining strict OC adjuncts.
(75) | *Chandler bought Monicai a frying panj [PROi to cook with tj], and Ross did so [PROi to hit people with tj]. |
However, unlike the strict OC adjuncts, OPCs may be linearized before adjunction and therefore act as islands to movement afterwards. That this is the case is suggested by the fact that CED effects are strong in OPCs.
(76) | a. | Chandler bought Monica a knife [to cut something with]. |
b. | *Whati did Chandler buy Monica a knife [to cut ti with]? |
One possible reason for this is that OPCs have a larger structure than low-adjoining strict OC adjuncts (see §4.2), and may therefore be atomized as CP phases (Chomsky 2001) prior to adjunction. Strict OC adjuncts that are smaller than CPs are only linearized upon merger of the next phase head.
This proposal derives the strict OC status of goal clauses and SPCs. These adjuncts are strictly OC because they permit upward movement from the adjunct to the base position of the controller, and therefore the preference for OC over NOC is strong. This is in contrast to OC/NOC adjuncts, which require sideward movement for OC, either because they are atomized prior to adjunction, as is the case with OPCs, or because they adjoin too high, as is true of the other OC/NOC adjuncts. Although OC may still be preferred, this preference is weaker than in strict OC adjuncts due to the fact that it is derived via sideward movement, resulting in the possibility of NOC.
Table 5 summarizes how the type of movement involved in the control dependency interacts with the control status of the adjunct. RatCs, temporal adjuncts, response clauses, and absolutives all involve sideward movement because of their attachment height above the base position of the verb’s arguments. OPCs also involve sideward movement, not because of attachment height, but because they are linearized prior to adjunction, possibly due to their larger clause size. In each case, sideward movement leads to both OC and NOC being possible. In contrast, goal clauses and SPCs both adjoin low and are not linearized prior to adjunction. Upward movement is therefore possible, resulting in strict OC.
Adjunct | Status | Height | CP? | Movement |
---|---|---|---|---|
RatCs | OC/NOC | above vP | ✓ | sideward |
Temporal | OC/NOC | above vP | sideward | |
Response | OC/NOC | above vP | sideward | |
OPCs | OC/NOC | below vP | ✓ | sideward |
Absolutives | OC/NOC | above vP | ✗ | sideward |
SOAs | strict NOC | above TP | ✗ | |
Goal | strict OC | below vP | ✗ | upward |
SPCs | strict OC | below vP | ✗ | upward |
Telic | strict OC | above vP | ✓ |
In what follows, I will discuss SOAs and telic clauses, which present challenges to this proposal.
5.3 Remaining challenges
The MTC is able to account for OC/NOC adjuncts, as well as low-adjoining strict OC adjuncts. However, there are at least two potential problem cases for the current proposal: SOAs, which are strictly NOC, and telic clauses, which require OC but adjoin too high for upward movement.
5.3.1 Speaker-oriented adverbials
It was noted above that PRO in SOAs such as those in (77) can only refer to the speaker, which is evidence for their being restricted to logophoric NOC.
(77) | a. | [PRO To be honest], Jon would be better off without Mary. |
b. | [PRO Judging from experience], Jon will be better off without Mary. |
The explanation offered for the TTC was that since SOAs adjoin high in the clause, above the position of the matrix subject, as in (78), the adjunct is too high for a sentential argument to predicatively control PRO. Logophoric control is therefore the only option. However, if having a small clause size results in strict OC, as briefly suggested in Landau (2015) and as explored above, then SOAs still present a problem for the TTC, since they can adjoin as bare participials and still exhibit strict NOC.
(78) |
Intuitively, it seems that a height-based explanation of the strict NOC status of SOAs should be able to apply to the MTC. With the structure in (78), PRO is not c-commanded by any matrix argument. Movement out of that position to the main clause would then result in an ill-formed chain, since the head of the chain would not c-command the tail (Chomsky 1995). Although the same is true initially for all cases of sideward movement, here the problem is more serious, since even at the end of the derivation, the final position of the moving element does not c-command the trace in the adjunct.
However, Hornstein & Kiguchi (2003) argue that c-command is not required for sideward movement. They argue that examples like (79) involve OC via sideward movement, and yet PRO’s controller does not c-command it, even on the surface. And this is not limited to psych-verbs, as might be assumed based on theories such as that of Belletti & Rizzi (1988), since PRO in (80) is also not c-commanded by its OC antecedent (Norbert Hornstein, p.c.).
(79) | John said [that [PROi washing herself] delighted Maryi]. |
(80) | [PROi Brushing her teeth] made Maryi late for the movie. |
If OC does not actually require c-command, then it is not clear why in SOAs the matrix subject should not be able to sideward move from the adjunct into the main clause, as in (81).
(81) |
Importantly, however, it is also unclear how the TTC would explain the OC properties of (79) and (80). If predication requires c-command, then predicative OC should be impossible. Logophoric OC would also be insufficient, since it is unclear what would restrict the logophoric context of the non-finite clause to one representing Mary’s perspective. In fact, the sentence could easily be representing the opinion of a separate individual, such as John in (79). Therefore, if Hornstein & Kiguchi’s arguments are right, and (79) and (80) do exhibit OC, then the TTC must also admit that OC does not require c-command, leaving no good explanation of SOAs. If, on the other hand, Hornstein & Kiguchi are incorrect, and these examples do not involve OC, then the same explanation proposed for the TTC will work in the MTC, namely that SOAs adjoin too high for OC to occur.
Under either account, the restriction of SOAs to NOC may also be due to other factors. One possibility is that there is a functional head high in the structure where SOAs adjoin that requires the adjunct to represent the perspective of the speaker (Cinque 1999). Unless the matrix subject is also the speaker, this would require NOC in order to satisfy the demands of that functional head.
5.3.2 Telic clauses
Finally, telic clauses likely involve sideward movement, and yet appear to be restricted to OC. Strict OC in an adjunct is only expected under the MTC if that adjunct attaches lower than the base position of the controller and is not linearized prior to adjunction, thus allowing control via upward movement. But as discussed in §4.1, Whelpton (1995) provides evidence that telic clauses adjoin at the IP level, well outside the merge position of the subject within the vP. Because of this, the only way for OC to occur would be through sideward movement, as in (82).
(82) |
Because sideward movement is required, the account presented here predicts that NOC should be possible in telic clauses given the right context. In order to account for the strict OC status of telic clauses, the MTC would either have to say that they attach lower than Whelpton (1995) thought, claim that NOC is ruled out for some other reason, or provide evidence that has eluded me that NOC is possible. Importantly, though, the TTC account in §4 is also unable to account for telic clauses, since there is no way that they could be arguments of the matrix predicate, and they appear to be at least as large as a CP, which should be sufficient to allow a logophoric structure. I leave further investigation of telic clauses to future research.
6 Conclusion
Landau (2017) provided good evidence that RatCs and temporal adjuncts allow both OC and NOC (see also Green in press). A simple hypothesis would be that the same is true for all other adjuncts as well. This paper has shown that such a hypothesis is too general. Some adjuncts are restricted only to one type of control, either OC or NOC. Although an explanation within the TTC for strict NOC adjuncts is possible due to their adjunction height, strict OC adjuncts present a more serious challenge. I have proposed an alternative within the MTC which is better able to account for the strict OC status of low-adjoining adjuncts.
Although Landau (2017) only deals with RatCs and temporal adjuncts, extending his account leads to the prediction that an adjunct will only be restricted to OC if it is too small to support a logophoric CP, or if it is not an adjunct at all, but a complement. Neither of these conditions can suitably explain strict OC adjuncts. As demonstrated in §4, strict OC adjuncts cannot actually be complements. Incorporating the idea that control properties are due to the size of the adjunct does better, but the account then faces issues with absolutives, SOAs, and telic clauses. If strict OC adjuncts were restricted to OC simply because their structure is too small for NOC, then absolutives and SOAs, which adjoin as bare adverbials, should also demonstrate strict OC. Under the TTC, it is unclear why these would allow NOC, while other small adjuncts that adjoin lower do not. It is also unclear why telic clauses, which have a full CP structure, would be restricted to OC.
The MTC is able to explain all of the OC/NOC adjuncts, including absolutives, as well as most of the strict OC adjuncts, although like the TTC it still struggles with telic clauses. For strict OC adjuncts, if the adjunct adjoins low enough, it will allow upward movement from the controllee to the controller position, unless it is atomized prior to adjunction, as is the case with OPCs. Because upward movement makes OC more strongly preferred than sideward movement does, possibly due to sideward movement incurring a weak grammatical penalty, these adjuncts are expected to require OC just as strongly as complement control does. As for why absolutives allow both OC and NOC despite their small structure, this account argues that they adjoin higher than the base position of the matrix subject and therefore require sideward movement for OC. This reduces the preference for OC, which increases the availability of NOC. Low-adjoining strict OC adjuncts permit upward movement, preventing pronominalization and NOC.
Importantly, this account is able to explain the correlation between adjunction height and control properties. Under the TTC, the fact that most strict OC adjuncts adjoin lower than OC/NOC adjuncts should not matter, since they all adjoin low enough to be predicated of the matrix subject in its final position. Unless these adjuncts were actually complements, which I have argued is not the case, the low adjunction of strict OC adjuncts would be a coincidence. But under the MTC, this property, in conjunction with their small structure, is what derives their strict OC status. The only strict OC adjunct that the MTC struggles with is the telic clause, but the TTC also had no good explanation for it.
The study of control has most frequently focused on cases where the controlled clause is the complement of a main clause verb. Theories of the control relation and of controller choice have been built largely on the properties of complement control, and adjuncts have often been ignored. In many syntactic theories of control such as the predominant version of the MTC, it is assumed that adjunct control will display the same properties as complement control (Hornstein 1999; Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes 2010a). Even some semantic control theories make the same assumption. For example, Farkas (1988) argued that controller choice is determined by a responsibility relation in complement control as well as in adjuncts, although her discussion of the latter is limited to RatCs. Other semantic theories of control such as that of Sag & Pollard (1991) do admit that the mechanism of controller choice in adjuncts may differ from the one involved in complement control, since they are not selected by any element of the main clause, but the discussion of adjuncts is stated as an aside, with no detailed analysis. This paper has provided evidence that adjuncts do not all behave in the same way as complements, in line with Landau (2017); while complements require OC, some adjuncts allow both OC and NOC. It is also not the case, though, that all adjuncts uniformly behave differently from complements; several adjuncts permit both OC and NOC, while others are restricted to one or the other.
In addition, it is not the case that syntactic OC and non-syntactic NOC are in complementary distribution, contrary to the assumptions of many previous theories (e.g. Manzini 1983; Boeckx & Hornstein 2007; McFadden & Sundaresan 2016). NOC can sometimes appear where OC is also possible (see also Green in press). But although both are possible in some instances, OC is still strongly preferred, all else equal. I have argued that this is due to processing preferences: under the MTC, parsers may prefer to posit a trace rather than a null pronoun when they encounter a gap (Boeckx & Hornstein 2007; Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes 2010a). But the preference for OC is not dependent on the MTC. Under the TTC, parsers may prefer OC because of its simpler structure (Landau 2017). In addition to or instead of these, OC may also be preferred to NOC due to a more general preferences for bound variable readings (Reinhart 1983; 2006), or for local (Cunnings & Sturt 2014) or recent (Cunnings, Patterson & Felser 2014) antecedents. Factors favoring NOC may include the availability of a non-local perspective-holding potential antecedent, whether OC would result in a strange interpretation (Landau 2017), attachment site of the adjunct (Landau 2013), or other factors (Green 2018).
Although this paper represents an important step toward understanding adjunct control, further work is necessary. Especially useful will be investigations of the relation between parsing preferences and grammatical distinctions in determining controller choice. This will further our knowledge of how syntactic and non-syntactic processes and sources of information interact in control and in anaphora resolution more generally.
Notes
- Culicover & Jackendoff (2001) note that for some adjuncts semantic components may be important, but their discussion is limited mainly to RatCs. See also Farkas (1988). [^]
- For simplicity, I will not generally distinguish between the labels of the null subject in OC and NOC, but their actual representation is hypothesized to differ in many theories. [^]
- This is similar to the classification system of E. Williams (1992), which also distinguishes between predicative and logophoric control, but there are important differences. [^]
- The additional layer of structure is more complicated than illustrated in (8). There are also functional elements that ensure a logophoric interpretation of the pro. See Landau (2015). [^]
- Rothstein (2004) stipulates that depictive secondary predicates combine with their hosts by a semantic rule that enforces exactly this sort of sharing. Nonetheless, this stipulation is not one that follows from the concept of temporal concurrence. [^]
- NOC is actually possible in complements with a wh-phrase in their spec-CP, as in (i). Although Landau (2015) does not address this, perhaps it has to do with the fact that wh-infinitives have a modal interpretation, which in turn leads to a generic interpretation of PRO (Bhatt 1999).
[^]
(i) Jon asked [*(how) PROi to shave oneselfi]. - Implicit control is not always possible for response clauses. In (i), PRO requires an explicit antecedent (Alexander Williams, p.c.).
I will not attempt an explanation of when implicit control is available, but note that it is not always possible for temporal adjuncts and RatCs either (see Landau 2017; Green 2018). [^]
(i) The dog barked *(at someonei) [for PROi approaching the house too quickly]. - https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Jane_Shaw, October 18, 2018. [^]
- The obligatory gap is the result of empty operator movement to the CP, illustrated in (i) (Chomsky 1980; E. Williams 1980; 1992; Whelpton 2002).
[^]
(i) [CP Opi [TP PRO to…ti…]] - A reviewer suggests that these might in fact be non-finite relative clauses, since they sometimes behave as constituents with the controlling noun (i). Crucially, however, the same control properties obtain if the controller is replaced with a pronoun or with one (ii)–(iii), in which case a relative-clause analysis is impossible.
[^]
(i) A frying pan to cook with is what Chandler bought Monica. (ii) a. Chandler bought Monicai thatj [PROi to cook with tj]. b. *That to cook with is what Chandler bought Monica. (iii) a. Chandler bought Monicai onej [PROi to cook with tj]. b. *One to cook with is what Chandler bought Monica. - A reviewer suggests that the examples in (i) may be SOAs with OC, since PRO here can be coreferential with the main clause subject.
However, although they look similar to the SOAs in (25), their semantic properties suggest otherwise. While the SOAs in (25) represent an evaluation of the content of the main clause or a degree of certainty about its truth, the adjunct in (i) represents Jon’s reason for using plastic containers, and is better analyzed as a RatC. The adjunct in (ii) expresses how the carpenter determined how many studs to use, not his evaluation or certainty of that fact, and is better analyzed as a generic absolutive (see §3.1.3). Both RatCs and absolutives allow both OC and NOC. [^]
(i) a. [PROi To be thrifty], Joni re-used the plastic container for leftovers. b. [PROi Judging from experience], the carpenteri determined how many studs to use for the wall. - In addition to these adjuncts, Huettner (1989) discusses stimulus clauses (i-a), result clauses (i-b), and exchange clauses (i-c), claiming that they display the same syntactic properties as the adjuncts I argue here to be strictly OC. For reasons of space, I do not include discussion of these adjuncts, but they too appear to exhibit strict OC.
[^]
(i) a. Maryi smiled [PROi to think what a fool she had been]. b. The dampi seeped in [PROi to chill our bones]. c. I paid Maryi ten dollars [PROi to stand on her head]. - SPCs are also similar to RatCs, especially when the latter does not include in order, but the meaning of the two adjuncts differs subtly. SPCs give the intended purpose for the theme of the matrix clause, whereas RatCs give the responsible party’s intended result of the event described. For example, the adjunct in (i) is ambiguous between an SPC and a RatC. On the SPC reading, Jack intends the car to be what makes Jill angry, not the fact that he bought it (suppose he wants her to be happy with the fact that he bought her something, but he wants her to be angry and knows the car itself will irritate her). On the RatC reading, Jack could intend the buying of the car to make Jill angry, even if he knows that the car itself will make her happy (Jill may love the car, but hate that Jack bought it for her).
SPCs also differ from transitive goal clauses as in (27d), in that an SPC gives the intended purpose of the theme, and a goal clause gives the intended purpose of the verb. [^]
(i) Jack bought Jill a car to make her angry. - In this and following examples, the intended antecedent to do so is in bold. [^]
- For space reasons, the size of temporal adjuncts and response clauses is not discussed here. [^]
- See Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes (2010a: Chapter 7) for a broader discussion on problems with selectional theories of control such as the TTC. [^]
- For other criticisms of the MTC, see Landau (2003; 2007), and Bobaljik & Landau (2009). But see Boeckx, Hornstein & Nunes (2010b) and Drummond & Hornstein (2014) for replies. [^]
- This idea is similar to a proposal from Reinhart (1983), which states that if the same meaning can be expressed using either a bound variable or a free pronoun, the bound variable will be preferred by both speakers and hearers. See Lasnik (1991); Heim (1998; 2009); Fox (2000); Reinhart (2006); Roelofsen (2008); Drummond (2011); a.o., for alternative theories and discussions on problems with Reinhart’s (1983) proposal. [^]
- Under the TTC, logophoric control involves pro even in complements, where it is OC. The preference scale in (64) is specific to the MTC, although Landau (2017) also argues that logophoric control involving pro will be less preferred than predicative control, but because of its more complex structure, not because of the pronominalization per se. [^]
- See Chomsky (1965) and Epstein (1990) for discussions on different types of violations resulting in penalties of differing strength. [^]
- Hornstein (1999) follows Nunes (1995) in assuming that the Extension Condition (Chomsky 1995) applies to adjuncts. If this is true, then an alternative derivation, whereby the subject sideward moves out of the adjunct into the matrix clause followed by low, late adjunction, is impossible. [^]
Acknowledgements
Thank you to Alexander Williams, Norbert Hornstein, and Masha Polinsky for helpful discussion, to the anonymous reviewers for their many suggestions, and to the audience at NELS 49.
Funding Information
This material is based upon work supported in part by the National Science Foundation under Grant No. 1449815.
Competing Interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
References
Aelbrecht, Lobke & William Harwood. 2015. To be or not to be elided: VP ellipsis revisited. Lingua 153. 66–97. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2014.10.006
Badecker, William & Kathleen Straub. 2002. The processing role of structural constraints on interpretation of pronouns and anaphors. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 28(28). 748–769. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1037/0278-7393.28.4.748
Belletti, Adriana & Luigi Rizzi. 1988. Psych-verbs and θ-theory. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 6(6). 291–352. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00133902
Betancort, Moisés, Manuel Carreiras & Carlos Acuña-Fariña. 2006. Processing controlled PROs in Spanish. Cognition 100(100). 217–282. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2005.04.001
Bhatt, Rajesh. 1999. Covert modality in non-finite contexts. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania dissertation.
Bobaljik, Jonathan David & Idan Landau. 2009. Icelandic control is not Amovement: The case from case. Linguistic Inquiry 40(40). 113–132. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2009.40.1.113
Boeckx, Cedric & Norbert Hornstein. 2007. On (non-)obligatory control. In William D. Davies & Stanley Dubinsky (eds.), New horizons in the analysis of control and raising, 251–262. Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-6176-9_11
Boeckx, Cedric, Norbert Hornstein & Jairo Nunes. 2010a. Control as movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511761997
Boeckx, Cedric, Norbert Hornstein & Jairo Nunes. 2010b. Icelandic control really is A-movement: Reply to Bobaljik and Landau. Linguistic Inquiry 41(41). 111–130. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/ling.2010.41.1.111
Chomsky, Noam. 1965. Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.21236/AD0616323
Chomsky, Noam. 1972. Some empirical issues in the theory of transformational grammar. In Paul Stanley Peters (ed.), Goals of linguistic theory, 63–130. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall Inc.
Chomsky, Noam. 1980. On binding. Linguistic Inquiry 11(11). 1–46. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178149.
Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110884166
Chomsky, Noam. 1986. Barriers. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262527347.001.0001
Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Michael Kenstowicz (ed.), Ken Hale: A life in language, 1–52. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo. 1999. Adverbs and functional heads: A cross-linguistic perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2006. Restructuring and functional heads (The Cartography of Syntactic Structures, vol. 4). Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.
Clark, Robin Lee. 1990. Thematic theory in syntax and interpretation. London: Routledge. DOI: http://doi.org/10.4324/9781315519890
Culicover, Peter W. & Ray Jackendoff. 2001. Control is not movement. Linguistic Inquiry 32(32). 493–512. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/002438901750372531
Cunnings, Ian, Clare Patterson & Claudia Felser. 2014. Variable binding and coreference in sentence comprehension: Evidence from eye movements. Journal of Memory & Language 71(71). 39–56. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.jml.2013.10.001
Cunnings, Ian & Patrick Sturt. 2014. Coargumenthood and the processing of reflexives. Journal of Memory & Language 75. 117–139. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.jml.2014.05.006
DeArmond, Richard C. & Nancy Hedberg. 1998. On complements and adjuncts. In Proceedings of the Canadian Linguistics Society meeting, cahiers linguistiques d’Ottawa, 95–106. Ottawa: University of Ottawa.
Drummond, Alex. 2011. Binding phenomena within a reductionist theory of grammatical dependencies. College Park, MD: University of Maryland dissertation. http://hdl.handle.net/1903/12191.
Drummond, Alex & Norbert Hornstein. 2014. Some purported problems for the movement theory of control. Linguistic Inquiry 45(45). 449–462. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00162
Epstein, Samuel David. 1990. Differentiation and reduction in syntactic theory: A case study. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 8(8). 313–323. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00135616
Ernst, Thomas. 2009. Speaker-oriented adverbs. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 27(27). 497–544. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-009-9069-1
Español-Echevarría, Manuel. 2000. The interaction of obligatory and nonobligatory control in rationale clauses. In Roger Billerey & Brook Danielle Lillehaugen (eds.), Proceedings of WCCFL 19 19. 97–110.
Fabricius-Hansen, Cathrine & Kjell Johan Sæbø. 2011. Behabitive reports. In Elke Brendel, Jörg Meibauer & Markus Steinbach (eds.), Understanding quotation, 85–106. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter Mouton. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110240085.85
Farkas, Donka F. 1988. On obligatory control. Linguistics and Philosophy 11(11). 27–58. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00635756
Fillmore, Charles J. 1971. Types of lexical information. In Danny D. Steinberg & Leon A. Jakobovits (eds.), Semantics: An interdisciplinary reader in philosophy, linguistics and psychology, 370–392. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fillmore, Charles J. 1986. Pragmatically controlled zero anaphora. In Proceedings of the twelfth annual meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, 95–107. DOI: http://doi.org/10.3765/bls.v12i0.1866
Fox, Danny. 2000. Economy and semantic interpretation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Grano, Thomas. 2015. Control and restructuring. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198703921.001.0001
Green, Jeffrey J. 2018. Adjunct control: Syntax and processing. College Park, MD: University of Maryland dissertation. http://dx.doi.org/10.13016/M2HX15V08.
Green, Jeffrey J. in press. Non-subject control of temporal adjuncts. In Proceedings of CLS 54.
Hallman, Peter. 2015. Syntactic neutralization in double object constructions. Linguistic Inquiry 46(46). 389–424. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00187
Heim, Irene. 1998. Anaphora and semantic interpretation: A reinterpretation of Reinhart’s approach. In Uli Sauerland & Orin Percus (eds.), The interpretive tract (MITWPL, vol. 25), 205–246.
Heim, Irene. 2009. Forks in the road to Rule I. In Anisa Schardl, Martin Walkow & Muhammad Abdurrahman (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 38 1. 339–358. Amherst, MA: GLSA. http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/71811.
Hornstein, Norbert. 1999. Movement and control. Linguistic Inquiry 30(30). 69–96. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/002438999553968
Hornstein, Norbert. 2001. Move! A minimalist theory of construal. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hornstein, Norbert. 2003. On control. In Randall Hendrick (ed.), Minimalist syntax, 6–81. Oxford: Blackwell. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1002/9780470758342.ch1
Hornstein, Norbert & Hirohisa Kiguchi. 2003. PRO Gate and movement. Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 8(8). 101–114.
Huang, Cheng-Teh James. 1982. Logical relations in Chinese and the theory of grammar. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation. http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/15215.
Huettner, Alison K. 1989. Adjunct infinitives in English. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts dissertation.
Janke, Vikki & Laura R. Bailey. 2017. Effects of discourse on control. Journal of Linguistics 53(53). 533–565. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226716000281
Jones, Charles. 1991. Purpose clauses: Syntax, thematics, and semantics of English purpose constructions (Studies in linguistics and philosophy, vol. 47). Dordecht: Kluwer Academic.
Kawasaki, Noriko. 1993. Control and arbitrary interpretation in English. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts dissertation.
Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from the verb. In Johann Rooryck & Laurie Zaring (eds.), Phrase structure and the lexicon, 109–137. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8617-7_5
Landau, Idan. 2003. Movement out of control. Linguistic Inquiry 34(34). 471–498. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/002438903322247560
Landau, Idan. 2007. Movement-resistant aspects of control. In William D. Davies & Stanley Dubinsky (eds.), New horizons in the analysis of control and raising (Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, vol. 71), 293–325. Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-6176-9_14
Landau, Idan. 2013. Control in generative grammar: A research companion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139061858
Landau, Idan. 2015. A two-tiered theory of control (Linguistic Inquiry Monographs, vol. 71). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262028851.001.0001
Landau, Idan. 2017. Adjunct control depends on voice. In Claire Halpert, Hadas Kotek & Coppe van Urk (eds.), A pesky set: Papers for David Pesetsky. Cambridge, MA: MITWPL.
Landau, Idan. 2018. From predication to control and back again: Lessons and puzzles. Paper presented at GLOW 41. Hungarian Academy of Science.
Larson, Richard K. 1988. On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry, 335–391. https://www.jstor.org/stable/25164901.
Lasnik, Howard. 1991. On the necessity of binding conditions. In Robert Freidin (ed.), Principles and parameters in comparative grammar, 7–28. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lasnik, Howard. 2001. When can you save a structure by destroying it? In M. Kim & U. Strauss (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 31 2. 301–320.
Lasnik, Howard & Mamoru Saito. 1984. On the nature of proper government. Linguistic Inquiry 15(15). 235–289. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178382.
Manzini, Maria Rita. 1983. On control and control theory. Linguistic Inquiry 14(14). 421–446. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178338.
Manzini, Maria Rita. 1986. On control and binding theory. In S. Berman, J-W. Choe & J. McDonough (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 16, 322–337. Amherst, MA: GLSA Publications.
McFadden, Thomas & Sandhya Sundaresan. 2016. Failure to control is not a failure: it’s pro. In Christopher Hammerly & Brandon Prickett (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 46 3. 1–10. Amherst, MA: GLSA.
Mohanan, K. P. 1983. Functional and anaphoric control. Linguistic Inquiry 14(14). 641–674. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178353.
Nicol, Janet & David Swinney. 1989. The role of structure in coreference assignment during sentence comprehension. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 18(18). 5–19. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/BF01069043
Nishigauchi, Taisuke. 1984. Control and the thematic domain. Language 60(60). 215–250. DOI: http://doi.org/10.2307/413640
Nunes, Jairo. 1995. The copy theory of movement and linearization of chains in the Minimalist Program. College Park, MD: University of Maryland dissertation.
Nunes, Jairo. 2001. Sideward movement. Linguistic Inquiry 32(32). 303–344. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/00243890152001780
Pires, Acrisio. 2007. The derivation of clausal gerunds. Syntax 10(10). 165–203. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9612.2007.00100.x
Reinhart, Tanya. 1983. Coreference and bound anaphora: A restatement of the anaphora questions. Linguistics and Philosophy 6(6). 47–88. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00868090
Reinhart, Tanya. 2006. Interface strategies. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/3846.001.0001
Roelofsen, Floris. 2008. Anaphora resolved. Amsterdam: Institute for Logic, Language, & Computation, Universiteit van Amsterdam dissertation.
Roeper, Thomas. 1987. Implicit arguments and the head-complement relation. Linguistic Inquiry 18(18). 267–310. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178538.
Ross, John Robert. 1967. Constraints on variables in syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation. http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/15166.
Ross, John Robert. 1969. Guess who? In Robert I. Binnick, Alice Davison, Georgia M. Green & Jerry L. Morgan (eds.), Papers from the fifth regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 252–286. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199645763.003.0002
Rothstein, Susan. 2004. Structuring events: A study in the semantics of lexical aspect. Oxford: Blackwell. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1002/9780470759127
Sag, Ivan A. & Carl Pollard. 1991. An integrated theory of complement control. Language 67(67). 63–113. DOI: http://doi.org/10.2307/415539
Sheehan, Michelle. 2013. The resuscitation of CED. In S. Kan, C. Moore-Cantwell & R. Staubs (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 40, 135–150. Amherst, MA: GLSA.
Sheehan, Michelle. 2018. On the difference between exhaustive and partial control. In Frederica Cognola & Jan Casalicchio (eds.), Null subjects in generative grammar: A synchronic and diachronic perspective, 141–170. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198815853.003.0006
Stromdahl, Larson. 2018. The control of infinitival adjuncts and ditransitive constructions. Poster presented at the Annual Meeting of the LSA. Salt Lake City, UT.
Truswell, Robert. 2007. Extraction from adjuncts and the structure of events. Lingua 117(117). 1355–1377. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2006.06.003
Uriagereka, Juan. 1999. Multiple spell-out. In Samuel Epstein & Norbert Hornstein (eds.), Working minimalism (Current Studies in Linguistics, vol. 32). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Whelpton, Matthew. 1995. The syntax and semantics of infinitives of result in English. University of Oxford: Oxford dissertation.
Whelpton, Matthew. 2001. Elucidation of a telic infinitive. Journal of Linguistics 37(37). 313–337. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226701008842
Whelpton, Matthew. 2002. Locality and control with infinitives of result. Natural Language Semantics 10(10). 167–210. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1022107429786
Williams, Alexander. 2015. Arguments in syntax and semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139042864
Williams, Alexander & Jeffrey J. Green. 2017. Why control of PRO in rationale clauses is not a relation between arguments. In Andrew Lamont & Katerina Tetzloff (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 47 3. 233–246. Amherst, MA: GLSA.
Williams, Edwin. 1980. Predication. Linguistic Inquiry 11(11). 203–238. https://www.jstor.org/stable/4178153.
Williams, Edwin. 1992. Adjunct control. In Richard K. Larson, Sabine Iatridou, Utpal Lahiri & James Higginbotham (eds.), Control and grammar (Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol. 48), 297–321. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7959-9_9