1 Introduction
1.1 Mbyá resultatives and valency alternations
This paper explores a point of cross-linguistic variation in the formation of resultative predicates, through a detailed study of resultatives in Mbyá Guaraní, a Tupí-Guaraní language spoken in Argentina, Brazil and Paraguay. I use the term resultatives to refer to stative predicates that entail the existence of a causing event,1 such as adjectival passives in English (Wasow 1977; Levin & Rappaport Hovav 1986). Using the label adjectival passive would be misleading in Mbyá, since there is no participial morphology in the language and resultatives are formally distinct from passives.
My starting point is the observation that Mbyá resultatives have a more restricted distribution than English adjectival passives. In English, adjectival passives can be derived not only from inchoative verbs like break but also from transitive causatives that do not participate in labile alternations, like bury:
(1) | English | |
a. | The door broke. | |
b. | Chris broke the door. | |
c. | Chris will repair the broken door. |
(2) | English | |
a. | *The body buried. | |
b. | Chris buried the body. | |
c. | (…) cadaver dogs found the buried body.2 |
German and Greek are similar to English in this respect.
In Mbyá on the other hand, resultatives can only be derived from inchoative verbs. As I will discuss in more detail in section 3, resultative predicates are derived by adding the suffix -kue or its voiced allomorph -gue to an inchoative verb stem.3 Resultative derivation is ungrammatical not only with derived and underived transitive causatives, as illustrated in (4b) and (5b), but also with causative stems whose valency has been reduced with the reflexive/passive prefix je-/nhe-, as illustrated in (4c) and (5c), to be compared with the grammatical reflexives/passives in (4d)/(5d):
- (3)
- a.
- Okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ.
- A3-break
- ‘The door broke.’
- b.
- A-mo-ĩ
- A1.SG-CAUS-be
- porã
- good
- ta
- PROSP
- okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ-gue.
- A3-break-RES
- ‘I am going to fix the broken door.’
- (4)
- a.
- João
- João
- o-mo-pẽ
- A3-CAUS-break
- okẽ.
- door
- ‘João broke the door.’
- b.
- *A-mo-ĩ
- A1.SG-CAUS-be
- porã
- good
- ta
- PROSP
- okẽ
- door
- o-mo-pẽ-gue.
- A3-CAUS-break-RES
- Intended: ‘I am going to fix the broken door.’
- c.
- *A-mo-ĩ
- A1.SG-CAUS-be
- porã
- good
- ta
- PROSP
- okẽ
- door
- o-nhe-mo-pẽ-gue.
- A3-PASS-CAUS-break-RES
- Intended: ‘I am going to fix the broken door.’
- d.
- Okẽ
- door
- o-nhe-mo-pẽ.
- A3-PASS-CAUS-break
- ‘The door was broken.’
- (5)
- a.
- A-j-aty
- A1.SG-B3-bury
- jaixa.
- paca
- ‘I buried the paca.’
- b.
- *Jagua
- dog
- o-jou
- A3-find
- jaixa
- paca
- (j)-aty-kue.
- B3-bury-RES
- Intended: ‘The dog found the buried paca.’
- c.
- *Jagua
- dog
- o-jou
- A3-find
- jaixa
- paca
- o-je-aty-kue.
- A3-PASS-bury-RES
- Intended: ‘The dog found the buried paca.’
- d.
- Tatu
- tatu
- o-je-aty.
- A3-REFL-bury
- ‘The tatu buried itself.’
Faced with these different distributions, one may be tempted to conclude that the stativizing operators that derive resultative predicates in English and Mbyá have different properties. To the contrary, I will argue that the difference between the two languages is located not in the properties of their stativizing operators, but rather in the properties of the verbs to which they apply. More precisely, I propose that the restricted distribution of Mbyá resultatives is due to an interaction between two factors: (i) that they are, as target state resultatives, incompatible with heads that introduce agents or causers and (ii) that roots of underived transitive causatives are more tightly associated with their external arguments in Mbyá than in English, German or Greek.
Regarding the first of these two factors, I argue following much previous work (see Rapp 1996; Schlüker 2005; Gehrke 2011; Meltzer-Asscher 2011; McIntyre 2013; Alexiadou et al. 2015) that target state resultatives are incompatible with the expression of agents or causers that are not participants in the result state. Following Alexiadou et al. (2015), this is interpreted as evidence of the incompatibility of target stativizers with agentive or causative Voice heads.
Regarding the second factor, it will be shown that all alternations involving external arguments must be marked morphosyntactically in Mbyá. Moreover, we will see that anticausative and labile alternations are unattested. Building on these observations, I will argue that the roots of all underived transitive causatives in Mbyá must be realized in syntactic frames that introduce an external argument. In the analytical framework adopted in this paper, this means that these roots must co-occur with an agent or causer Voice head.
The incompatibility of Mbyá resultatives with transitive causative verbs then follows from the incompatibility of target state resultatives with agent or causer Voice heads, together with the fact that these verbs require the presence of such a head in their syntactic frame, either lexically or through morphological causativization.
In languages like English, German or Greek, on the other hand, target state resultatives can be derived from non-alternating transitive causative verbs like bury in (2), because the roots of these verbs do not require the presence of agent or causer Voice head in their syntactic frame, despite the fact that they do not participate in labile alternations. More precisely, we will see in section 4 that target state resultative formation with transitive causatives in these languages is only excluded with verbs that select agents as their external arguments, as argued by Alexiadou et al. (2015) and Anagnostopoulou (2017).
In sum, I will argue that the difference between Mbyá on the one hand and better studied languages like English, German or Greek on the other hand is located not in the properties of their stativizers, but in the more stringent selectional restrictions that Mbyá roots impose on their argument structure.
The contributions of the paper are threefold. First, it contributes to the cross-linguistic study of resultative predicates, by providing a fine grained description and analysis of the grammar of resultatives in Mbyá. Second, it reveals a point of variation in the association between roots and external-argument introducing Voice heads across languages: it will be argued that Mbyá differs from English, German and Greek in the range of roots that are required to co-occur with an agent or causer Voice head. Finally, the paper presents new empirical support for the analysis of causative/inchoative alternations as Voice alternations of Kratzer (2005) and Alexiadou et al. (2006) and the related observation that resultant and target stativizers differ with respect to their syntactic height relative to Voice heads (Alexiadou et al. 2015; Anagnostopoulou 2017).
1.2 Theoretical assumptions
My analysis is grounded in constructivist theories of argument structure, which spring from the seminal work of Hale and Keyser (2002), and are represented by studies such as Ramchand (2008), Harley (2012) and Marantz (2013). In this tradition, the event structure and argument structure of verbs is built syntactically, through the combinations of roots with functional heads that enrich their event structure and introduce their arguments.
On the semantic side, I adopt a Neo-Davidsonian analysis of event descriptions, with full syntactic decomposition. In particular, I will assume that verb roots introduce predicates of events or states, and arguments are introduced by separate thematic heads. For a defence of thematic separation in syntax, see Borer (2003; 2005). For a review of semantic arguments in favour of thematic decomposition, see Williams (2015: Chapter 9).
Finally, I will adopt a realizational analysis of morphology, according to which syntax acts as a generative engine that builds abstract representations that are then spelled out phonologically. In section 5, I will argue that restrictions on the distribution of Mbyá resultatives are elegantly captured in a spanning theory, which holds that sequences of non-terminal nodes in a linearized syntactic structure can be realized as single morphemes, see in particular Haugen and Siddiqi (2016).
1.3 Ethics and data sources
Mbyá examples, judgments of grammaticality and truth-value were elicited by the author with two native speakers of Mbyá from Paraguay and one speaker living in the state of Rio de Janeiro in Brazil in July 2017 and July 2018. The author sought the informed consent of the consultants prior to elicitation. The three consultants authorized the author to publish the contents of these elicitation sessions in scientific communications. This study also relies on Robert Dooley’s (2015; 2016) description of Mbyá. Dooley (2015; 2016) provided a translation of his examples into Brazilian Portuguese. I have (re-)glossed these examples and I have provided an English translation. Unless indicated otherwise, all Mbyá examples provided in the paper were elicited by the author.
1.4 Caveat lector
Mbyá is spoken on a large territory that includes the Misiones province in Argentina, parts of Paraguay and several states in Brazil. Therefore, it goes without saying that regional variation is expected, and I can only claim that the description of resultatives presented in this paper reflects the usage of the three consultants I worked with. However, it is worth noting that this description is consistent with Dooley’s (2015; 2016) own description of Mbyá resultatives, which is based mainly on data collected in the Rio das Cobras community, in the state of Paraná in Brazil.
1.5 Structure of the paper
Sections 2 and 3 present the core Mbyá data to be analyzed. Section 2 focuses on valency alternations, and section 3 on resultative predicates. I argue in section 3 that Mbyá resultatives denote properties of target states rather than of resultant states. In section 4, I compare the distributions of target state resultatives in Mbyá, English, German and Greek, and I argue that the restricted distribution observed in Mbyá is due to the more stringent constraints that Mbyá roots impose on their syntactic frame, in combination with the cross-linguistically attested incompatibility of target stativizers with agent or causer Voice heads. Section 5 presents an implementation of the analysis in a realizational theory of morphology with insertion at non-terminal nodes, and compares it to an implementation in Distributed Morphology. Section 6 concludes.
2 Valency alternations in Mbyá
2.1 Split intransitivity in Mbyá
In order to discuss valency alternations in Mbyá, it is important to give an overview of agreement in the language. Mbyá verbs are uninflected for tense and aspect (Dooley 2015: §12.3). Bare verbs are interpreted with a non-future reference time, and are underspecified for viewpoint aspect.4 By contrast, subjects and/or objects are cross-referenced on the verb, following a split-S system. Two paradigms of cross-reference markers are used, which I refer to as class A and class B markers (see Table 1).
Class A | Class B | |
---|---|---|
1st singular | a- | xe- |
2nd singular | (e)re- | nde-/ne- |
1st plural inclusive | ja- / nha- | nhande-nhane |
1st plural exclusive | (o)ro- | ore- |
2nd plural | pe- | pende-/pene- |
3rd | o- | i-/(i)j-/(i)nh-, h-, ∅ |
Some intransitive verbs cross-reference their subject with class A markers, others with class B markers. Intransitive verbs that use class A markers are known as active, while those that use class B markers are known as inactive. Transitive verbs cross-reference either their subject or their object, with the exception of combinations of first person subjects and second person objects, which are cross-referenced with the portmanteau prefix ro-.5 With all other combinations of persons, a person hierarchy is used to determine which argument is cross-referenced (where “n > m” stands for “n wins over m”):
(6) | Mbyá person hierarchy: 1 > 2 > 3 |
Transitive subjects are cross-referenced with class A markers, while objects are cross-referenced with class B markers. With two third person arguments (e.g. third person subject and third person object), the subject is cross-referenced.6 In other configurations, the highest argument on the hierarchy is cross-referenced. The following constructed examples illustrate:
- (7)
- a.
- A-exa.
- A1.SG-see
- ‘I saw her/him/them/it.’
- b.
- Xe-r-exa.
- B1.SG-R-see
- ‘She/he/they/it saw me’ or ‘You saw me.’
The nature of the cross-referencing system of Guaraní languages has been the subject of some theoretical debates, see in particular Velázquez-Castillo (2002a) and Zubizarreta & Pancheva (2017a) on Paraguayan Guaraní.
One fact that bears mentioning in this section is that the distinction between intransitive verbs that select class A markers and those that select class B markers is orthogonal to the distinction between intransitive verbs that support resultative derivations and those that don’t. The following examples show that resultative predicates can be derived from either class of verbs:
- (8)
- a.
- Xo’o
- meat
- o-jy-kue.
- A3-cook-RES
- ‘The meat is cooked.’
- b.
- Xe-po
- B1.SG-hand
- i-ruru-kue.
- B3-swell-RES
- ‘My hand(s) is/are swollen.’
Consequently, the opposition between class A and class B markers will not play a direct role in my analysis of Mbyá resultatives.
2.2 Stative/inchoative alternations
In Mbyá, stative verbs may alternate between their stative interpretation and a dynamic, inchoative interpretation without morphological marking. This is illustrated in (9) and (10), where adverb choice in context forces a stative versus dynamic interpretation of the verb, respectively:
- (9)
- Context: I left my shirt outside, and it started to rain. I am worried that it got wet, so after the rain, I ask you to go have a look. You come back to me and say:
- Kamixa
- shirt
- i-piru
- B3-dry
- teri.
- still
- ‘The shirt is still dry.’
- (10)
- Context: I left a wet shirt to dry in the sun fifteen minutes ago. I went back to the shirt and I see that it is now dry. I exclaim:
- Kamixa
- shirt
- i-piru
- B3-dry
- reve’i.
- quickly
- ‘The shirt dried quickly.’
- (11)
- Okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ.
- A3-break
- ‘The door broke.’
2.3 Causative alternations and causative verbs
Alternations between intransitive and causative uses of a verb are marked by the causative prefix mbo- and its allomorph mo-:78
- (12)
- João
- João
- o-mo-mbiru
- A3-CAUS-dry
- kamixa.
- shirt
- ‘João dried the shirt.’
- (13)
- João
- João
- o-mo-pẽ
- A3-CAUS-break
- okẽ.
- door
- ‘João broke the door.’
Causativization with mo-/mbo- targets all intransitive predicates, including unergative predicates:
- (14)
- a.
- Anguja
- rat
- o-nha.
- A3-run
- ‘The rat was running.’
- b.
- Ava
- man
- o-mo-nha
- A3-CAUS-run
- anguja.
- rat
- ‘The man made the rat run.’
There are also non-alternating causative verbs in Mbyá, as illustrated by the verbs juka and aya:
- (15)
- a.
- João
- João
- o-juka
- A3-kill
- jaixa.
- paca
- ‘João killed the paca.’
- b.
- Jaixa
- paca
- o-juka.
- A3-kill
- ‘She/he/they/it killed the paca.’ (Not: ‘#The paca died.’)
- c.
- João
- João
- o-j-aya
- A3-B3-cut
- o-po.
- 3.POSS-hand
- ‘João cut his hand(s).’
- d.
- O-po
- 3.POSS-hand
- o-*(j)-aya.
- A3-B3-cut
- ‘She/he/they/it cut his/her/their hand(s).’ (Not: ‘#Her/his/their hand(s) got cut.’)
As examples (15b) and (15d) illustrate, verbs stems like juka and aya have no intransitive uses. In particular, they do not participate in labile alternations.
Finally, it should be mentioned that mo-/mbo- is not the only causative marker attested in Mbyá. Transitive verbs are causativized by the suffix -uka, and sociative causatives (cf. Shibatani & Pardeshi 2002; Guillaume & Rose 2010) are built with the prefix (gu)ero-, see Dooley (2015: §13.2). Since causatives of transitives and sociative causatives are not directly relevant to the argument that will be developed in the rest of the paper, I will not discuss them.
2.4 Valency reduction with je-/nhe-
The valency of transitive verbs may be reduced with the prefix je- and its nasal allomorph nhe-, which I will argue has both reflexive and passive uses (see Velázquez-Castillo 2002a for a brief description of this prefix in Paraguayan Guaraní). The reflexive use of je-/nhe- is the most frequent according to Dooley (2015: §13.2), and is illustrated in (16). In this example, the agent of the killing must be the subject:
- (16)
- João
- João
- o-je-juka.
- A3-REFL-kill
- ‘João killed himself.’ (not: “#João was killed.’)
But je- is also attested in what may initially appear to be marked anti-causative constructions:
- (17)
- Okẽ
- door
- o-nhe-mo-pẽ.
- A3-PASS-CAUS-break
- ‘The door was broken.’
However, such constructions differ crucially from inchoative verbs in implying the existence of an external argument. A first piece of evidence of this contrast is provided by the impossibility to deny the existence of an agent or causer with passivized causatives, as opposed to inchoatives:9
- (18)
- a.
- Kamixa
- shirt
- i-piru
- B3-dry
- reve’i
- quickly
- va’eri,
- although
- avave
- nobody
- n-o-mo-mbiru-i.
- NEG-A3-CAUS-dry-NEG
- ‘Although the shirt dried quickly, nobody dried it.’
- b.
- (#Kamixa
- shirt
- o-nhe-mo-mbiru
- 3-PASS-CAUS-dry
- reve’i
- quickly
- va’eri),
- although
- avave
- nobody
- n-o-mo-mbiru-i.
- NEG-A3-CAUS-dry-NEG
- (19)
- a.
- Okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ
- A3-break
- va’eri,
- although
- avave
- nobody
- n-o-mo-pẽ-i.
- NEG-A3-CAUS-break-NEG
- ‘Although the door broke, nobody broke it.’
- b.
- (#Okẽ
- door
- o-nhe-mo-pẽ
- A3-PASS-CAUS-break
- va’eri),
- although
- avave
- nobody
- n-o-mo-pẽ-i.
- NEG-A3-CAUS-break-NEG
- Comment: “It sounds like you said someone broke it, but then your corrected yourself.”
Another piece of evidence is provided by instrument modification, which is allowed with passivized causatives but not with inchoatives:
- (20)
- a.
- João
- João
- o-mo-pẽ
- A3-CAUS-break
- okẽ
- door
- yvyra
- wood
- py.
- with
- ‘João broke the door with a stick.’
- b.
- Okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ
- A3-break
- (*yvyra
- wood
- py).
- with
- Comment: “You need someone to use the stick.”
- c.
- Okẽ
- door
- o-nhe-mo-pẽ
- A3-CAUS-break
- yvyra
- wood
- py.
- with
- ‘The door was broken with a stick.’
- (21)
- a.
- Ava-kue
- man-PL
- o-mo-yxyĩ
- A3-CAUS-smooth
- tape
- path
- maquina
- machine
- py.
- with
- ‘The men smoothed out the road with a machine.’
- b.
- Tape
- path
- h-yxyĩ
- B3-smooth
- (*maquina
- machine
- py).
- with
- c.
- Tape
- path
- o-nhe-mo-yxyĩ
- A3-PASS-CAUS-smooth
- maquina
- machine
- py.
- with
- ‘The road was smoothed out with a machine.’
Not only do (20c) and (21c) imply the existence of an external argument, it is also understood that this argument is an agent, rather than the door or the road itself: clearly, the door cannot be the participant manipulating the stick in (20c), and if it were the understood external argument in (19b), negating the existence of an agent with avave (‘nobody’) should be coherent. In sum, it appears that the reduced causatives of Mbyá cannot be analyzed as reflexive verbs with a semantically impoverished effector external argument, as proposed by Koontz-Garboden (2009) for marked anti-causatives. In these respects, non-reflexive causatives whose valency was reduced with je-/nhe- are more similar to English passives, which also imply the existence of an external argument, than to marked anti-causatives. French SE-anticausatives, for instance, are consistent with negating the existence of an external argument, and license neither instrument modifiers nor agentive prepositional phrases:
- (22)
- French
- a.
- La
- the
- porte
- door
- s’est
- SE=is
- cassée,
- broken
- mais
- but
- personne
- nobody
- ne
- NEG
- l’a
- it=has
- cassée.
- broken
- ‘The door broke, but nobody broke it.’
- b.
- La
- the
- porte
- door
- s’est
- SE=is
- cassée
- broken
- (*avec
- with
- un
- a
- bâton).
- stick
- c.
- La
- the
- porte
- door
- s’est
- SE=is
- cassée
- broken
- (*par
- by
- Jean).
- Jean
I will not offer a detailed analysis of the structure and interpretation of valency reduction with je-/nhe-, nor will I explain the preference for its reflexive interpretation, since these questions are orthogonal to our main argument. What matters to the analysis of resultative formation is that transitive verbs prefixed with je-/nhe- introduce an external argument, which is either existentially quantified or bound through reflexivization. In both cases, these verb forms contrast with inchoatives, which lack an external argument altogether.
2.5 There are no anticausative or labile alternations in Mbyá
We have seen that causativization in Mbyá is marked by the prefix mo-/mbo-, the suffix -uka or the sociative causative prefix (gue)ro-. The prefix je-/nhe- is used as a reflexive or passive marker. Two other valency increasing or decreasing markers that we will not discuss here are the reciprocal prefix jo-/nho-, and the impersonal voice marker -a, which binds the external argument of a transitive or intransitive verb without promoting its internal argument (Dooley 2015: §13.2).
The demotion of a direct object to an oblique argument is not marked by derivational morphology, but is marked syntactically by the use of postpositions:
- (23)
- Dooley (2016: 144)
- a.
- A-i-peju
- A1.SG-B3-blow
- atã
- strong
- tata.
- fire
- ‘I blew on the fire with strength.’
- b.
- Yvytu
- wind
- o-i-peju
- A3-B3-blow
- yvyra
- tree
- re.
- OBL
- ‘The wind blew on the tree.’
Given this rich inventory of valency changing markers, we may ask ourselves whether there are any unmarked valency alternations in the language. With respect to external argument alternations, the answer is clearly negative. As Dooley observes in his grammatical sketch of Mbyá, alternations that affect the external argument are marked morphologically (Dooley 2015: §13.2).
The situation is more complex with alternations involving internal arguments, which are optional with some verbs:
- (24)
- Dooley (2016: 30)
- a.
- O-ẽ
- A3-go.up
- o-vy.
- A3-go
- ‘He kept going up.’
- b.
- O-ẽ
- A3-go.up
- yvy’ã.
- mountain
- ‘He went up the mountain.’
- (25)
- Dooley (2016: 144)
- a.
- Yvytu
- wind
- o-i-peju
- A3-B3-blow
- atã.
- strong
- ‘The wind blew strongly.’
- b.
- A-i-peju
- A1.SG-B3-blow
- atã
- strong
- tata.
- fire
- ‘I blew on the fire with strength.’
I conclude that, with the possible exception of optional internal arguments, every operation that increases or decreases the valency of a verb is marked either by derivational morphology, or by the use of adpositions. In particular, all operations that introduce or bind an external argument are marked by derivational morphology.
An important consequence of this state of affairs is that Mbyá lacks any form of anticausative or labile alternation. We saw that valency reduction with je-/nhe- should be analyzed as a form of passivization or reflexivization. So-called labile alternations, covert alternations between inchoative and transitive causative uses of a verb, are also unattested, as is middle voice. In these respects, Mbyá differs from English, in which labile alternations are attested, as well as German and Greek, in which both labile alternations and marked anticausatives are attested (Alexiadou et al. 2006). In section 4, I will argue that this property of Mbyá is closely linked to the restricted distribution of resultatives in the language.
3 Guaraní resultatives
3.1 Morphological makeup
Resultative predicates are formed by attaching the suffix -kue/-gue to the verb root. Both active and inactive verbs are attested in resultatives. The following examples illustrate the predicative use of resultatives:
- (26)
- a.
- Okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ-gue.
- A3-break-RES
- ‘The door is broken.’
- b.
- Xo’o
- meat
- o-jy-kue.
- A3-cook-RES
- ‘The meat is cooked.’
- c.
- Kova’e
- this
- kumanda
- bean
- h-aguino-gue.
- B3-spoil-RES
- ‘These beans are spoiled.’
- d.
- Xe-po
- B1.SG-hand
- i-ruru-kue.
- B3-swell-RES
- ‘My hand is swollen.’
Mbyá resultatives also have attributive uses:
- (27)
- a.
- A-mo-ĩ
- A1.SG-CAUS-be
- porã
- good
- ta
- PROSP
- okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ-gue.
- A3-break-RES
- ‘I am going to fix the broken door.’
- b.
- Ha’u-xe
- A1.SG.eat-DES
- xo’o
- meat
- o-xyryry-kue.
- A3-fry-RES
- ‘I want to eat fried meat.’
- c.
- A-i-poru
- A1.SG-B3-use
- ta
- PROSP
- kova’e
- this
- cable
- cable
- xo-gue.
- tear-RES
- ‘I am going to use this torn cable.’
We now come to the observation at the centre of this paper, namely that the resultative suffix -kue/-gue cannot attach to causative verbs, whether they are derived causatives or underived transitive causatives. This is illustrated in examples (28) and (29):
- (28)
- a.
- A-j-aty
- A3-B3-bury
- jaixa.
- paca
- ‘I buried the paca.
- b.
- *Jagua
- dog
- o-jou
- A3-find
- jaixa
- paca
- (j)-aty-kue.
- 3-bury-RES
- Intended: ‘The dog found the buried paca.’
- (29)
- *A-mo-ĩ
- A1.SG-CAUS-be
- porã
- good
- ta
- PROSP
- okẽ
- door
- o-mo-pẽ-gue.
- A3-CAUS-break-RES
- Intended: ‘I am going to fix the broken door.’ (cf. (27a))
Resultative formation is also unacceptable with causative verbs whose valency has been reduced with the prefix je-/nhe-:
- (30)
- *A-mo-ĩ
- A1.SG-CAUS-be
- porã
- good
- ta
- PROSP
- okẽ
- door
- o-nhe-mo-pẽ-gue.
- A3-PASS-CAUS-break-RES
Note that resultative formation is not acceptable with all intransitive verbs. Resultatives formed from activity verbs are unacceptable, as illustrated in (31):
- (31)
- *Kunumi
- boy
- o-guata-kue
- A3-walk-RES
- i-kane’õ.
- B3-tired
Furthermore, resultatives are not attested with all inchoative verbs:
- (32)
- a.
- A-mo-ĩ
- A1.SG-CAUS-be
- axuka
- sugar
- ka’ay
- mate
- py,
- in
- ha’e
- and
- he’ẽ
- sweet
- reve’i.
- quickly
- ‘I put sugar in the mate, and it got sweet quickly.’
- b.
- ?A-ka’ay-’u-xe
- A1.SG-mate-drink-DES
- ka’ay
- mate
- he’ẽ-gue.
- sweet-RES
- Intended: ‘I want to drink sweetened mate.’
The following resultatives were identified in Dooley’s (2016) lexicon. Note that all base verbs in the list are intransitive in Mbyá, with the apparent exception of monda, to which we come back below:
(33) | a. | aguino > aguino-gue | rot > rotten |
b. | jy > jy-kue | cook > cooked | |
c. | kanhy > kanhy-gue | disappear > disappeared | |
d. | ke > ke-kue | turn (of milk) > turned | |
e. | monda > monda-kue | steal > stolen | |
f. | u’ũ > u’ũ-gue | rot > rotten | |
g. | xo > xo-gue | break off > broken off | |
h. | xoro > xoro-kue | tear > torn | |
i. | xyryry > xyryry-kue | fry > fried | |
j. | ypi > ypi-kue | dry (of a tree) > dried | |
k. | vo > vo-kue | crack > cracked |
My consultants judged that these resultatives are well formed. They also accepted the following ones. Again, all base verbs in the list are intransitive:
(34) | a. | aju > aju-kue | ripen > ripe |
b. | akỹ > akỹ-gue | get wet > wet | |
c. | o’yxã > o’yxã-gue | cool > cooled | |
d. | karẽ > karẽ-gue | bend (intransitive) > bent | |
e. | pẽ > pẽgue | break > broken | |
f. | pererĩ > pererĩ-gue | thin > thinned | |
g. | piru > piru-kue | dry > dried | |
h. | potĩ > potĩ-gue | clean > cleaned | |
i. | re’õ > re’õ-gue | soften > softened | |
j. | ynyẽ > ynyẽ-gue | fill up > filled-up | |
k. | ruru > ruru-kue | swell > swollen | |
l. | yxyĩ > yxỹi-gue | smooth > smoothed | |
m. | kai > kai-kue | burn > burned |
All verbs in these lists but monda have inchoative uses. Indeed, in his lexicon, Dooley (2016: 92) observes that the formation of resultatives with -kue/-gue is restricted to intransitive verbs, with the exception of the form mondakue (‘stolen’), which my consultants also accepted:
- (35)
- A-jo-gua
- A1.SG-TR-buy
- ao
- clothes
- monda-kue.
- steal-RES
- ‘I bought stolen clothes.’
It should be noted that monda is not a direct transitive verb, but rather an intransitive verb with an oblique theme argument:
- (36)
- Dooley (2016: 119)
- Kyxe
- knife
- re
- ABL
- i-monda.
- B3-steal
- ‘He stole the knife.’
Still, monda differs from the other predicates listed in (33) and (34) insofar as its subject is not a theme but an agent, and constitutes an apparent exception to the generalization that Mbyá resultatives may only be derived from inchoative verbs. In section 5, I will argue that the compatibility of monda with resultative derivation is due to the irregular character of this verb, and that this exception actually brings further support to the proposed analysis of the restricted distribution of Mbyá resultatives.
Before I close this section, I would like to point out that the Guaraní suffix -kue/-gue is also attested as nominal temporal marker (Tonhauser 2006; 2007; Thomas 2014):
- (37)
- Xe-r-embireko-kue
- B1.SG-R-wife-PAST
- o-menda
- A3-marry
- xe-irũ
- B1.SG-friend
- r-eve.
- R-with
- ‘My ex-wife married my friend.’
However, uses of -kue/-gue as a nominal tense and as a resultative marker have different distributions and interpretations. As a past temporal marker, -kue/-gue cannot be suffixed to verbs that have not been nominalized. If the verb is nominalized, -kue/-gue can attach to it regardless of its event structure. In (38a), the bare verb o-o is compatible with a past tense interpretation. Attaching the temporal marker -kue to the verb in (38b) is ungrammatical. In (38c), the temporal marker attaches to the nominalizer va’e, which rescues the sentence:
- (38)
- a.
- João
- João
- o-o
- A3-go
- Argentina
- Argentina
- py.
- to
- ‘João went to Argentina.’
- b.
- Czech
- *João
- João
- o-o-kue
- A3-go-PAST
- Argentina
- Argentina
- py.
- to
- c.
- Czech
- João
- João
- o-o
- A3-go
- va’e-kue
- NMLZ-PAST
- Argentina
- Argentina
- py.
- to
- ‘João went to Argentina.’
By contrast, the resultative use of -kue/-gue is restricted to inchoative verbs, and does not require nominalization. Since the present paper is only concerned with the resultative use of -kue/-gue, and its use as a temporal marker has a different distribution, the question of the unification of resultative and past uses will be left to future research.
3.2 Semantic properties of Mbyá resultatives
Embick (2004) observes that English adjectival passives, unlike pure state predicates, cannot be used in complements of verbs of creation:
(39) | English (Embick 2004: 357) | |
a. | This door was built open. | |
b. | *This door was built opened. |
(40) | English (Embick 2004: 357) | |
a. | This new ruler was built long. | |
b. | *This new ruler was built lengthened. |
Since adjectival passives describe states that result from a previous causing event, asserting that an entity was in a result state at its time of creation is incoherent. Applying the same diagnostics in Mbyá confirms that inchoative verbs suffixed with -kue/-gue denote properties of result states, rather than properties of pure states:
- (41)
- a.
- Para
- Para
- o-j-apo
- A3-B3-make
- kamixa
- shirt
- tuixa.
- large
- ‘Para made a large shirt.’
- b.
- #Para
- Para
- o-j-apo
- A3-B3-make
- kamixa
- shirt
- (o)-xoro-gue.
- A3-tear-RES
- c.
- João
- João
- o-j-apo
- A3-B3-make
- okẽ
- door
- r-atã.
- R-hard
- ‘João made a sturdy door.’
- d.
- #João
- João
- o-j-apo
- A3-B3-make
- okẽ
- door
- (o)-pẽ-gue.
- A3-break-RES
- Consultant’s comment: “The door can only be broken after it’s been made.”
One may further ask what kind of result state is described by Mbyá resultatives. In a seminal study, Kratzer (2000) observed that German and English adjectival passives do not form a homogeneous class. Kratzer identified two kinds of adjectival passives in these languages, depending on the nature of the state and its relation to the causing event. Resultant state adjectival passives denote mere states of events having culminated, which Kratzer models as properties of times that follow the culmination of an event. Target state adjectival passives, on the other hand, describe semantically richer states that result from the culmination of an event, but may not persist indefinitely. In English and German, target state adjectival passives that do not describe permanent states are compatible with modification by still (in German: immer noch), unlike resultant state adjectival passives, as illustrated by (42a) vs (42b), respectively:
- (42)
- German (Kratzer 2000: 385–386)10
- a.
- Die
- the
- Geisslein
- little_goats
- sind
- are
- immer
- always
- noch
- still
- versteckt.
- hidden
- ‘The little goats are still hidden.’
- b.
- Das
- the
- Theorem
- theorem
- ist
- is
- (*immer
- (*always
- noch)
- still)
- bewiesen.
- proven
- ‘*The theorem is still proven.’
The distinction between resultant states and target states was initially formulated by Parsons (1990), who offers an elegant description of the difference between these two kinds of states:
(43) | Parsons (1990: 234–235) |
“For every event e that culminates, there is a corresponding state that holds forever after. This is “the state of e’s having culminated,” which I call the “Resultant state of e” (…) It is important not to identify the Resultant-state of an event with its “target” state. If I throw a ball onto the roof, the target state of this event is the ball’s being on the roof, a state that may or may not last for a long time. What I am calling the Resultant state is different; it is the state of my having thrown the ball onto the roof, and it is a state that cannot cease holding at some later time.” |
Following this intuition, Kratzer (2000) proposes that target state adjectival passives are derived by applying a stativizer to a relation between events and states, while resultant state adjectival passives are derived by using a stativizer that is essentially a perfect operator, which maps a property of events to a property of times:
(44) | a. | ⟦(42a)⟧ = ∃e∃s [ CAUSE(e)(s) & HIDDEN(s)(the goats) & t0 ⊆ τ(s) ] |
b. | ⟦(42b)⟧ = ∃e [ PROVE(e)(the theorem) & τ(e) ≤ t0 ] |
Kratzer’s denotations for the two stativizers are given in (45). I have renamed the target and resultant stativizers RESTARGET and RESRESULT, respectively:
(45) | a. | ⟦ RESTARGET ⟧ = λR.λs. ∃e[R(e)(s)] |
b. | ⟦ RESRESULT ⟧ = λP.λt. ∃e[P(e) & τ(e) ≤ t] |
Coming back to Mbyá, all the resultatives that my consultants accepted and that do not describe permanent states are compatible with modification by teri (‘still’):
- (46)
- a.
- Okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ-gue
- A3-break-RES
- teri.
- still
- ‘The door is still broken.’
- b.
- Xe-ao
- B1.SG-clothes
- akỹ-gue
- wet-RES
- teri.
- still
- ‘My clothes are still wet.’
- c.
- Xe-po
- B1.SG-hand
- i-ruru-kue
- B3-swell-RES
- teri.
- still
- ‘My hand is still swollen.’
We must of course make allowance for resultative predicates that are incompatible with teri because they denote permanent states:11
- (47)
- a.
- #Xo’o
- meat
- o-jy-kue
- A3-cook-RES
- teri.
- still
- b.
- #Jety
- potato
- xyryry-kue
- fry-RES
- teri.
- still
Finally, the incompatibility of -kue/-gue resultatives with activity predicates (cf. example (31)) is also explained if -kue/-gue denotes a target stativizer, which takes relations between events and states as arguments. Since activity predicates denote properties of events without an associated target state, they will not be able to combine with -kue/-gue.
I conclude that -kue/-gue resultatives denote target states rather than resultant states.
3.3 Structure of Mbyá resultatives
My analysis of the structure of Mbyá resultatives builds on the constructivist analysis of causativization of Schäfer (2007) and Alexiadou et al. (2006; 2015). Verbs are decomposed into an uncategorized root together with a number of functional projections:
(48) | [VoiceP Voice [vP v √ROOT ]] |
Following Marantz (1997), roots are category neutral. A little v head categorizes them as verbal. Following earlier proposals by Kratzer (1996), Hale & Keiser (2002) and Pylkkännen (2002; 2008), external arguments are introduced by a Voice head.
In addition, Schäfer (2007) and Alexiadou et al. (2015) analyze causative/inchoative alternations as Voice alternations. Inchoative verbs (i.e. unmarked anticausatives) consist of a Voice-less vP. In causative verbs, an agent or causer argument is introduced by an additional Voice head:
(49) | English (Alexiadou et al. 2015: 29) | ||
a. | The door opened. | ||
b. | [ vCAUS [ the door √OPEN ]] |
This analysis follows a tradition of decomposing causative verbs into a state denoting root, and an operator that introduces a causing event (see among many others Lakoff 1965; McCawley 1968; Dowty 1979; von Stechow 1996; Harley 2008; 2012). In addition, Pylkkänen (2002; 2008) argued based on the analysis of Finnish desiderative causatives and Japanese adversative causatives that causing events may be introduced independently from causer arguments. She concludes that causative relations between eventualities and agents of causing events are introduced by different heads, which in the present framework are identified with little v and Voice, respectively. Further extending this line of reasoning, Kratzer (2005) observes that Pylkkänen’s dissociation of causing events from causer arguments makes it possible to analyze causative alternations as Voice alternations. Kratzer argues that causation should be analyzed as a relation between a causing event and an event or state that the culmination of this event brings about. In this perspective, one may assume that inchoative predicates are causative too:
(50) | Kratzer (2005) |
“the commonly posited BECOME operator becomes superfluous in the decomposition of inchoatives, causatives, and anticausatives. Those three types of verbs are all plain causatives. They differ with respect to voice.” |
Finally, Schäfer (2007) and Alexiadou et al. (2015) provide syntactic arguments for the presence of a causative little v head in inchoatives, in the absence of external argument introducing head.
Building on this analysis of causative structures, Alexiadou et al. (2015) argue that resultative operators differ with respect to their height relative to the Voice head. In resultant state adjectival passives, the resultative head (which I will refer to as RES) is introduced above Voice, while in target state adjectival passives, it is introduced below the Voice head. In resultant state adjectival passives, Voice may introduce an agent or a causer argument. On the other hand, when Voice is present in target state adjectival passives, it introduces as an external argument a participant12 in the target state, which accounts for the incompatibility of target state adjectival passives with modifiers that relate to agents or causers, with the exception of agents and causers that participate in the result state (see McIntyre 2013 and section 4.1). The class of target state adjectival passives is not itself syntactically homogeneous, since target state participles in English and German as well as target state interpretations of Greek participles formed with the suffix -menos are argued to embed a full vP, while Greek target state participles formed with the suffix -tos only embed a root or √P:
(51) | Structure of resultant state (RSAP) and target state adjectival passives (TSAP): | ||
a. | [RESRESULT [VoiceAGENT/CAUSER [ v √ROOT]] | RSAP | |
b. | [VoiceHOLDER [RESTARGET [ v √ROOT]] | TSAP in English, German, Greek -menos | |
c. | [RESTARGET √ROOT ] | TSAP with Greek -tos |
In this perspective, if Mbyá resultatives describe target states, we expect that they should occur lower than Voice, or more generally lower than the point where external arguments are introduced in the syntactic structure. This is indeed confirmed by the fact that Mbyá resultatives do not license agent/causer related modifiers, as illustrated below with instrumental modifiers. In this respect, resultatives pattern with inchoative verbs, as opposed to causative and passive verbs:
- (52)
- a.
- Okẽ
- door
- o-nhe-mo-pẽ
- A3-PASS-CAUS-break
- yvyra
- wood
- py.
- with
- ‘The door was broken with a piece of wood.’
- b.
- *Okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ
- A3-break
- yvyra
- wood
- py.
- with
- c.
- *Okẽ
- door
- o-pẽ-gue
- A3-break-RES
- yvyra
- wood
- py.
- with
- (53)
- a.
- Tape
- path
- o-nhe-mo-yxyĩ
- A3-PASS-CAUS-smooth
- maquina
- machine
- py.
- with
- ‘The road was smoothed out with a machine.’
- b.
- *Tape
- path
- h-yxyĩ
- B3-smooth
- maquina
- machine
- py.
- with
- c.
- *Tape
- path
- h-yxyĩ-gue
- B3-smooth-RES
- maquina
- machine
- py.
- with
Resultatives that include a v layer entail the existence of a causing event. Evidence that Mbyá resultatives are of this type was already presented in (41), where it was shown that they are unacceptable in complements of verbs of creation.
In sum, resultative predicates formed with -kue/-gue denote a target state, which entails the existence of a causing event. The resultative head is introduced above little v, and is incompatible with an agent/causer Voice head. This suggests the following structure for Mbyá resultatives:
(54) | a. | piru-kue | |
dry-RES | |||
‘dried’ | |||
b. | [AspP RESTARGET [vP [v √DRY vCAUS ] [θP θTHEME DP ] ] ] |
In this structure, the stative root √DRY is adjoined to the vCAUS head, which introduces a causing event. The thematic head θTHEME introduces the holder of the state, in the complement domain of little v. The little vP denotes a relation between states of the theme being dry and their causing event. The resultative head RESTARGET maps these relations to a property of target states of such events.
In the syntactic representation in (54), it is assumed that the root denotes a state. This is appropriate for verbs like piru, which can be used as pure stative predicates. However, some inchoative verbs only have a dynamic use. This is the case for instance with pẽ (‘break’). How can we capture the dynamic nature of such verbs? Following Embick (2009), I propose that the roots of predicates of caused states denote a property of events and must co-occur with a “proxy” predicate of states. In inchoative structures, the root √BREAK denotes a property of events that is adjoined to a causative little v head, and specifies a manner of causing. The caused state is denoted by an abstract predicate ST that is c-commanded by little v:13
(55) | [vP [v √BREAK vCAUS ] [θP [θ ST θ THEME ] DP ] ] |
Given these assumptions, we may represent the structure of resultatives derived from predicates of caused states as follows:
(56) | a. | pẽ-gue |
break-RES | ||
‘broken’ | ||
b. | [AspP RESTARGET [vP [v √BREAK vCAUS ] [θP [θ ST θ THEME ] DP ] ] ] |
The compositional interpretation of these structures is discussed in the appendix.
4 Explaining the restricted distribution of Mbyá resultatives
4.1 Target stativizers and Voice
Following previous studies by Rapp (1996), Schlüker (2005), Gehrke (2011), Meltzer-Asscher (2011) and McIntyre (2013), Alexiadou et al. (2015) note that English, Greek and German target state adjectival passives fail to license agent/causer related modifiers, unless the agent they refer to is present in the target state, or the adverb modifies that state directly. The following contrasts illustrate this fact:
(57) | English (McIntyre 2013: 31) | |
a. | The door seemed broken (*by Mary). | |
b. | The road remained blocked by the police. |
(58) | English (McIntyre 2013: 31) | |
a. | The door seemed painted (*by Mary). | |
b. | The door seemed painted by Picasso. |
The target state adjectival passives in (57a) and (58a) are incompatible with agentive by-phrases. In (57b) and (58b), agentive modification is acceptable. McIntyre argues that the relevant contrast lies in the relation of the agent to the target state. While the agents of (57a) and (58a) only participate in the causing event, those of (57b) and (58b) are interpreted as participants in the target state. As McIntyre puts it, they are “responsible for continuing the state expressed by the participle” or are somehow essential to the characterization of the state. It appears then that the arguments introduced in by-phrases in (57b) and (58b) are arguments of the target state, and that these examples are consistent with the generalization that target state adjectival passives are incompatible with agent oriented modifiers that relate to the causing event rather than its result state. This generalization is further supported by the incompatibility of target state adjectival passives with instrument modifiers and agent oriented adverbs. The following examples from Greek illustrate:
- (59)
- Greek (Alexiadou et al. 2015: 158)
- Ta
- the
- lastixa
- tires
- ine
- are
- (*akoma)
- still
- fuskomena
- inflated
- me
- with
- tin
- the
- tromba.
- pump
- ‘The tires are (*still) inflated with the pump.’
- (60)
- Greek (Alexiadou et al. 2015: 158)
- To
- the
- thisavrofilakio
- safe
- itan
- was
- (*akoma)
- still
- prosektika
- cautiously
- anigmeno.
- opened
- ‘The safe was (*still) cautiously opened.’
Based on these observations and additional modification tests, Alexiadou et al. (2015) conclude that target stativizers are introduced below Voice, and block the introduction of agent/causer Voice.
In order to explain the incompatibility of target stativizers with agent/causer Voice, Anagnostopoulou (2017; 2018) proposes that target state but not resultant state participles represent outcomes of scalar changes. She further argues that verbs that lexicalize scalar changes must express change along a single dimension. The presence of Voice is then argued to be blocked in target state adjectival passives because it would lead to interactions between the agent and the theme that would render the change too complex.
In the next subsection, I will argue that the incompatibility of target stativizers with agent/causer Voice explains the restricted distribution of resultatives in Mbyá.
4.2 Explaining the restricted distribution of Mbyá resultatives
Mbyá target state resultatives are unacceptable with all transitive verbs. This contrasts with target state adjectival passives in English and German, which can be derived from a subset of non-alternating transitive causatives, as illustrated by the following examples:
- (61)
- German (Kratzer 2000: 385)
- a.
- Die
- the
- Reifen
- tires
- sind
- are
- immer
- always
- noch
- still
- aufgepumpt.
- pumped_up
- ‘The tires are still pumped-up.’
- b.
- Das
- the
- Gebäude
- building
- ist
- is
- immer
- always
- noch
- still
- geräumt.
- evacuated
- ‘The building is still evacuated.’
- c.
- Der
- the
- Deckel
- lid
- ist
- is
- immer
- always
- noch
- still
- abgeschraubt.
- screwed_off
- ‘The lid is still screwed off.’
- d.
- Die
- the
- Ausfahrt
- driveway
- ist
- is
- immer
- always
- noch
- still
- versperrt.
- obstructed
- ‘The driveway is still obstructed.’14
The fact that these adjectival passives are compatible with modification by still suggests that they are interpreted as target state resultatives. Importantly, the transitive verb stems from which they are derived lack inchoative alternants:
(62) | English | |
a. | *The tires pumped up. | |
b. | #The building evacuated.15 | |
c. | *The lid screwed off. | |
d. | *The driveway obstructed. |
- (63)
- German
- a.
- *Die
- the
- Reifen
- tires
- pumpten
- pumped
- auf.
- up
- b.
- *Das
- the
- Gebäude
- building
- evakuierte.
- evacuated
- c.
- *Der
- the
- Deckel
- lid
- schraubte
- screwed
- ab.
- off
- d.
- *Die
- the
- Ausfahrt
- driveway
- versperrte.
- obstructed
In German, the native speakers I consulted accept sich-forms of these verbs only to the extent that internal causation is conceivable. To illustrate, one speaker commented that (64b) is acceptable “if I imagine a building that has a function of ejecting all residents in the case of a threat”. Another speaker observed that (64a) suggests that “the tires have a built-in inflation mechanism (much like life jackets in an airplane).” One speaker judged that, as a consequence of these implications, (64b) and (64d) are odd. Another one judged that (64c) and (64d) are odd, for the same reasons.
- (64)
- German
- a.
- Die
- the
- Reifen
- tires
- pumpten
- pump
- sich
- REFL
- auf.
- up
- ‘The tires pumped themselves up.’
- b.
- ?Das
- the
- Gebäude
- building
- evakuierte
- evacuated
- sich.
- REFL
- ‘The building evacuated itself.’
- c.
- ?Der
- the
- Deckel
- lid
- schraubte
- screw
- sich
- REFL
- ab.
- off
- ‘The lid screwed itself off.’
- d.
- ?Die
- the
- Ausfahrt
- driveway
- versperrte
- obstructed
- sich.
- REFL
- ‘The driveway obstructed itself.’
I conclude that these examples, to the extent that they are acceptable, are interpreted reflexively, and are therefore semantically transitive.
This discussion shows that target state resultatives are compatible with some transitive verbs that do not participate in causative alternations in English and German. Why then are resultatives incompatible with transitive causatives in Mbyá? We saw in section 3 that Mbyá lacks any form of anticausative or labile alternations. Furthermore, the only operations that reduce the valency of transitive verbs preserve external argument entailments: both reflexive and passive verbs entail the existence of an external argument, and there appears to be no middle voice in the language. In the present analytical framework, this suggests that the roots of lexically causative verbs in Mbyá are only ever attested in syntactic frames that include an agent or causer Voice head, which introduces an external argument in the semantic representation of the verb. I conclude that these roots are lexically required to occur in such syntactic frames. This entails that these verbs will be incompatible with resultative derivation with the suffix -kue/-gue, since this suffix is a target stativizer and as such is incompatible with agent or causer Voice. The same reasoning also explains the ungrammaticality of resultatives derived from morphological causatives, under the assumption that the causative prefix mo-/mbo- introduces a thematic Voice head.
By contrast, given the compatibility of the English and German transitive causatives with target state derivation in (61), we must conclude that the roots of these verbs may occur in syntactic frames that lack agent or causer Voice, despite the fact that these verbs do not have inchoative alternants.
Note that a similar analysis of restrictions on the distribution of target state resultatives was already proposed in Greek by Anagnostopoulou (2017), who observed that verbs of manner of killing and verbs of creation, as well as a subset of verbs with manner entailments, cannot form target state adjectival passives:
- (65)
- Greek (Anagnostopoulou 2017: 115)
- Aftos
- this
- o
- the
- anthropos
- man
- ine
- is
- (*akomi)
- (*still)
- dolofonimenos/straggalismenos
- murdered/strangled
- dhilitiriasmenos/pirovolimenos/mexeromenos.
- poisoned/shot/knived
- (66)
- Greek (Anagnostopoulou 2017: 115)
- a.
- To
- the
- vivlio
- book
- mu
- my
- ine
- is
- (*akomi)
- (*still)
- grameno.
- written
- b.
- O
- the
- kiklos
- circle
- ine
- is
- (*akomi)
- (*still)
- sxediasmenos.
- drawn
- (67)
- Greek (Anagnostopoulou 2017: 115)
- *Ta
- the
- magula
- cheeks
- tis
- her
- ine
- are
- akomi
- still
- xastukismena,
- slapped,
- gi’afto
- for_this
- ponai.
- hurts
- ‘*Her cheeks are still slapped, that’s why she hurts.’
Anagnostopoulou observes that the causative verbs that cannot form target state adjectival passives require an agent as an external argument. By contrast, at least some verbs of external causation that are not strictly agentive appear to form acceptable target state adjectival passives in Greek, as illustrated by the following examples (the judgments in (69) were provided by a native speaker of Greek):
- (68)
- Greek (Alexiadou et al. 2015: 157)
- Ta
- the
- lasticha
- tires
- ine
- are
- akoma
- still
- fuskomena.
- pumped_up
- (69)
- Greek
- a.
- ?To
- the
- ktirio
- building
- ine
- is
- akoma
- still
- ekenomeno.
- evacuated
- b.
- ?To
- the
- kapaki
- lid
- ine
- is
- akoma
- still
- ksevidomeno.
- screwed_off
- c.
- O
- the
- dromos
- driveway
- ine
- is
- akoma
- still
- mplokarismenos.
- blocked
In the present framework, verbs that require an agent as external argument must be realized in a frame that includes an agentive Voice head, which explains their incompatibility with target stativizers. By contrast, the roots of non-agentive causative verbs that are compatible with target state adjectival passives must be able to occur in syntactic frames that lack an agent or causer Voice head, even if they fail to participate in labile alternations.
In sum, the crucial difference between Mbyá and languages like English, German or Greek with respect to the distribution of target state resultatives appears to be range of roots that are required to co-occur with an agent or causer Voice head. In Mbyá, all roots of transitive causatives are subject to this requirement. In English, German and Greek, at least some roots of non-alternating transitive causative verbs must be able to occur in frames that do not include agent or causer Voice.
4.3 Coda
I have argued that all roots of transitive lexical causatives in Mbyá require the presence of an agent or causer Voice head in their syntactic frame. This, in combination with the incompatibility of target state resultatives with such heads, explains the restricted distribution of resultatives in this language. What is still unclear at this point is the nature of the association between Voice and the roots of causative verbs in Mbyá. In the next section, I sketch two alternative analyses of this dependency. The first one builds on the assumption that phonological exponents may spell out linearized sequences of terminal nodes, and proposes that exponents of roots of transitive lexical causatives in Mbyá spell out sequences of heads that include the root itself and its associated Voice head. The second adopts a more classical approach to Vocabulary Insertion, and posits that these roots bear a feature that must be checked by a Voice head.
5 Spelling out Mbyá verbs
5.1 Spelling out syntactic frames with post-linearization spanning
An elegant way of capturing the requirement that roots of transitive causatives impose on the presence of a Voice head is to assume that the exponent of these verbs spell out a chunk of structure that includes both heads. Theories of Vocabulary Insertion at non-terminal nodes are well suited to implement this idea. In this subsection, I will sketch an analysis of the morphological realization of Mbyá verbs using the theory of post-linearization spanning of Haugen & Siddiqi (2016).
An important motivation of realizational models of morphology with non-terminal insertion is the avoidance of the proliferation of null exponents and post-syntactic readjustment operations like fusion and fission. Null exponents and readjustment operations are invoked in realizational models of morphology when a piece of syntactic structure that contains multiple terminal nodes is spelled out by a single exponent. This arises for instance in the analysis of irregular past forms of English verb tenses like hit or sang (Halle & Marantz 1993). The former may be analyzed by positing a null allomorph of the past tense, whose use is triggered by the presence of the root √HIT:
(70) | Vocabulary Items for T[+past] (Embick 2015: 93) | ||||
a. | T[+past] | ↔ | -t | /{√BEND, √LEAVE, …}__ | |
b. | T[+past] | ↔ | ∅ | /{√HIT, √QUIT, …}__ | |
c. | T[+past] | ↔ | -ed |
An analysis of sang will involve not only positing a null exponent for the past tense in the context of √SING, but also invoking a phonological readjustment rule that will change the nucleus of the exponent of the root in the context of the past tense.
By contrast, post-linearization spanning treats hit and sang as exponents of adjacent sequences of heads after linearization:16
(71) | a. | Syntactic structure: | [ T[+past] [vP v √HIT ] ] |
b. | Linearized sequence of heads: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
(72) | a. | Syntactic structure: | [ T[+past] [vP v √SING ] ] |
b. | Linearized sequence of heads: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
The realization of sequences of heads by a single Vocabulary Item is subject to the two following principles:
(73) | Post-linearization Contiguous Morpheme Insertion Principle (Haugen & Siddiqi 2016: 369) |
Insertion may realize multiple adjacent X0s (features) provided that the features realized by the inserted Vocabulary Item are as large a subset of the string of adjacent X0s (features) as that which could otherwise be expressed by separate overt Vocabulary Items at the contained X0s (features). |
(74) | Minimize Exponence (Siddiqi 2009: 4) |
The most economical derivation will be the one that maximally realizes all the formal features of the derivation with the fewest morphemes. |
Note that in post-linearization spanning, a Vocabulary Item may provide an exponent for a series of heads, without matching all the heads in the series. This is similar to the insertion of underspecified Vocabulary Items under bundles of features in Distributed Morphology. In view of this fact, the discussion that follows will distinguish exponence (the phonological realization of a series of heads) from feature matching. In the graphical representation of Vocabulary Insertion that are used in this section, e.g. (72b)–(72c), horizontal curly brackets represent exponence, rather than feature matching.
Keeping this in mind, let us now illustrate how the two principles in (73) and (74) interact in the realization of the past form of sing. This process involves a competition between the irregular form sang and the regular form *singed, which exploits the following set of Vocabulary Items:
(75) | a. | T[+past] | ↔ | -ed |
b. | √SING | ↔ | sing | |
c. | √SING, T[+past] | ↔ | sang |
Two options compete for the phonological realization (i.e. exponence) of the linearized sequence of heads. For ease of reading, feature matching between Vocabulary Items and sequences of heads are indicated through boldface, while exponence is indicated with curly brackets:
(76) | a. | Syntactic structure: | [ T[+past] [vP v √SING ] ] |
b. | Linearized sequence of heads: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
(77) | a. | Syntactic structure: | [ T[+past] [vP v √SING ] ] |
b. | Linearized sequence of heads: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
While both options satisfy the Post-linearization Contiguous Morpheme Insertion Principle, Minimize Exponence favours sang over singed, since the former realizes (i.e. matches) the same number of features (√SING and T[+past]) with fewer morphemes. Note that, given the inventory of Vocabulary Items in (75), the little v head does not qualify as realized in either option, in the matching sense of realization. Nevertheless, this head is still spelled out by sang in (76c) and by sing in (77c).
It is worthwhile to discuss the process that leads to the realization of the past form of hit, since this will illustrate an important feature of post-linearization spanning, namely the use of homophony in the analysis of morphological irregularities. Both the present non-third person form of this verb and its past tense form are realized as hit. The Vocabulary Item in (78b) may be used to spell out the former. However, spelling out the past form of this verb with this Vocabulary Item is less optimal than using the regular form *hitted, since (78b) does not match the past tense feature. Consequently, we must introduce a homophone of hit in (78c), in order to account for the irregular realization of the verb in the past tense.
(78) | a. | T[+past] | ↔ | -ed |
b. | √HIT | ↔ | hit1 | |
c. | √HIT, T[+past] | ↔ | hit2 |
(79) | a. | Syntactic structure: | [ T[+past] [vP v √HIT ] ] |
b. | Linearized sequence of heads: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
(80) | a. | Syntactic structure: | [ T[+past] [vP v √HIT ] ] |
b. | Linearized sequence of heads: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
(81) | a. | Syntactic structure: | [ T[+past] [vP v √HIT ] ] |
b. | Linearized sequence of heads: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
While the appeal to root homophony in post-linearization spanning may be criticized by some, it is embraced by Haugen & Siddiqui (2016), who argue that this approach is no more stipulative than positing a contextually conditioned zero-allomorph of the past tense, and reflects some degree of arbitrariness in the history of these irregular forms.
Let us now consider how post-linearization spanning may be used to provide a model of the morphological realization of Mbyá resultatives and valency alternations. In a realizational morphological framework, the most delicate aspect of Mbyá verb morphology to model is the lack of labile alternations. Indeed, we must make sure that (i) exponents of inchoative verbs cannot be used to spell out transitive structures, and (ii) exponents of transitive causatives cannot be used to spell out inchoative structures. In Distributed Morphology, both problems would arise if null exponents were used indiscriminately to spell out little v heads and Voice. Remembering that the verb piru (‘dry’) is restricted to intransitive inchoative or stative uses, while aty (‘bury’) is restricted to transitive uses, consider the following inventory of Vocabulary Items:
(82) | a. | √DRY | ↔ | piru |
b. | √BURY | ↔ | aty | |
c. | vCAUS | ↔ | ∅ | |
d. | Voice | ↔ | ∅ |
Unrestricted use of null exponents for vCAUS and Voice predicts, incorrectly, that the exponent piru may realize a causative verb, and that the exponent aty may realize an inchoative verb:
(83) | a. | Syntactic structure:17 | |
b. | Phonological realization: | *∅Voice – ∅v – piru |
(84) | a. | Syntactic structure: | |
b. | Phonological realization: | *∅v – aty |
These cases of over-generation are elegantly avoided using post-linearization spanning. One may restrict the use of aty to causative structures by assuming that this exponent spells out a sequence of heads that includes both the root and Voice:
(85) | a. | Voice, vCAUS, √BURY | ↔ | aty | ||
b. | Syntactic structure: | |||||
c. | Linearizarion: | |||||
d. | Phonological realization: |
Because the Vocabulary Item in (85a) is specified for Voice, it cannot spell out a sequence that does not include this head.
The impossibility to spell out transitive structures with piru is also easily accounted for with Minimize Exponence, given the availability of the alternative realization mombiru. To illustrate, the exponent piru defined in (86a) spells out all three features present in (87), but it matches only the root, while the combination of mo- and piru (mombiru) in (88) matches all three features:
(86) | a. | √DRY | ↔ | piru |
b. | Voice, vCAUS | ↔ | mo- |
(87) | a. | Syntactic structure: | |
b. | Linearization: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
(88) | a. | Syntactic structure: | |
b. | Linearization: | ||
c. | Phonological realization: |
Minimize Exponence favours (88) over (87), since the causative morpheme mo- matches the Voice and vCAUS heads, which are left unmatched in (87). Note that this analysis relies on an auxiliary assumption, which is that there is no Vocabulary Item that spells out Voice with a null exponent. This however is a consequence of a design feature of post-linearization spanning, which eschews the use of null exponents altogether.
The analysis also captures covert event structure alternations between stative and inchoative uses of piru and other stative roots, under the assumption that little v heads lack independent exponents in the language (which is supported by the lack of overt marking of alternations between stative and dynamic interpretations of verbs, as well as by the lack of overt marking of the opposition between inchoative and process verbs, all these oppositions being encoded in flavours of little v in the proposed analysis):
(89) | a. | √DRY | ↔ | piru |
b. | Syntactic structure: | |||
c. | Linearization: | |||
d. | Phonological realization: |
In sum, this analysis captures dependencies between the roots of lexical causatives and Voice lexically, by encoding in Vocabulary Items the information that the exponents of these roots also spell out Voice. In this perspective, the incompatibility of roots of underived transitive causatives with resultative derivation receives the same explanation as the impossibility of these roots to occur in inchoative verb frames. Namely, since both structures lack agent or causer Voice, the only Vocabulary Item that may spell out the root is overspecified. Compare (92) to the grammatical resultative in (91):
(90) | a. | RESTARGET | ↔ | -kue |
(91) | a. | vCAUS, √BREAK | ↔ pẽ | ||
b. | Syntactic structure: | ||||
c. | Linearization: | ||||
d. | Phonological realization: |
(92) | a. | Voice, vCAUS, √BURY | ↔ aty | ||
b. | Syntactic structure: | ||||
c. | Linearization: | ||||
d. | Phonological realization: |
5.2 Remarks on thieving
It was observed in section 3.1 that the verb monda (‘steal’) is compatible with resultative -kue/-gue, which appears to contradict the generalization that resultative -kue/-gue only combines with inchoative predicates. I believe that the source of this exception lies in the irregular character of the predicate monda itself. This is a dynamic predicate which requires the presence of an agent argument and a theme that undergoes a transfer of possession. As such, monda falls under Tsunoda’s (1981) category of predicates of effective action. The fact that the theme of this verb is realized as an oblique argument is somewhat surprising, since effective action predicates tend to be realized as transitive verbs cross-linguistically (Tsunoda 1985; Malchukov 2005; Grimm 2011). Even more surprising is the fact that the agent of monda is cross-referenced with a class B inactive marker. Velázquez-Castillo (2012a) observed that arguments that initiate a process of change (in this case a transfer of possession) are marked as actors in Paraguayan Guaraní. Mbyá is similar to Paraguayan Guaraní in this respect (see Dooley 2015: §10.1). We would therefore expect the agent of monda to be cross-referenced with a class A marker. This is indeed how the agent of dynamic uses of monda is cross-referenced in Paraguayan Guaraní (see Jover Peralta & Osuna 1950; Guasch & Ortiz 2008).
Given this state of affairs, I would like to suggest that monda has an argument structure that is not characteristic of agentive verbs, and that this property is reflected both in its unexpected cross-referencing pattern and in its compatibility with resultative derivation. More precisely, I will argue that because of its peculiar argument structure, monda differs from other agentive verbs in Mbyá in not requiring the presence of a Voice head in its syntactic frame. My argument will rely on Zubizarreta & Pancheva’s (2017a; b) theory of cross-referencing in Paraguayan Guaraní, which I apply to Mbyá.
Zubizarreta & Pancheva (2017a; b) analyze the cross-referencing system of Paraguayan Guaraní transitive verbs as a direct/inverse system, class A markers being used to cross-reference subjects in the direct order, while class B markers are used to cross-reference objects in the indirect order. In addition, Zubizarreta and Pancheva argue that while class A markers are agreement prefixes, class B 1st and 2nd person markers are pronouns. In the simplest case of indirect order, they are object pronouns that are promoted to a position of adjunction to the inflection head I, via the edge of vP, as illustrated by the following example from Paraguayan Guaraní:18
- (93)
- Paraguayan Guaraní (Zubizarreta & Pancheva 2017a: 1177)
- a.
- (Nde)
- you
- che=mbo-jahu.
- 1SG.OBJ=TR-bathe
- ‘You bathe me.’
- b.
- [I D1SG I[1SG] [vP (DP1SG) [vP DP2SG [vP v[1SG] [ V (DP1SG) ] ] ] ] ]
Zubizarreta and Pancheva observe that object cross-reference markers in the inverse order may originate as possessors of incorporated noun phrases. This analysis is supported by the formal identity of possessive pronouns with class B cross-reference markers, as illustrated in (94a)–(94b):
- (94)
- Paraguayan Guaraní (Zubizarreta & Pancheva 2017a: 1181–1182)
- a.
- Nde
- you
- re-johéi
- 2SG-wash
- che
- 1POSS
- rova
- face
- (ky’a).
- dirty
- ‘You wash my (dirty) face.’
- b.
- Nde
- you
- che=rova
- 1POSS=face
- (jo)héi.
- wash
- ‘You wash my face.’
In (94b), the 1st person cross-reference marker is argued to be base generated as a possessor in the specifier of the incorporated nP che=rova, before undergoing cyclic movement to I.
Zubizarreta and Pancheva extend this analysis to class B 1st and 2nd person cross-reference markers of so-called “triform-verbs”, which they argue originate as possessors of an nP incorporated into little v. Consider for instance the verb che=rasẽ in (95). This verb consists of the nP asẽ (‘cry’) incorporated into a light v. Its class B 1st person cross-reference marker originates as a possessor of the incorporated nP, and is cyclically moved to a position of adjunction to the I head:
- (95)
- Zubizarreta & Pancheva (2017b: 97)
- (Che)
- I
- che=rasẽ.
- 1POSS=cry
- ‘I cry.’
I propose that the Mbyá verb monda (‘steal’) has a structure similar to that of intransitive tri-form verbs, where the incorporated phrase is a possessive DP, rather than an nP:
- (96)
- a.
- Kyxe
- knife
- re
- ABL
- xe-monda.
- B1-steal
- ‘I stole the knife.’
- b.
- [IP [I D I[1SG] ] [vP DP1SG [vP PP [v [DP nP[1SG] [ DPOS [nP [n √THEFT n ] ST ] ] ] vCAUS ] ] ] ]
In this example, the stem xemonda is derived by incorporating an event denoting DP interpreted as ‘my theft’ into a light v. Its 1st person cross-reference marker originates as a possessor (nP[1SG]) in the specifier of DP, and is cyclically moved until it ends up as a D head adjoined to I. The theme is introduced as a post-positional argument of the verb. The introduction of the agent as a possessor explains its unexpected cross-referencing with a class B marker.
Moving on to the interpretation of (96b), we can assume that the possessor nP[1SG] is base-generated in a thematic position. More precisely, the root √THEFT denotes a property of events of stealing, and the possessive head DPOS introduces introduces nP[1SG] as the agent of these events (cf. John’s theft of the $1,000).
Crucially, while we argued that agent-introducing Voice is always spelled out together with the root of transitive causative verbs, this generalization need not apply to the relation between nominal roots and DPOS. If √THEFT can be spelled out independently of DPOS, it should be possible for the target stativizer -kue to combine with the stem monda, as illustrated in (97), repeated from (35), and in (98):
- (97)
- A-jo-gua
- A1.SG-TR-buy
- ao
- clothes
- monda-kue.
- steal-RES
- ‘I bought stolen clothes.’
(98) | a. | √THEFT | ↔ | monda |
b. | Syntactic structure: | [ RESTARGET [vP [nP [n √THEFT n ] ST ] vCAUS ] ] | ||
c. | Linearization: | |||
d. | Phonological realization: |
In sum, analyzing monda as an incorporated DP explains its irregular inflection class and argument structure. In addition, the hypothesis that its agent is not introduced by Voice but rather by a possessive DPOS head explains why monda is not subject to the requirement that all roots of lexical transitive causatives in Mbyá should be spelled out together with Voice.
5.3 Cross-linguistic Variation
The analysis sketched in the previous subsection accounts for the lack of target resultatives derived from transitive causatives in Mbyá. However, we haven’t yet explained why such alternations are attested in English and similar languages. For alternating verbs like dry, the answer is simple. The Vocabulary Item that is used to spell out the root of such verbs is underspecified for Voice. Since causative alternations are unmarked in English, the same Vocabulary Item can be used to spell out the root in an inchoative or a transitive frame, the former being compatible with resultative formation:
(99) | a. | √DRY | ↔ | dry |
b. | Syntactic structure: | |||
c. | Linearization: | |||
d. | Phonological realization: |
(100) | a. | √DRY | ↔ | dry |
b. | Syntactic structure: | |||
c. | Linearization: | |||
d. | Phonological realization: |
The situation is more complicated with transitive causatives that do not alternate, like bury. Because these verbs can form target state adjectival passives, the Vocabulary Items that realize their roots must not be specified for agent or causer Voice:
(101) | vCAUS, √BURY | ↔ | bury |
However, this cannot be the whole story, since the Vocabulary Item in (101) could then be used to spell out the root √BURY in an inchoative frame, which we know is unattested.
In order to solve this puzzle, I propose that the constraints that prevent the realization of these roots in inchoative frames are not lexical, but pragmatic. I will now sketch an analysis along these lines, by building on an earlier proposal by Rappaport Hovav (2014).
Following Levin & Rappaport Hovav (1995), Rappaport Hovav (2014) observes that some causative verbs like clear only alternate with particular choices of theme argument:
(102) | English (Rappaport Hovav 2014: 9) | |
a. | I cleared the screen. | |
b. | The screen cleared. |
(103) | English (Rappaport Hovav 2014: 9) | |
a. | The waiters cleared the counter. | |
b. | *The counter cleared. |
Rappaport Hovav argues that the availability of the inchoative form with clear type verbs is not due to lexical restrictions, but to pragmatic constraints which favour the more informative expression of the cause argument:
(104) | Rappaport Hovav (2014: 23) |
“In the description of a change of state, the cause of the change of state is relevant; therefore, since an utterance which specifies the cause of the change of state is more informative than one which expresses just the change of state, it is to be preferred, all things being equal.” |
If the cause of a change of state is always relevant, speakers should use the more informative transitive verb form, unless they have additional reasons not to do so. One such reason would be that the speaker assumes there is no external cause. In Gricean terms, using the transitive form would then violate the maxim of quality (Grice 1975). In this scenario, the inchoative form is preferred:
(105) | Rappaport Hovav (2014: 25) | |
a. | My watch broke after the warranty ran out. | |
b. | #I broke my watch after the warranty ran out. | |
(does not have the same interpretation as (a)). |
Note that Rappaport Hovav (2014) does not intend her pragmatic analysis to apply to verbs like kill and destroy. Since these verbs never alternate, she argues that they are lexically associated with an external argument. However, given the availability of target state adjectival passives with non-agentive transitive causatives like bury, I believe that a lexical analysis of the lack of alternation of bury-type verbs is not tenable. Instead, I suggest that Rappaport Hovav’s pragmatic analysis of causative alternations with clear-type verbs can be extended to non-alternating non-agentive transitive causatives. While the Vocabulary Items that spell out the roots of these verbs are by themselves compatible with inchoative frames, transitive frames are preferred due to their greater informativity. The challenge that we face is to explain why this preference rules out the inchoative use of bury type verbs, while it can be overridden by contextual factors for break and clear type verbs.
I suggest that the unacceptability of inchoative alternants with bury type verbs can be attributed to an obligatory implicature. Let us assume that the inchoative form of lexical causatives competes with its passive alternative:
(106) | English | |
a. | *The body buried. | |
b. | The body was buried. |
(106b) is more informative than (106a), since it entails the existence of an external cause that lead to the body being buried. Everything else being equal, an utterance of (106a) will therefore lead to an implicature that the speaker is not in a position to assert (106b). This implicature, however, conflicts with the common knowledge that events of burying have external causes. Indeed, bury is similar to kill and destroy insofar as these verbs denote non-spontaneous events, i.e. events that are unlikely to occur without the intervention of a external cause (Haspelmath 1993). In this respect, bury differs from verbs like break and clear, which are compatible with internal as well as external causes (Harley & Noyer 2000), and will therefore trigger non-contradictory implicatures.
Note that this analysis requires the computation of the implicature of (106a) to be mandatory and blind to common knowledge. Indeed, if the implicature could be cancelled, it would not lead to a contradiction and unacceptability. In addition, the computation of the implicature must be blind to common knowledge. Otherwise, given the piece of information that events of burying are always associated with an external cause, (106a) and (106b) would be truth-conditionally equivalent, and an utterance of (106a) would not trigger the implicature that the speaker is not in a position to assert (106b). A theory of blind and mandatory implicatures was developed by Magri (2009), in order to account for lifetime effects of individual-level predicates. For reasons of space, I will not discuss how the present analysis could be implemented in Magri’s framework. There are certainly loose ends to tie up, but I believe that the broad lines of this analysis are clear enough for our purposes.
Importantly, this analysis can account for the felicity of target state resultatives derived from non-alternating lexical causatives, given adequate assumptions about the set of syntactic alternatives to adjectival passives. Consider for instance example (107):
(107) | English |
The body is still buried. |
The implicature that is responsible for the unacceptability of inchoative uses of buried depends on a competition between the verbal passive and inchoative forms of the verb. Under the assumption that target state adjectival passives do not compete with verbal passives, they will not trigger the faulty implicature. If adjectival and verbal passives differ in syntactic category in English, this assumption could be reduced to the more general requirement that two constituents cannot be syntactic alternatives of one another unless they have the same category, a requirement that is already part of Katzir’s (2007) theory of structural alternatives.
5.4 Conspiracies
The analysis that was presented in this section relies on post-linearization spanning. However, it is also possible to model Mbyá verb morphology even if Vocabulary Insertion is limited to terminal nodes. To do so, one may wish to posit null exponents for Voice and little v heads. In order to account for the lack of covert alternations targeting external arguments, the former should be restricted to contexts that include the root of a lexically transitive verb:
(108) | a. | Voice | ↔ | ∅ | /{√BURY, √BLOW, …} |
b. | Voice | ↔ | mo- | ||
c. | vCAUSE | ↔ | ∅ |
Likewise, in order to block the insertion of roots of transitive verbs in inchoative verb frames, the exponents of these roots should be specified for insertion in the context of a Voice head:
(109) | a. | √BURY | ↔ | aty | / vCAUSE – ] Voice ] |
b. | √BLOW | ↔ | peju | / vPROC – ] Voice ] | |
c. | … |
In such a system, the absence of external argument alternations with roots of causative verbs arises as a conspiracy, as in the case of English irregular past tense inflection.19 In the latter case, the blocking of a regular past tense verb form in the context of √SING conspires with the blocking of the regular exponent of √SING in the context of T[+PAST]. In the former, the realization of agent/causer Voice by the causative prefix mo- is blocked in the context of a transitive root, while the phonological realization of the root is restricted to the context of agent/causer Voice.
While such an analysis is tenable, I believe that an analysis based on insertion at non-terminal nodes is more elegant. Indeed, in the conspiracy analysis, the restriction of the root of a causative verb to a transitive frame is encoded in the Vocabulary Item that specifies the exponent of this root. The fact that Voice is not realized independently from the root is arbitrarily encoded in a second Vocabulary Item. While this arbitrariness may be justified in the analysis of irregular processes, the morphology of Mbyá verbs appears to be a paragon of regularity, which is elegantly captured by the spanning analysis.
Note that I am not claiming that analyses of irregularities in post-linearization spanning are generally more principled than analyses that rely on null exponents and readjustment rules. As Haugen & Siddiqi (2016) recognize, the use of homophony in the former is no less stipulative than that of lexically conditioned zero allomorphs. In the specific case that concerns us here, however, a spanning analysis appears to more elegant.
6 Conclusion
I have argued that what appeared to be an arbitrary selectional restriction governing the distribution of the Mbyá resultative suffix -kue/-gue is in fact an epiphenomenon, which reveals the interplay between lexical constraints on the frames in which roots may be inserted, and the syntactic properties of target stativizers.
The proposed analysis brings to light a point of variation in the lexical encoding of the dependencies between roots and functional heads: the distribution of resultatives in Mbyá suggests that all roots of underived transitive causatives are lexically associated with an agent/causer Voice head in this language, in contrast to English, German and Greek, where this lexical association only holds of roots of strictly agentive verbs.
Finally, this study of Mbyá resultatives offers new empirical support for the analysis of adjectival passives of Alexiadou et al. (2015), and stresses the importance of the distinction between target states and resultant states in the structure of adjectival passives and related resultative predicates.
Additional File
The additional file for this article can be found as follows:
Semantic composition. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.688.s1
Abbreviations
The following abbreviations are used in glosses in this paper: A = cross-referenced argument, class A, ABL = ablative case, ACC = accusative case, B = cross-referenced argument, class B, CAUS = causative, COMPL = completive aspect, DES = desiderative, INTR = intransitive verbalizer, NEG = negation, NMLZ = nominalizer, NOM = nominative case, OBJ = object, PAST = past temporal marker, PASS = passive, PL = plural, POSS = possessive, PROSP = prospective aspect, TR = transitive verbalizer, REFL = reflexive, RES = resultative, SG = singular, SE = romance “se”-reflexive.
Notes
- This use of ‘resultative’ is close to Nedjalkov and Jaxontov’s (1988) use of the term. However, while I label resultant state predicate as resultatives, Nedjalkov and Jaxontov classify them as perfects, as observed by Kratzer (2000). Note that I do not discuss complex resultative predicates like kick the door open in this paper. [^]
- Retrieved on April 15, 2019 from: http://www.fox2detroit.com/news/local-news/body-discovered-buried-in-detroit-house-s-yard-on-west-side. [^]
- This suffix is also used as a nominal temporal marker in Paraguayan Guarani (Tonhauser 2006; 2007) and in Mbyá Guarani (Thomas 2014). The relation of its temporal use to its resultative use is discussed in section 3.1. [^]
- Unless required by the context of an example, I will translate bare achievements and accomplishments with past perfective English verbs, and bare activities and states with present (progressive) English verbs or adjectives. [^]
- Note that, contrary to Paraguayan Guarani, Mbyá does not have different portmanteau prefixes for singular and plural second person objects. [^]
- A subset of transitive verbs cross-reference both their subject and object, when the latter is third person. Following Dooley (2015), I analyze the i- and j- prefixes in word forms such as o-j-aty (‘A3-B3-bury’) and o-i-kuaa (‘A3-B3-know’) as third person cross-reference markers. [^]
- The allomorph mo- is used with nasal roots. With oral roots, the allomorph mbo- is used, unless the first segment of the root is a voiceless stop, in which case this segment may be prenasalized and the allomorph mo- is used. Root prenasalization by the causative prefix appears to be a lexical phenomenon that does not affect all roots. See for instance mo- + piru → mo-mbiru (‘to dry [something]’) but mo- + pi → mbo-pi (‘to flog [someone]’). [^]
- For a discussion of causativization in Paraguayan Guarani, see Velázquez-Castillo (2002b). [^]
- This test is reminiscent of the by itself modification test used notably by Chierchia (2004) and Koontz-Garboden (2009) to diagnose the absence of external arguments in inchoative verbs. Since there is no equivalent construction in Mbyá, and more generally no agent PPs in passives or in the language at large, the by-itself test cannot be applied in Mbyá. [^]
- Glosses in Kratzer’s (2000) examples have been modified to fit the Leipzig glossing rules. [^]
- More precisely: these states are permanent by virtue of the nonreversible nature of the change of state described by the root, not because the resultatives have perfect-type meanings. [^]
- A consequence of this analysis is that causative little v heads can occur independently of agent/causer Voice in English adjectival passives. In that sense, it challenges the claim that English is a v-Voice bundling language, contra Pylkkänen (2008) and in line with Harley (2009). [^]
- See Koontz Garboden & Beavers (2017), Beavers (2018) for objections to Embick’s proposal and an alternative analysis. Note that the debate about the proper representation of states in break type verbs is ultimately orthogonal to the argument made in this paper. [^]
- Kratzer (2000) observes that some uses of obstructed lack event implications, and therefore do not qualify as adjectival passives, e.g. Because of a congenital malformation, tissue obstructed the blood vessel. Kratzer concludes that the verb obstruct has stative as well as eventive uses. [^]
-
Evacuate has intransitive uses, see (i) below. Note that in this example, “the building” is understood metonymically as referring to its residents. Therefore, such examples do not provide evidence of labile alternations with evacuate:
[^]
(i) The last time the building evacuated was during the 2013 floods. (Retrieved from https://calgary.ctvnews.ca/water-leak-forces-hundreds-of-residents-out-of-salvation-army-building-1.4095618 on April 15, 2019). - Haugen & Siddiqi assume that the English past tense and past participle have a common [bound] feature, which I will ignore in this exposition, for the sake of conciseness. [^]
- In this example and the following ones, I do not discuss the phonological realization of the internal argument of the verb, which does not belong to the same Spell Out domain as little v. This has been indicated by greying out θP in the syntactic representation of each example. [^]
- Note that Zubizarreta and Pancheva gloss the causative prefix mo-/mbo- as a transitivizer, TR. [^]
- I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for calling my attention to this point. [^]
Acknowledgements
Many thanks to the three Mbyá consultants who provided the data for this study. I am also grateful to four Glossa anonymous reviewers for their comments, which greatly improved the quality of the manuscript, as well as to the speakers of German and Greek who provided judgments of grammaticality for these languages. The paper benefited from a presentation at the 23rd Workshop on the Structure and Constituency of the Languages of the Americas at the university of Ottawa, and from discussions with Susana Bejar and Maria Luisa Zubizarreta. All errors are mine.
Competing Interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
References
Alexiadou, Artemis, Elena Anagnostopoulou & Florian Schäfer. 2006. The properties of anticausatives crosslinguistically. In Mara Frascarelli (ed.), Phases of interpretation, 187–211. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110197723.4.187
Alexiadou, Artemis, Elena Anagnostopoulou & Florian Schäfer. 2015. External arguments in transitivity alternations: A layering approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199571949.001.0001
Anagnostopoulou, Elena. 2017. Voice, manners, and results in adjectival passives. In Roberta D’Alessandro, Irene Franco & Ángel Gallego (eds.), The verbal domain, 105–128. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198767886.003.0005
Anagnostopoulou, Elena. 2018. Adjectival participles as a tool to study manner and result components in Verbs. Paper presented at the Endpoints Workshop. Germany: Humboldt Universität zu Berlin.
Beavers, John. 2018. Result entailments in the meaning of roots: A cross-linguistic study. Paper presented at the Endpoints Workshop. Germany: Humboldt Universität zu Berlin.
Borer, Hagit. 2003. Exo-skeletal vs. endo-skeletal explanations: syntactic projections and the lexicon. In John Moore & Maria Polinsky (eds.), The nature of explanation, 31–67. Chicago, IL: SLI Publications.
Borer, Hagit. 2005. Structuring sense volume 2: the normal course of events. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199263929.001.0001
Chierchia, Gennaro. 2004. A semantics for unaccusatives and its syntactic consequences. In Artemis Alexiadou, Elena Anagnostopoulou & Martin Everaert (eds.), The Unaccusativity puzzle: Explorations of the syntax–lexicon interface, 22–59. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199257652.003.0002
Dooley, Robert. 2015. Léxico Guarani, dialeto Mbyá: introdução. Anápolis: Associação Internacional de Linguística – SIL Brasil. (https://www.sil.org/resources/archives/72343).
Dooley, Robert. 2016. Léxico Guarani, dialeto Mbyá: Guarani-Português. Anápolis: Associação Internacional de Linguística – SIL Brasil. (https://www.sil.org/resources/archives/72342).
Dowty, David. 1979. Word meaning and Montague Grammar: The semantics of verbs and times in generative semantics and in Montague’s PTQ. Dordrecht: Reidel. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9473-7
Embick, David. 2004. On the structure of resultative participles in English. Linguistic Inquiry 35(3). 355–392. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/0024389041402634
Embick, David. 2009. Roots, states, and stative passives. Paper presented at the Roots workshop, University of Stuttgart, June 10–12.
Embick, David. 2015. The morpheme: A theoretical introduction. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9781501502569
Grice, Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Peter Cole & Jerry Morgan (eds.), Syntax and Semantics 3: speech acts. New York, NY: Academic Press.
Guasch, Antonio & Diego Ortiz. 2008. Diccionario Castellano-Guaraní y Guaraní-Castellano. Asunción: Centro de Estudios Paraguayos Antonio Guasch.
Guillaume, Antoine & Françoise Rose. 2010. Sociative causative markers in South American languages: a possible areal feature. In Franck Floricic (ed.), Essais de typologie et de linguistique générale: mélanges offerts à Denis Creissels, 383–402. Lyon: ENS Éditions.
Hale, Ken & Samuel Keyser. 2002. Prolegomenon to a theory of argument structure. Cambridge, MA: the MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/5634.001.0001
Halle, Morris & Alec Marantz. 1993. Distributed Morphology and the pieces of inflection. In Ken Hale & Samuel J. Keyser (eds.), The view from building 20: Essays in linguistics in honor of Sylvain Bromberger, 111–176. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Harley, Heidi. 2008. On the causative construction. In Shigeru Miyagawa & Mamoru Saito (eds.), Handbook of Japanese linguistics, 20–53. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195307344.013.0002
Harley, Heidi. 2009. The morphology of nominalizations and the syntax of vP. In Monika Rathert & Anastasia Giannadikou (eds.), Quantification, definiteness and nominalization, 320–342. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harley, Heidi. 2012. Lexical decomposition in modern syntactic theory. In Markus Werning, Wolfram Hinzen & Edouard Machery (eds.), The Oxford handbook of compositionality, 328–350. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199541072.013.0015
Harley, Heidi & Rolf Noyer. 2000. Formal vs. encyclopedic properties of vocabulary: Evidence from nominalization. In Bert Peeters (ed.), The lexicon–encyclopedia interface, 349–74. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Haspelmath, Martin. 1993. More on the typology of inchoative/causative verb alternations. In Bernard Comrie & Maria Polinsky (eds.), Causatives and transitivity, 87–120. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/slcs.23.05has
Haugen, Jason & Daniel Siddiqi. 2016. Towards a restricted realization theory: Multimorphemic monolistemicity, portmanteaux and post-linearization spanning. In Daniel Sidiqqi & Heidi Harley (eds.), Morphological metatheory. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.229.12hau
Jover Peralta, Anselmo & Tomas Osuna. 1950. Diccionario Guaraní-Español y Español-Guaraní. Buenos Aires: Editorial Tupã.
Katzir, Roni. 2007. Structurally-defined alternatives. Linguistics & Philosophy 30. 669–690. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-008-9029-y
Koontz-Garboden, Andrew. 2009. Anticausativization. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 27. 77–138. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-008-9058-9
Koontz-Garboden, Andrew & John Beavers. 2017. Change of state verbs and the semantics of roots. In Brendel, Cole, Aaron Kaplan, Abby Kaplan, Miranda McCarvel, Jeff Pynes & Ed Rubin (eds.), Proceedings of the 34th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, 347–354. Sommerville, MA: Cascadilla.
Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Johan Rooryck & Laurie Zaring (eds.), Phrase structure and the lexicon, 109–137. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8617-7_5
Kratzer, Angelika. 2000. Building statives. In Lisa J. Jonathan, Jeff Good, Darya Kavitskaya, Alyssa Wulf & Alan Yu (eds.), Proceedings of the Twenty-sixth Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistic Society: General Session and Parasession on Aspect, 109–37. Berkeley, CA: Berkeley Linguistics Society. DOI: http://doi.org/10.3765/bls.v26i1.1131
Kratzer, Angelika. 2005. Building resultatives. In Claudia Maienborn & Angelika Wöllstein-Leisten (eds.), Event arguments in syntax, semantics and discourse, 178–212. Tübingen: Niemeyer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110913798.177
Lakoff, George. 1965. On the nature of syntactic irregularity. NSF report 16. The Computational Laboratory of the University of Harvard.
Levin, Beth & Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1986. The formation of adjectival passives. Linguistic Inquiry 17. 623–661.
Levin, Beth & Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity: At the syntax-lexical semantics interface. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Magri, Giorgio. 2009. A theory of individual-level predicates based on blind mandatory scalar implicatures. Natural Language Semantics 17(3). 245–297. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-009-9042-x
Malchukov, Andrej L. 2005. Case pattern splits, verb types, and construction competition. In Mengistu Amberber & Helen de Hoop (eds.), Competition and variation in natural languages: the case for Case, 73–117. Amsterdam: Elsevier Publishers. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/B978-008044651-6/50006-9
Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: don’t try morphological analysis in the privacy of your own lexicon. In Alexis Dimitriadis, Laura Siegel, Clarisa Surek-Clark & Alexander Williams (eds.), University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics 4. 201–225. Philadelphia, PA: Penn Graduate Linguistics Society.
Marantz, Alec. 2013. Verbal argument structure: events and participants. Lingua 130. 152–168. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2012.10.012
McCawley, James. 1968. Lexical insertion in a transformational grammar without deep structure. In Proceedings of the Chicago Linguistics Society 4. 71–80. Chicago, IL: Chicago Linguistic Society.
McIntyre, Andrew. 2013. Adjectival passives and adjectival participles in English. In Artemis Alexiadou & Florian Schäfer (eds.), Non-canonical passives, 21–42. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.205.02mci
Meltzer-Asscher, Aya. 2011. Adjectival passives in Hebrew: Evidence for parallelism between the adjectival and verbal systems. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 29(3). 815–855. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-011-9138-0
Nedjalkov, Vladimir & Sergei Jaxontov. 1988. The typology of resultative constructions. In Vladimir Nedjalkov & Sergei Jaxontov (eds.), Typology of resultative constructions, 3–62. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/tsl.12.06ned
Parsons, Terence. 1990. Events in the semantics of English: A study in subatomic semantics. Cambridge, MA: the MIT Press.
Pylkkänen, Liina. 2002. Introducing arguments. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation.
Pylkkänen, Liina. 2008. Introducing arguments. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262162548.001.0001
Ramchand, Gillian. 2008. Verb meaning and the lexicon: A first phase syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511486319
Rapp, Irene. 1996. Zustand? Passiv? Überlegungen sum sogenannten “Zustandspassiv”. Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft 15(2). 231–65. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/zfsw.1996.15.2.231
Schäfer, Florian. 2007. On the nature of anticausative morphology: External arguments in change-of-state contexts. Stuttgart: University of Stuttgart dissertation. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.126
Shibatani, Masayoshi & Prashant Pardeshi. 2002. The causative continuum. In Masayoshi Shibatani (ed.), The grammar of causation and interpersonal manipulation, 85–126. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/tsl.48.07shi
Siddiqi, Daniel. 2009. Syntax within the word: Economy, allomorphy and argument selection in Distributed Morphology. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.138
Thomas, Guillaume. 2014. Nominal tense and temporal implicatures: Evidence from Mbyá. Natural Language Semantics 22. 357–412. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-014-9108-2
Tonhauser, Judith. 2006. The temporal semantics of noun phrases: Evidence from Guaraní. Stanford, CA: Stanford University dissertation.
Tonhauser, Judith. 2007. Nominal tense? The meaning of Guaraní nominal temporal markers. Language 83. 831–869. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2008.0037
Tsunoda, Tasaku. 1981. Split case-marking in verb types and tense/aspect/mood. Linguistics 19. 389–438. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/ling.1981.19.5-6.389
Velázquez-Castillo, Maura. 2002a. Grammatical relations in active systems: The case of Guaraní. Functions of Language 9(2). 133–167. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/fol.9.2.03vel
Velázquez-Castillo, Maura. 2002b. Guaraní causative constructions. In Masayoshi Shibatani (ed.), The grammar of causation and interpersonal manipulation, 507–534. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/tsl.48.18vel
von Stechow, Arnim. 1996. The different readings of wieder ‘again’: a structural account. Journal of Semantics 13. 87–138. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/13.2.87
Wasow, Thomas. 1977. Transformations and the lexicon. In Peter Culicover, Thomas Wasow & Joan Bresnan (eds.), Formal syntax, 327–360. New York, NY: Academic Press.
Williams, Alexander. 2015. Arguments in syntax and semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139042864
Zubizarreta, Maria Luisa & Roumi Pancheva. 2017a. A formal characterization of person-based alignment: The case of Paraguayan Guaraní. Natural Language Linguistic Theory 35. 1161–1204. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-016-9357-5
Zubizarreta, Maria Luisa & Roumi Pancheva. 2017b. A note on the syntax of possession in Paraguayan Guaraní. In Elena Castroviejo Miró, Olga Fernández Soriano & Isabel Pérez-Jiménez (eds.), Boundaries, phases, and interfaces, 87–106. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.239.05zub