1 INTRODUCTION

This paper proposes an analysis of an interesting phenomenon found with the Hebrew focus sensitive particle be-sax ha-kol (literally translated as ‘in sum the all/whole’), and examines implications of the analysis for issues in the research of focus/alternative sensitivity, typologies of scalar particles, gradability and (not-) at-issueness.

The core observation illustrating this phenomenon is two readings that be-sax ha-kol can give rise to. The first is an exclusive reading, of the sort we find with the English exclusive particles only or just, as in e.g. (1), and the second is what we call the approximative reading, which is similar to the one found with more or less, as in e.g. (2):1

    1. (1)
    1. saba
    2. grandfather
    1. sheli
    2. mine
    1. haya
    2. was
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. pakid.
    2. clerk
    1. ‘My grandfather was only / just a clerk.’
    1. (2)
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is more or less clean.’

Based on preliminary suggestions and observations made in Orenstein & Greenberg (2013); Orenstein (2015; 2016); Greenberg & Orenstein (2016), we propose that despite inducing these two readings, be-sax ha-kol is not ambiguous, i.e. does not denote an exclusive and an approximative operations. Instead, we propose that in both readings it should be analyzed as a member of a typology of exclusive particles in Hebrew, along particles like rak (‘only’) and stam (‘merely’). Following previous work, we take members in this typology cross linguistically to convey a positive and a negative semantic component, namely, the truth of their prejacent, p, and the exclusion of stronger alternatives on a relevant scale, respectively, but to potentially vary along several parameters.

Various studies have already suggested some parameters along which exclusive particles – both within and across languages – can vary. Some examples of such parameters are given below:

  1. The ordering of alternatives along the scale: for example, Beaver & Clark (2008); Orenstein & Greenberg (2010) and Coppock & Beaver (2014) show that whether the alternatives are ranked in terms of entailment (where stronger alternatives asymmetrically entail weaker ones) or in terms of some evaluative or rank-based ordering can distinguish between exclusive particles. For example, whereas English merely and Hebrew stam are specified for evaluative ordering, English exclusive, exclusively, sole and Hebrew yaxid (‘sole’), are specified to operate over entailment scales. Other particles, like English only and Hebrew rak (‘only’) seem to be compatible with both types of orderings.

  2. The nature of the alternatives to p: e.g., whether they are atom-based or sum-based alternatives, discussed in Liu (2007). Liu shows that this distinction can derive different uses of Mandarin jiu: an exclusive use vs. a rank-order use, respectively.

  3. The strength of the exclusive component discussed in Liu (2017) as well: This parameter distinguishes Mandarin jiu from zhi. While zhi (like English only) requires the rejection of all non-weaker alternatives, jiu has the weaker requirement that all alternatives stronger than p are rejected.

  4. The semantic type of the particle discussed in Coppock & Beaver (2014). This suggestion can explain contrasts of e.g. The only/sole candidate vs. Only/#sole John arrived.

  5. The question under discussion (QUD) that the exclusive helps answering discussed in Coppock & Beaver (2014) as well. According to them, sentences like e.g. x is a mere P are used to answer the question What is x like? whereas sentences like x is a sole P of y answer the relational question What is an R of y?

  6. The position of the prejacent on the scale discussed in Orenstein & Greenberg (2010) and Orenstein (2016). For example, while the prejacent of only and rak can be very close to the top of the scale (e.g. having only one alternative above it), that of English merely and Hebrew stam needs to be low, having more alternatives above it.

  7. The status of the preajcent and of the exclusive component discussed in Bassi et al. (2019), who suggest that with overt only the prejacent is presupposed and the exclusive component is asserted, whereas with covert exh the status of these components is reversed.

The main goal of this paper is to suggest an additional relevant parameter of variation that should be used to enrich the typology of exclusive particles, namely the ability vs. inability of the particle to operate over overt-based vs. covert-based alternatives. In particular, we will suggest below that on both the exclusive and approximative readings be-sax ha-kol conveys the same type of interpretative components, namely the truth of the prejacent and the exclusion of stronger alternatives, as all scalar exclusives do. However, unlike the unmarked Hebrew exclusive rak (‘only’), be-sax ha-kol can associate with covert focused material – specifically the covert degree modifier pos – and operate over alternatives which vary with respect to this element. We will suggest that the fact that this particle can get an approximative interpretation results precisely from this ability. In addition, we will examine wider implications of our proposal regarding the relationship between scale structure and standards with gradable expressions, the difference between true and derivative approximators, and factors affecting variability in the (not) at-issue status of interpretive components.

The paper is structured as follows. In the next section we present differences between rak and be-sax ha-kol, concentrating on the exclusive and approximative readings of the latter. Section 3 offers our proposal of how to derive the two readings of be-sax ha-kol, and explores the types of gradable expressions which can and which cannot license the approximative reading in light of the literature on the scale structure and standards with such expressions. Section 4 is devoted to examining and rejecting a potential simpler analysis where be-sax ha-kol is ambiguous between an exclusive and an approximative operator. We argue that this suggestion is not only less economical than ours, but unlike our theory, it fails to capture differences between the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol and true approximative particles (like more or less). Section 5 discusses the observation that the (not)-at-issuness status of the interpretive components with the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol is reversed relative to the one found with the exclusive reading and with typical exclusive particles like only/just. We examine ways to capture this difference within our proposal, relying on theories which point out other cases of reversed (not)-at-issueness with exclusives, as well as those which take the status of interpretive content to be more flexible than has been traditionally assumed. Section 6 concludes.

2 DATA: TWO READINGS OF BE-SAX HA-KOL

This section describes in more detail the exclusive and the approximative readings of the Hebrew particle be-sax ha-kol mentioned above, which at least on the surface seem very different from one another.2

On its exclusive reading be-sax ha-kol can be translated as only or just. This is seen again in (3), where be-sax ha-kol is interchangeable with rak, the unmarked exclusive particle in Hebrew.

    1. (3)
    1. a.
    1. saba
    2. grandfather
    1. sheli
    2. mine
    1. haya
    2. was
    1. rak
    2. only
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. pakid.
    2. clerk
    1. ‘My grandfather was only / just a clerk.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Danny
    2. Danny
    1. hizmin
    2. invited
    1. rak
    2. rak
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. et
    2. ACC.
    1. Rina
    2. Rina
    1. la-mesiba.
    2. to-the party
    1. ‘Danny invited only / just Rina to the party.’

Similarly to rak in (3a, b), be-sax ha-kol gives rise to the inferences that my grandfather did not have any other more important or prestigious profession,3 and that Danny did not invite more people (besides Rina) to the party, respectively.

However, when be-sax ha-kol appears with some gradable expressions (e.g. gradable adjectives or verbs), the prominent reading it yields is approximative, similarly to the reading induced by paxot o yoter (‘more or less’).

    1. (4)
    1. a.
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the- room
    1. paxot
    2. less
    1. o
    2. or
    1. yoter
    2. more
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is more or less clean.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ani
    2. I
    1. paxot
    2. less
    1. o
    2. or
    1. yoter
    2. more
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. mevin
    2. understand
    1. et
    2. ACC.
    1. ha-teorya.
    2. the-theory
    1. ‘I more or less understand the theory.’

On this approximative reading, be-sax ha-kol, like paxot or yoter (‘more or less’), raises two main inferences, a negative and a positive one. To illustrate, (4a) conveys that the room is not maximally clean, but it is nonetheless considered clean. The presence of the first, negative, inference is supported by the felicity contrasts between the responses in (5) and (6).

    1. (5)
    1. A:
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is more or less clean.’
    1.  
    1. B:
    1. lo
    2. not
    1. naxon
    2. right
    1. /
    2. /
    1. #naxon.
    2.   right.
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. legamrey
    2. completely
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘That’s not right. /#That’s right. The room is completely clean.’
    1. (6)
    1. A:
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is clean.’
    1.  
    1. B:
    1. #lo
    2.   not
    1. naxon
    2. right
    1. /
    2. /
    1. naxon.
    2. right.
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. legamrey
    2. completely
    1. naki.4
    2. clean
    1.    ‘#That’s not right / That’s right. The room is completely clean.’

To support the presence of the second, postive, inference, namely that the room is considered clean, we can rely on a diagnostic suggested in Amaral & del Prete (2010) concerning differences between approximators like around, more or less, and almost as shown in (7) and (8).

(7) A:   Leo arrived almost at 3 p.m.
  B:   That’s false, actually Leo arrived at 3 p.m.
(8) A:   Leo arrived around 3 p.m.
  B: #That’s false, actually Leo arrived at 3 p.m.

As can be seen in the contrast between (9) and (10) below, be-sax ha-kol behaves like around/more or less, and unlike almost (kim’at), in this respect.

    1. (9)
    1. A:
    1. ha- xeder
    2. the-room
    1. kimat
    2. almost
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is almost clean.’
    1.  
    1. B:
    1. lo. le-ma’ase
    2. no. actually
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘No. Actually, the room is clean.’
    1. (10)
    1. A:
    1. ha- xeder
    2. the-room
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is more or less clean.’
    1.  
    1. B:
    1. #/??lo. le-ma’ase
    2.          no. actually
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. #/??‘No. Actually the room is clean.’

The difference between negating vs. entailing the prejacent with kim’at (‘almost’) vs. be-sax ha-kol, respectively, is further supported by the contrast in (11).

    1. (11)
    1. A:
    1.   ha- xeder
    2.   the-room
    1. naki?
    2. clean?
    1.    ‘Is the room clean?’
    1.  
    1. B:
    1.   lo./#ken.
    2.   no. /yes.
    1. hu
    2. It
    1. kim’at
    2. almost
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1.    ‘No. / #Yes. It is almost clean.’
    1.  
    1. B’:
    1. #lo. / ken.
    2.   no. /yes.
    1. hu
    2. it
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. hakol
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1.    ‘#No. / Yes. It is more or less clean.’

Notice, however, that the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol is constrained: while it is perfectly felicitous with adjectives associated with scales which have an upper-bound, it is degraded with one-dimensional adjectives associated with lower-closed and with open scales. This is illustrated by the felicity contrast in (12) with the totally closed, lower-closed and open-scale one-dimensional adjectives full, dirty and expensive, respectively.

    1. (12)
    1. ha-kos
    2. the-cup
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. mele’a
    2. full/
    1. /
    2.  
    1. #meluxlexet
    2. #dirty/
    1. /
    2.  
    1. #yekara.
    2. #expensive
    1. ‘The cup is more or less full/ #dirty/ #expensive.’

Given these data, there seem to be two main options with which to analyze be-sax ha-kol. One is to treat the particle as ambiguous between an exclusive and an approximative operator. The other option is to derive its two readings from a parametric variation arising from a basically unified semantics. In this paper we adopt the second option, which we detail in the next section. In Section 4 we reject the first option.

3 PROPOSAL

3.1 THE BASIC IDEA

We suggest that on both of its readings be-sax ha-kol is a focus sensitive particle which conveys the positive and negative components conveyed by scalar exclusive particles cross linguistically, i.e. the truth of its prejacent, p, and the falsehood of all stronger alternatives in C (the contextually supplied set of focus alternatives to p). This is seen in (13).5

(13) Interpretative components conveyed by scalar exclusive particles:6
  a. The positive component: w ∈ p
  b. The negative component: ∀q∈C ∧ q >s p → w∉q
    Where C ⊆ llpllF ∧ llpll0 ∈ C ∧ ∃q≠p ∧ q∈C

(13) (see e.g. Beaver & Clark 2008 and Roberts 2011) is based on the assumption that exclusive particles are focus sensitive, namely that they operate on alternatives triggered by focus. This is captured in the literature by letting the focus sensitive operator associate with a focused element (which is usually also stressed and accented) and to create a set of alternatives C, which is a contextually supplied subset of the focus semantic value of this element. These alternatives are constructed by substituting this element with another element of the same semantic type (cf. Rooth 1985; 1992).

Our main claim is that although be-sax ha-kol shares these interpretative components with e.g. Hebrew rak and English only, it differs from them in that it is more flexible regarding the overtness or covertness of its associate, and as a result, with respect to the kind of alternatives it operates over. In particular, we suggest that be-sax ha-kol, but not rak, can associate with the covert degree modifier pos (cf. e.g. von Stechow 1984a and Kennedy & McNally 2005a). In this case too, alternatives are constructed by substituting this focused element with other (covert or overt) elements of the same semantic type, i.e. with other degree modifiers. We suggest that the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol results from its association with the covert pos.

Preliminary support for the idea that the apparent ambiguity of be-sax ha-kol is due to its ability to operate over two different sorts of alternatives can be seen in (14). In particular, we observe that changing the salience of alternatives in the context affects the prominence of the two readings. Above we saw that a sentence like (2) ((14b here) has an approximative reading. But (2) can also have an exclusive reading, indicating that the room is clean, but does not have other properties. This reading is made more prominent when properties which can replace the one denoted by the overt adjective clean are made salient in the context. In contrast (14a) with rak is not ambiguous and can only have the exclusive reading, i.e. mean that the room is clean but does not have the other relevant properties, i.e. is not large and does not have a view to the sea.

    1. (14)
    1. Context: John and Mary booked a room in a hotel for their important guests and asked that the room will be clean, large, and with view to the sea. John says:
    1.  
    1. a.
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. rak
    2. only
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is only clean.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ha- xeder
    2. the-room
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is only clean.’ / ‘The room is more or less clean.’

3.2 THEORETICAL BACKGROUND: THE “TYPE OF ALTERNATIVE” PARAMETER, AND ASSOCIATION WITH OVERT VS. COVERT FOCUS

Before showing in more detail how the exclusive and approximative readings of be-sax ha-kol can be derived from the difference in the type of alternatives this particle operates over, we would like to point out that our suggestion is similar in its general reasoning to a suggestion made in Liu (2017) regarding apparent ambiguities between Mandarin jiu, and dou. Let us quote Liu here (2017: 62):

“I take it to be our basic assumption that an FP [a focus particle] operates on a set of alternatives (Rooth 1985). Then, the meaning of an expression containing an FP is a function of (a) the meaning of the FP, (b) the meaning of FP’s prejacent, π and (c) π’s alternatives. With this background, what we propose about Mandarin FPs is that (c), instead of (a), is the locus of ‘ambiguity’: with varieties of alternatives, apparent distinct meanings can be derived without altering the semantics of the FP.”

Liu takes this behavior of Mandarin focus particles to be part of a more general pattern, where different sorts of alternative sets are posited for a single alternative operator to create different interpretations (cf. Chierchia 2013 for different alternatives for only-like and for even-like operators). To the extent that our suggestion is on the right track, the behavior of be-sax ha-kol in Hebrew can further support this pattern.

More specifically, the variation in the type of alternatives we propose concerns overt-based vs. covert-based alternatives, which we take to derive from the association of be-sax ha-kol with overt vs. covert focused material.

This claim is not trivial, though, since focused elements are usually taken to be overt and prosodically marked. Moreover, some authors explicitly claim that focus must be realized phonologically, as in the discussion of Second Occurrence Focus7 (SOF henceforth). For example, Partee 1999 argues that the second occurrence of vegetables in (15) is not prosodically marked, although it is bound by only, and concludes that it is not focused. Rooth 1992 makes a similar claim regarding the second occurrence of rice in (16).

(15) Partee (1999: 2016)
  Everyone already knew that Mary only eats [vegetables]F. If even [Paul]F knew that Mary only eats [vegetables]SOF, then he should have suggested a different restaurant.
(16) Rooth (1992: 109)
  People who [grow]F rice usually only [eat]F rice.

In contrast, some theories argue that SOF is prosodically marked after all, although not in the same form as the first occurring focus (see e.g. Beaver et al. 2007). What is more important to us are suggestions that prosodic prominence is actually not a necessary condition for the status of an expression as focused. For example, Féri & Ishihara (2009: 8) argue that in many cases “phonetic marking of focus can be masked by independent phonetic/phonological effects”, such as de-accentuation due to competition with stronger phonetic realization on another element in the sentence, or having an element in post-nuclear position. In such cases, Féri & Ishihara propose, an element can be focused even if it has no prosodic prominence.

Similar cases were pointed out in e.g. the free-focused construction in (17), where an element is de-accented due to givenness, although it is focused (cf. Kadmon 2001 and Wagner 2012).

(17) Wagner (2012: 3)
  A: Smith walked into a store. What happened next?
  B: A detective ARRESTED Smith.

Even more relevant to our proposal is (18) from Kadmon & Sevi (2011), where the exclusive particle only is argued to associate with the focused element Larry, even though it is not accented (see also Umbach 2009 on accented noch and Egg & Zimmermann 2011 on accented doch):

(18) Kadmon & Sevi (2011: 8)
  A: Larry danced with Mary.
  B: Yes. The problem is that ONLY [Larry]F danced with Mary.

In general, then, focused material is argued to optionally carry no prosodic prominence, and focus sensitive particles were argued to be able to associate with prosodically unmarked focus.

Our proposal takes such suggestions one step further, in that it takes be-sax ha-kol to be able to associate with elements which, by virtue of being covert, have no phonological realization, and hence cannot be accented. We can take this to be a special (and, in fact extreme) case of Féri & Ishihara’s (2009) idea that a focused element can have no phonological marking if this marking is blocked due to some other phonological conditions (in our case, due to being covert).

Importantly, in this sense too, be-sax ha-kol is not isolated, since the ability to associate with covert material has been reported for other focus sensitive operators as well, for example for the covert O and E (as in the interpretation of any and give a damn) and the overt Hindi bhii (Chierchia 2013), the only-like particle just in English (Wiegand 2017), yielding an unexplanatory reading, the even-like BIXLAL in Hebrew (Greenberg 2020), and voobsce in Russian (Miashkur 2017; 2018), yielding intensification effects similar to very, as well as readings similar to at all. The ability to associate with covert material was claimed in these theories to explain special readings of these operators, which are not found with the unmarked correlates of these particles, e.g. the exclusive only, or the unmarked even-like particles in Hebrew (afilu) and Russian (daze).

Given this background, we turn now to show in detail how the proposed ability of be-sax ha-kol to associate with both overt and covert material can derive its exclusive and approximative readings, respectively.

3.3 DERIVING THE EXCLUSIVE READING OF BE-SAX HA-KOL

Henceforth, we will refer to the exclusive reading of be-sax ha-kol as in (3), repeated here, as be-sax ha-kolexcl. We propose that this reading results from the fact that be-sax ha-kol associates with overt focused elements, just like rak (and only) do, leading to standard, Roothian alternatives.

    1. (3)
    1. a.
    1. Danny
    2. Danny
    1. hizmin
    2. invited
    1. rak
    2. rak
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolexcl
    2. ha-kolexcl
    1. et
    2. ACC.
    1. [rina]F
    2. rina
    1. la-
    2. to the
    1. mesiba.
    2. party
    1. ‘Danny only / just invited [Rina]F to the party.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. saba
    2. grandfather
    1. sheli
    2. mine
    1. haya
    2. was
    1. rak
    2. rak
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolexcl
    2. ha-kolexcl
    1. [pakid]F.
    2. clerk
    1. ‘My grandfather was only / just [a clerk]F.’

Given these focused elements, the sets of alternatives in (3a, b) look as in (19a, b), respectively, where the prejacent is in boldface.

(19) a. {…..Danny invited Rina, Danny invited Rina and Yosi, Danny invited Rina, Yosi, and Moshe…..}
  b. {….My grandfather was a clerk, my grandfather was a manager, my grandfather was the president of the company…}

Given the two semantic components conveyed by exclusives in (13) and these sets of alternatives, (3a) and (3b) convey (a) the truth of the prejacent, i.e. that Danny invited Rina/that my grandfather was a clerk, and (b) the negation of all stronger alternatives in C, e.g. that it is false that Danny invited Rina and Yosi, Rina and Yosi and Moshe/that it is false that my grandfather was a manager or the president of this company.

Notice that be-sax ha-kolexcl, like rak, is compatible both with entailment scales, as in (19a), where stronger alternatives asymmetrically entail weaker ones, and with evaluative, or rank order scales, as in (19b) (cf. Orenstein 2016). However, there is a slight difference between rak and be-sax ha-kolexcl in terms of the scales. For example, in (3b) with rak we can also get the complement exclusion reading (using Coppock & Beaver’s 2014 terminology), where my grandfather had no other profession besides being a clerk, derived by an operation over entailment scales. Though this reading is less prominent than the evaluative reading (probably due to the real-world knowledge according to which people have one profession at a time), it is still possible. In contrast, with be-sax ha-kolexcl this reading is harder to get, and the evaluative reading, where my grandfather never had any profession more prestigious than being a clerk, is much more prominent. On this reading, even if my grandfather worked for some time in a less prestigious job, e.g. as a cleaning person, the sentence is still true and felicitous. When an evaluative ordering is salient, then, it seems that be-sax ha-kolexcl prefers it, whereas rak is more neutral, or less specified.8

3.4 DERIVING THE APPROXIMATIVE READING OF BE-SAX HA-KOL

3.4.1 THE BASIC DERIVATION

We now examine the more interesting story, which is the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol, which we will henceforth refer to as be-sax ha-kolapprox. To do that, we assume that be-sax ha-kolapprox conveys the same two interpretative components as be-sax ha-kolexcl, but differs from it in associating with a covert degree modifier, pos, which was argued to modify gradable adjectives in the positive form.9 Let us first briefly review the relevant claims regarding pos.

We follow the view that gradable adjectives are of type <d, <e,t>> (e.g., von Stechow 1984; Kennedy & McNally 2005a, among many others), indicating that an individual x has the degree d on the scale associated with the adjective, as in (20), where mA(x) represents the projection of x onto the scale associated with the adjective A.

(20) Kennedy & McNally (2005a: 367)
  [[A]]c,g = λdλx. mA(x)=d

The value of the degree d argument is not saturated and can be set by overt degree modifiers as in (21), which following Kennedy & McNally (2005a), we take to be of type <<d,<e,t>>, <e, t>>, as seen in (22), where R represents some restriction on d.

(21) a. John is two meters tall.
  b. The cup is completely full.
(22) Kennedy & McNally (2005a: 367)
  [[Deg (P)]]c,g = λGλx. ∃d[R(d) ∧ G(d)(x)]

For example, the measure phrases two meters/completely in (21a), specify the degree d to be at least two meters/is at the maximal endpoint of the scale, respectively.

In the case of apparently unmodified gradable adjectives, i.e. those in the positive form, as in (23a), the d argument is taken to be given a value through a covert degree modifier, pos, as in (23b). Pos, type <<d,<e,t>>,<e,t>> as well, relates the degree d to a relevant standard of comparison set on the scale associated with the adjective, as seen in (24).

(23) a. John is tall.
  b. John is pos tall.
(24) Kennedy & McNally (2005a: 350)
  [[pos]]g,c = λGλx. ∃d[standard (d)(G)(C)∧G(d)(x)]

For example, (23b) is true if John’s tallness is at least as high as the standard of tallness in C.

Given this background, we now suggest that be-sax ha-kolapprox associates with the covert degree modifier pos. For example, (2) above, repeated as in (25a) is represented as in (25b) where pos is in focus.

    1. (25)
    1. a.
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘The room is more or less clean.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. pos
    2. pos
    1. clean.
    2. clean.
    1. ‘The room is more or less clean.’

Crucially, since in this case pos is in focus, it is the source of the alternatives. Following Rooth’s ideas (1985; 1992) the alternatives are propositions identical to The room is pos clean where pos is replaced by other elements of the same semantic type, that is, by other degree modifiers of the type <<d,<e,t>>,<e,t>>.10 This is schematically seen in (26).

(26) {….The room is pos clean, The room is DegMod clean….}

Now, given the semantics of be-sax ha-kol, all alternatives q in C which are stronger than p are negated. We suggest that such alternatives are those with maximizing degree modifiers, i.e., The room is maximally/completely clean, as seen in (27).

(27) a. {…. the room is pos clean, the room is completely/ maximally clean}
  b. {∃d[stand.(d)(clean)(C)clean(d)(the room), ∃d[d = max(clean) ∧ clean(d)(the room)}

Thus, given the core exclusive semantics of be-sax ha-kol in (13) and this set of alternatives, (25) makes two semantic contributions. The first is that The room is pos clean is true, i.e. that there is a degree of cleanness d which is at least as high as the standard for cleanness, and the room is clean to this degree d. The second is that the stronger alternative, namely The room is completely/maximally clean is false.

The result of combining these two interpretative components is exactly the one we observed in Section 2, namely that the room is considered clean (since its degree of cleanness is at least as high as the standard), but it is not maximally clean. The approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol, then, is successfully derived.

Notice, however, that this kind of derivation relies on a non-trivial assumption, namely that the standard degree with total adjectives like clean can be non-maximal. We turn to this point in the next subsection.

3.4.2 THE APPROXIMATIVE READING OF BE-SAX HA-KOL WITH TOTAL ADJECTIVES AND THE VALUE OF THE STANDARD

A prominent claim in the literature on gradable adjectives, made in Kennedy & McNally (2005a), is that the value of the standard degree is constrained by the structure of the scale associated with the adjective. Thus, open-scale adjectives like tall are interpreted relative to a contextual standard (determined by, e.g. comparison classes). In contrast, the standard of lower-closed scale (partial) adjectives like dirty and wet is just above the scale minimal point, and crucially, that of upper-closed scale (total) adjectives like clean, straight and transparent, is always at the maximal endpoint of the scale.11

But if the standard with upper-closed adjectives is indeed always at the maximal endpoint of the scale, then for example, the negative component conveyed by sentences with be-sax ha-kolapparox as in (2) and (25) (that the room is not completely clean) would contradict the positive component (that the room is pos clean, i.e. clean to at least the standard degree). This would wrongly predict sentences with be-sax ha-kolapprox to be systematically infelicitous. Thus, our suggestion above can only hold if we assume that pos A does not necessarily equal completely A for total adjectives. But this would clash with what is suggested in Kennedy & McNally (2005a).12

There are, though, independent suggestions, e.g. Rotstein & Winter (2004); McNally (2011) and Toledo & Sassoon (2011) which take the standard with at least some total, upper-closed adjectives in the positive form to be potentially lower than the maximal endpoint. In this paper we follow this view and take it to explain how in sentences like (2) the room can be pos clean but not completely clean at the same time.

This position can now lead to a prediction: to the extent that a certain total adjective, or a certain use of such an adjective, does require a maximal standard, the status of be-sax ha-kolapprox with it will be degraded. Rotstein & Winter (2004) label adjectives with such maximal standards pointal. Based on contrasts like (28), they take complete to be such a pointal adjective, as opposed to clean, which is non-pointal.

(28) Rotstein & Winter (2004: 14)
  a.   Both towels are clean, but the red towel is cleaner than the blue one.
  b. ?Both your painting and my painting are complete, but your painting is more complete than mine.

Similarly, Toledo & Sassoon (2011) argue that while a full tank is many times not completely full, an empty one tends to be taken as completely empty. This is motivated by contrasts in (29). Using Rotstein & Winter’s terminology, then, empty, unlike full, tends to behave as pointal, at least when applied to objects like tanks.

(29) Toledo & Sassoon (2011: 139)
  a.   The gas tank is full, but you can still top it off. It’s not completely full yet.
  b. ?The gas tank is empty, but there are still a few drops left. It’s not completely empty yet.

Our prediction, then, is that be-sax ha-kolapprox will be degraded in sentences with such pointal adjectives. As can be seen in (30) and (31), this is borne out.13

    1. (30)
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. ha- ze
    2. the-this
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki
    2. clean
    1. /
    2.  
    1. ??shalem.
    2.     complete
    1. ‘This room is more or less clean / ??complete.’
    1. (31)
    1. ha-mexal
    2. the-tank
    1. ha- ze
    2. the-this
    1. be-sax
    2. be-xax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. male
    2. full
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ??rek.
    2.     empty
    1. ‘This tank is more or less full / ??empty.’

Moreover, we follow Rotstein & Winter (2004) and Toledo & Sassoon (2011) in taking the pointal vs. non-pointal distinction to be sensitive to context. For example, although empty behaves as pointal when applied to tanks (as shown in (29a)), it seems to have a non-pointal use as well, as in The theatre is empty, originally pointed out in Kennedy & McNally (2005a) which can be rather easily uttered when there are still a few people in the theatre. While Kennedy & McNally (2005a) take such cases to illustrate imprecise uses (modelled using e.g. Lasersohn’s 1999 pragmatic halos), and thus to still be compatible with the view that the standard of empty is maximal, we assume here that such cases illustrate a non-pointal use of empty, namely one with a non-maximal standard.

We predict, then, that the status of be-sax ha-kolapprox with rek (‘empty’) will be better when the subject is the theatre than when it is the tank. As seen in (32), this prediction is borne out. Although we got some variations in speaker judgements regarding the status of the former, our consultants agreed that it is better than the latter:

    1. (32)
    1. ?ha-teatron
    2.   the-theatre
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ??ha-mexal
    2.     the-tank
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. rek
    2. empty
    1. hayom.
    2. today
    1. ‘?The theatre / ??the tank is more or less empty today.’

Thus, the behavior of be-sax ha-kolapprox can be taken to provide further support for the independently made claims that the standard of total adjectives in the positive form is not necessarily at the maximal endpoint of the scale, and more generally, that scale structure and standards can be, at least to some extent, dissociated (pace Kennedy & McNally 2005a, and as in McNally 2011 and Toledo & Sassoon 2011).

It is important to emphasize, though, that our theory does not rule out the fact that in general the standard for total adjectives in the positive form can be set to the maximal endpoint. In fact, in many cases this is the default situation, and it is always one of the possible values of the standard with such adjectives. Crucially, then, when be-sax ha-kolapprox associates with pos, its presence leads to constraining the standard, i.e. to reinterpreting the prejacent so that the standard variable in it is set to be necessarily non-maximal.14 Without such a re-interpretation, we can get a clash between the default or contextually supplied interpretation of the prejacent, in which the standard can be maximal, and the negative component. This process is reflected in (33), where the constraint on the standard is in boldface. In particular, (33a), the positive component, conveys that the room is clean to some degree which is at least as high as the standard for cleanness, where this standard is not maximal. And (33b), the negative component, conveys that this degree of cleanness is not maximal either, i.e. that the room is not maximally clean.15

(33) a. Positive component: ∃d[stand.(d)(clean)(C) ∧ clean(d)(the room) ∧ stand.CLEAN < Max (clean)]
  b. Negative component: ¬∃d[d = max(clean) ∧ clean (d)(the room)]

3.4.3 WHY THE APPROXIMATIVE READING IS DEGRADED WITH (ONE-DIMENSIONAL) OPEN-SCALE ADJECTIVES

In Section 2 example (12) we pointed out that be-sax ha-kolapprox. prefers upper-closed adjectives and is degraded with open-scale and lower-closed adjectives. In this section we examine a possible reason for this fact.

A number of theories (e.g. cf. Roberts 2011; Alxatib 2013) suggest that when no stronger alternative to the prejacent exists, the use of exclusives is infelicitous. This is illustrated by the infelicity of only in e.g. #Only all students arrived, where the prejacent, namely, All students arrived is the strongest member in the relevant set of alternatives C, i.e. in {some students arrived; most students arrived; all students arrived}. A proposition stronger than the prejacent simply does not exist in this set (because the quantifier all is maximal). The result is that the exclusive operation of only is vacuous, violating the general non-vacuity constraint (Crnič 2011), and hence infelicitous.16

Now, it seems that when be-sax ha-kolapprox. associates with the covert pos modifier of (one-dimensional) lower-closed, or open-scale adjectives, we get a similar problem, i.e. no stronger alternatives exist in C. Consider (34).

    1. (34)
    1. ha-kvish
    2. the-road
    1. ha- ze
    2. the-this
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. batu’ax
    2. safe
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ??
    2. ??
    1. mesukan
    2. dangerous
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ??
    2. ??
    1. raxav.
    2. wide
    1. ‘This road is be-sax ha-kol safe/?? dangerous/?? wide.’

When p is This street is [pos]F dangerous or This street is [pos]F wide, a stronger alternative with completely modifying the adjective is not available in C, since completely cannot modify such adjectives. We propose, then, that it is the unavailability of stronger degree modifiers of lower-closed and relative adjectives associated with open scales which leads to a vacuous operation of be-sax ha-kolapprox, and thus to infelicity.

Two apparent issues with this proposal, though, are the ability of such adjectives to be modified by meod (‘very’) and mamaS (‘really’). Consider first the sentence in (35).

    1. (35)
    1. ha-rexov
    2. the-street
    1. ha-ze
    2. the-this
    1. meod
    2. very
    1. mesukan.
    2. dangerous
    1. ‘This street is very dangerous.’

The particle meod (‘very’) seems to be stronger than pos, and therefore (35) seems to be a potential stronger alternative than the prejacent This street is pos dangerous. If this is indeed the case, then we wrongly predict that sentences that have the template of The road is be-sax ha-kol dangerous could mean that the street is dangerous but not very dangerous. But this reading is absent from such sentences.

One way to rule out the availability of meod (‘very’) as a legitimate substitution for pos is to follow Kennedy & McNally (2005b), who analyze very as a modifier of type <<e,t>,<e,t>>, different from “true” degree modifiers (e.g. two meters/pos), type <<d,<e,t>>,<e,t>>. Based on previous analyses of very (e.g. Klein 1980), Kennedy & McNally (2005b) suggest that very takes [pos adjective], type <e,t>, and adjusts the standard of comparison associated with the gradable adjective that it modifies, based on a comparison class which includes only those individuals for whom the base standard applies. For example, in very tall, very applies to pos tall, and computes a new greater standard of height, based on a comparison class whose members are only those objects who exceed the standard of height determined by pos tall.

If this claim is adopted, then, we can argue that despite the fact that meod (‘very’) is a stronger modifier than pos, it cannot substitute the focused element pos, and thus cannot be used to construct a stronger alternative to the prejacent, because it is not of the right semantic type (as required in Rooth 1985; 1992).

Another apparent candidate that comes to mind as a potential stronger substitute for pos is the Hebrew modifier mamaS (‘really’). The sentence in (36) with mamaS is intuitively stronger than its minimally contrasting variant with pos.

    1. (36)
    1. ha-rexov
    2. the-street
    1. ha- ze
    2. the-this
    1. mamaS
    2. mamaS
    1. mesukan.
    2. dangerous
    1. ‘This street is really dangerous.’

However, this modifier does not seem to be a true degree modifier either. Similarly to Kennedy & McNally’s (2005b) claim regarding very, McNabb (2012) analyzes mamaS as a modifier of properties, type <<e,t>, <e,t>>. Moreover, given his analysis, mamaS does not make reference to degrees at all. It takes a property P of an individual x and returns a property which is true of the individual in all possible contexts, leading to an intensification effect (cf. also Beltrama & Bochnack 2015). McNabb supports this suggestion by showing that mamaS can also modify non-gradable expressions, as in (37).

    1. (37)
    1. a.
    1. ha-Skia
    2. the-sunset
    1. mitraxeSet
    2. happening
    1. mamaS
    2. mamaS
    1. axSav.
    2. now
    1. ‘The sunset is happening right now.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ha-malon
    2. the-hotel
    1. mamaS
    2. mamaS
    1. be-merkaz
    2. in-center
    1. Roma.
    2. Rome
    1. ‘The hotel is right in the center of Rome.’

Taking stock, we showed that be-sax ha-kolapprox is felicitous with upper-closed adjectives, like clean, but not with lower-closed or open-scale ones like dangerous or wide. We proposed that this is because of the (un)availability of stronger substitutes for pos, modifying the latter types of adjectives, namely maximality degree modifiers, which are of the same type as pos. Since with no stronger alternatives available, the exclusive function of be-sax ha-kol is vacuous, the approximative reading is blocked with such adjectives.

One adjective that can be used to test this claim is the Hebrew correlate of open, namely patu’ax. Given Kennedy & McNally’s (2005a) classification, unlike e.g. clean, or full, this adjective is partial in that its standard is minimal (e.g. a box which is just a little bit open can be considered already open). However, it is associated with an upper-closed scale, and it can be modified by completely. Thus, given our suggestion above this adjective is predicted to license be-sax ha-kolapprox although it is not total.

The prediction is borne out, as can be seen in (38), where be-sax ha-kolapprox is much better (fine or close to fine) with open than with the open-scale adjective expensive:

    1. (38)
    1. a.
    1. ha-kvish
    2. the-road
    1. ha- ze
    2. the-this
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. ?patu’ax
    2.   open
    1. /
    2. /
    1. #yakar.
    2.   expensive
    1. ‘This road is more or less ?open / #expensive.’

Another support for our proposal is the felicity of be-sax ha-kolapprox with relative multidimensional adjectives, as opposed to its infelicity with relative one-dimensional ones, illustrated in (39)–(40). We follow Sassoon (2013; 2018) in taking multidimensional adjectives to associate with several scales, each representing a “respect” or a “dimension”, e.g. being talented with respect to math, to history, etc. (in (39)), or being good with respect to service, food, comfortability, etc. (in (40)).

    1. (39)
    1. Danny
    2. Danny
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. #gavoha
    2.   tall
    1. /
    2. /
    1. nexmad
    2. nice
    1. /
    2. /
    1. idiot
    2. idiotic
    1. /
    2. /
    1. muxshar.
    2. talanted
    1. ‘Danny (is) more or less #tall / ?nice / ?idiotic / ?talented.’17
    1. (40)
    1. ha- tisa
    2. the flight
    1. hayta
    2. was
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. #aruka
    2.   long
    1. /
    2. /
    1. tova
    2. good
    1. /
    2. /
    1. gru’a.
    2. bad
    1. ‘The flight was more or less #long / good / bad / fine.’18

Following ideas in Sassoon (2018) and Greenberg (2020) to be pos A in the multidimensional reading is to have the adjectival property A with respect to a number n of relevant dimensions, where n is at least as high as the standard number of dimensions for this adjective.

Sassoon argues that the standard number of dimensions for multidimensioanl adjectives as in (39)–(40) is contextually determined, similarly to the standard degree with relative one-dimensional adjectives like tall. Importantly, however, multidimensional adjectives can be still classified as upper-closed, since they can be taken to associate with a scale with an upper-closed end, namely the scale involving all relevant dimensions of the adjectival property. Indeed, all such adjectives can be modified by the maximizing degree modifier be-kol ha-muvanim (‘in all respects’).

To derive the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol with multidimensional adjectives as in (39)–(40), then, we propose that here too the particle associates with a covert focused pos. In these cases, though, pos is used to set the standard number of dimensions for these adjectives (cf. Greenberg 2020 for a proposal). To illustrate, The flight was be-sax ha-kolapprox [pos]F good (cf. (40)), conveys the truth of the prejacent The flight was pos good as its positive inference, i.e. that the number of dimensions with respect to which the flight was good is at least as high as the contextually supplied standard number of relevant dimensions of being good. It also conveys the negative inference that the stronger alternative to the prejacent is false, namely that the flight was not good with respect to all relevant dimensions of being good. These are indeed the inferences we get with such a sentence.

4 EXAMINING (AND REJECTING) AN ALTERNATIVE ANALYSIS: BE-SAX HA-KOL AS AMBIGUOUS BETWEEN AN EXCLUSIVE AND AN APPROXIMATIVE PARTICLE

We proposed above that be-sax ha-kol always conveys the positive and negative components of scalar exclusive operators, and that be-sax ha-kolapprox is just a special case of it, derived from its association with the covert degree modifier pos.

But there seems to be a potential alternative hypothesis which one may consider, namely that be-sax ha-kolapprox is simply an approximator, similarly to e.g. more or less, about, sorta or -ish. Such approximators are usually analyzed as indicating that a standard of precision with respect to which a sentence with a scalar item is evaluated is low (cf. Sauerland & Stateva 2007), or as having a denotation within the pragmatic halo of the modified expression (cf. Lasersohn 1999; Morzycki 2011), etc.

One might want, then, to hypothesize that be-sax ha-kol is simply ambiguous between denoting an exclusive operation and an approximative operation. While this hypothesis is less economical than our own, in which this particle conveys the same interpretive components on both readings, it may seem simpler in that it does not force us to make the non-traditional assumption concerning the association of a focus sensitive particle with covert material (though see Section 3.2 for more particles reported to have this property).

Assuming that be-sax ha-kolapprox is simply an approximator may also seem natural given that in many cases it can be easily substituted with “real” approximators such as e.g. paxot o yoter (‘more or less’) or be-erex (‘around’), as illustrated in (41).

    1. (41)
    1. ha-xeder
    2. this-room
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. /
    2. /
    1. paxot
    2. less
    1. o
    2. or
    1. yoter
    2. more
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-erex
    2. approximately
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘This room is more or less clean.’

With all three expressions we get a similar reading that the room is close to being clean but is not completely clean.

However, a closer inspection of the data reveals differences between be-sax ha-kolapprox on the one hand, and typical approximative expressions, on the other hand.

Two of these differences were briefly mentioned above. First, unlike be-sax ha-kolapprox, which as discussed in Section 3.4.2 above is degraded with pointal adjectives, typical approximative particles are felicitous with such adjectives. For example, when trying to replace paxot o yoter in the following attested example with the pointal adjective shalem (‘complete’)19 with be-sax ha-kol, the result is degraded.

    1. (42)
    1. yadati
    2. -knew
    1. she-ha-ofano’a
    2. that-the-motorcycle
    1. yaxzor
    2. will-return
    1. elay
    2. to me
    1. paxot
    2. less
    1. o
    2. or
    1. yoter
    2. more
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ??be-xax ha-kolapprox
    2. be-sax ha-kol
    1. shalem.
    2. complete
    1. ‘I knew that the motorcycle will come back to me more or less complete.’

The opposite fact is illustrated in (43): unlike be-sax ha-kolapprox, which as we saw in Section 3.4.3 above is felicitous with relative multidimensional adjectives, paxot o yoter (as well as more or less) is degraded with many of these adjectives.

    1. (43)
    1. Danny
    2. Danny
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. /
    2. /
    1. ??paxot
    2.     less
    1. o
    2. or
    1. yoter
    2. more
    1. nexmad
    2. nice
    1. /
    2. /
    1. muxshar.
    2. talented
    1. ?’Danny is more or less nice / talented.’

In addition, unlike true approximators, be-sax ha-kolapprox cannot modify measure phrases. Consider, for example, the interpretational difference between (44a) and (44b).

    1. (44)
    1. a.
    1. ha-temperatura
    2. the-temperature
    1. kan
    2. here
    1. hi
    2. she
    1. paxot
    2. less
    1. o
    2. or
    1. yoter
    2. more
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-erex
    2. approximately
    1. 20
    2. 20
    1. maalot.
    2. degrees
    1. ‘The temperature here is more or less/approximately 20 degrees.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ha-temperatura
    2. the-temperature
    1. kan
    2. here
    1. hi
    2. she
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. 20
    2. 20
    1. maalot.
    2. degrees
    1. ‘The temperature here is only / #more or less 20 degrees.’

As seen in (44b), unlike the approximative reading we get with paxot o yoter (that the temperature is close to, but not precisely 20 degrees), the only reading we get with be-sax ha-kol is exclusive, namely, that the temperature is 20 degrees, and not higher (e.g. that it was expected to be warmer). The approximative reading is infelicitous here.

This difference is unexplained if be-sax ha-kolapprox is simply an approximator. In contrast, it is directly predicted if in order to get the approximative reading this particle must associate with a covert focused pos, which does not exist in (44).

Thus, we can now predict that, unlike real approximators, if we let be-sax ha-kol modify a gradable adjective which is itself modified by an overt degree modifier, the approximative reading will be blocked. Again, this is because in such cases too there is no covert pos to associate with. Indeed, the prediction is borne out, as seen in (45).

    1. (45)
    1. a.
    1. ha- kos
    2. the-glass
    1. paxot
    2. less
    1. o
    2. or
    1. yoter
    2. more
    1. /
    2. /
    1. be-erex
    2. approximately
    1. xaci
    2. half
    1. mele’a.
    2. full
    1. ‘The glass is more or less/approximately half full.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ha- kos
    2. the-glass
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kol
    2. ha-kol
    1. xaci
    2. half
    1. mele’a.
    2. full
    1. ‘The glass is only half full.’

Here too, as in (44a), the true approximators more or less/about give rise to an approximative reading (indicating that the glass is close to be half full), whereas be-sax ha-kol lacks this reading. The only reading available is the classical exclusive reading, namely that the glass is half full but not more than that.

To summarize, we pointed out several differences between be-sax ha-kolapprox. and true approximators, which cannot be explained if this particle has an approximative semantics. These differences seem to directly follow from our proposal above that be-sax ha-kol is a focus sensitive particle which conveys the same interpretative components as scalar exclusives, but it associates with covert material. Therefore, we conclude that be-sax ha-kol should not be considered ambiguous between the exclusive and approximative operations, and that its approximative reading is derivative.

5 THE STATUS OF THE INTERPRETIVE COMPONENTS WITH BE-SAX HA-KOL

5.1 THE DIFFERENCE IN THE STATUS OF THE PREJACENT AND THE EXCLUSION OF STRONGER ALTERNATIVES

In the previous sections we argued that be-sax ha-kol, on both its exclusive and approximative readings, conveys the same two components as scalar exclusive particles cross linguistically, namely the truth of the prejacent (the positive component) and the exclusion of stronger alternatives (the negative component).

However, a close look at these readings reveals that they differ in the status of these components. For be-sax ha-kolexcl this status is the same as the one reported for typical exclusive particles: the prejacent is presupposed/not-at-issue, and the exclusion of stronger alternatives is asserted/at-issue.20 In contrast, for be-sax ha-kolapprox the status seems to be the opposite, and in fact more similar to what we find with true approximators like more or less.21

This conclusion is supported by several diagnostics. For space reasons we present here two of them. The first is embeddability under antecedents of counterfactuals, which is supposed to target at-issue/asserted content. With be-sax ha-kolexcl what is being targeted by the counterfactual is the negative component that no stronger alternative is true: for example, from (46a) we infer that Danny has more than two dogs (and that this is why I am complaining). As seen in (46b) the same holds for English only/just.22 In contrast, for be-sax ha-kolapprox what is being targeted seems to be the positive component: from (47a) we do not infer that the room is maximally clean but that the room is not considered clean (and that if it was clean my aunt would agree to sleep in it). The same holds for the English translation with more or less seen in (47b):

    1. (46)
    1. a.
    1. im
    2. if
    1. le-Danny
    2. to-Danny
    1. hayu
    2. had
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolexcl
    2. ha-kol
    1. sheny
    2. two
    1. klavim
    2. dogs
    1. lo
    2. not
    1. hayiti
    2. would-I
    1. mitlonen.
    2. complain
    1. ‘If Danny had only /just two dogs I wouldn’t have complained.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. If Danny had only /just two dogs I wouldn’t have complained.
    1. (47)
    1. a.
    1. im
    2. if
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. haya
    2. was
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki
    2. clean
    1. doda
    2. aunt
    1. sheli
    2. mine
    1. hayta
    2. was
    1. maskima
    2. agreed
    1. lishon
    2. to-sleep
    1. bo.
    2. in-it
    1. ‘If the room was more or less clean my aunt would have agreed to sleep in it.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. If the room was more or less clean my aunt would have agreed to sleep in it.

Another diagnostic involves because-clauses. Coppock & Beaver (2014) show that such clauses target asserted/at-issue content, and that in the case of scalar exclusives like only or just they target the negative component, namely the exclusion of stronger alternatives, which they indeed assume to be asserted/at-issue. This seems to be the case for the negative component of be-sax-ha-kolexcl as well: from (48a) we infer that the reason that Danny is sad is because he didn’t publish more than two papers (and not because he published two papers). This is what makes the minimally contrasting version with happy a bit odd, given that people typically want to publish as many papers as they can. As seen in (48b) the same holds for English only, as expected.

In contrast, for be-sax ha-kolapprox the situation is reversed, and the because-clause seems to target the positive component: From (49a) we infer that Danny is happy because the room is clean (and not because it isn’t completely clean). This is what makes the minimally contrasting version with sad a bit odd, given that people typically prefer cleaner to less clean rooms. As seen in (47b) the same seems to hold for English more or less:

    1. (48)
    1. a.
    1. Danny
    2. Danny
    1. haya
    2. was
    1. acuv
    2. sad
    1. /
    2.  
    1. ?sameax
    2.   happy
    1. ki
    2. because
    1. hu
    2. he
    1. pirsem
    2. published
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolexcl
    2. ha-kol
    1. shney
    2. two
    1. ma’amarim
    2. papers
    1. ‘Danny was sad / ? happy because he published only two papers.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Danny was sad / ? happy because he published only two papers.
    1. (49)
    1. a.
    1. Danny
    2. Danny
    1. haya
    2. was
    1. sameax/?
    2. happy
    1. acuv
    2. sad
    1. ki
    2. because
    1. ha-xeder
    2. the-room
    1. haya
    2. was
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. naki.
    2. clean
    1. ‘Danny was happy / ?sad because the room was more or less clean.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Danny was happy / ?sad because the room was more or less clean.

In sum, while be-sax ha-kolexcl behaves like typical exclusive particles in terms of the status of its components, be-sax ha-kolapprox behaves like typical approximators.

One can attempt to take this observation as an indication that be-sax ha-kol is ambiguous between an exclusive and an approximative operator after all. However, given the differences we pointed out in the previous section between be-sax ha-kolapprox and clear approximators (in terms of compatibility with pointal adjectives, with relative multidimensional adjectives, with precise measure expressions and with adjectives which are themselves modified by degree modifiers), we believe that this direction is not the right one to take. Instead, in the next section we explore two ways to handle this data within the present proposal.

5.2 LEXICAL OR PRAGMATIC VARIABILITY IN THE STATUS OF THE COMPONENTS WITH BE-SAX HA-KOL

One way to handle the data above is to simply take be-sax ha-kol to have two entries as in (50a) and (50b), for the exclusive and the approximative readings, respectively.23

(50) a. ||be-sax ha-kolexcl / rak / only||g,c = λC. λp. λw: w∈ p. ∀q∈C ∧ q >sp → w∉q
  b. ||be-sax ha-kolapprox||g,c = λC. λp. λw: ∀q q∈C ∧ q >sp → w∉q. w∈ p.

The entry in (50a) is the typical entry for scalar exclusives, and (50b) differs minimally from it just in the reversed at issue vs. not at issue status of the positive and negative components. While on this proposal be-sax ha-kol is strictly speaking ambiguous, we think that taking this particle to have developed two closely related entries is still a more economical and plausible suggestion than taking it to be associated with two entirely distinct semantic operations (as an exclusive particle and as an approximator).

A relevant point to make here is that although on this hypothesis be-sax ha-kolapprox differs from be-sax ha-kolexcl and from typical exclusive operators (like English only and just, Hebrew rak, etc.), there is at least one other exclusive operator which seems similar to it in this respect. As already mentioned in the introduction, Bassi et al. (2019) argue that in order to account for a number of puzzles with scalar implicatures it is necessary to assume that unlike only, which presupposes its prejacent and asserts the exclusion of stronger (or non-weaker) alternatives, the status of these components with the covert exclusive operator involved with deriving scalar implicatures, which Bassi et al. (2019) call p-exh, is reversed. According to them, then, the prejacent of p-exh is asserted and the exclusion of non-weaker alternatives is presupposed (similarly to what has been sometimes claimed for clefts).24 This is in contrast to previous analyses of exh, the covert operator assumed to be involved with scalar implicatures, which took it to assert both components (see e.g. Chierchia et al. 2011 and much subsequent work). To the extent that this suggestion is on the right direction, the status of the positive and negative components can be seen as one of the parameters of variation along which exclusives differ. Thus, the fact that be-sax ha-kol can be associated with the two lexical entries in (50) is less surprising, and still allows us to consider it as part of the typology of exclusive operators. be-sax ha-kol may then be taken to be unspecified along this parameter.25

A second, more unified hypothesis we would like to examine is that be-sax ha-kol has only the entry in (50a), typical for exclusives. Unlike the previous proposal, where be-sax ha-kol differs from classical exclusive particles in two distinct properties (the ability to associate with covert focus and the status of its interpretative components), on this proposal it differs from them only in the former, and the different status of the interpretative components, observed in the approximative reading, will be pragmatically derived.

This kind of hypothesis is inspired by recent research on the flexibility of the asserted vs. presupposed status of interpretive content. While traditionally this status was assumed, implicitly or explicitly, to be totally fixed and lexically determined for each lexical item (cf. Heim 1992; van der Sandt 1992), there are now various theories which question one of these assumptions, or even both. We now briefly review some relevant claims made in such theories (although for space reasons we cannot do justice to their richness nor to the differences between them).

5.3 EXISTING CLAIMS REGARDING GRADIENCER AND VARIABILITY IN PROJECTIVITY AND (NOT)-AT-ISSUENESS

As is well known, presupposed/not at issue material is traditionally assumed to project over entailment cancelling operators like negation, questions, possibility modals, etc. even when embedded under such operators. However, various authors observed cases where such material does not project. In general, such authors observed that projectivity is gradient – some presuppositions are judged to be more projective than others. Moreover, projectivity of presupposed material has been argued to be affected by information structural factors, which in turn affect the degree to which such material ends up being at-issue, or up for debate/up for discussion.

To illustrate, consider the sentential complement of factive verbs like find out or discover, which is assumed to be presupposed, and does indeed usually project. As Simons et al. (2017) show, such commitments are weakened or disappear when relevant parts of such sentential complements are accented (which they take to indicate that they are focused), as in (51), or are answers to explicit or implicit questions in the context, (e.g. the question of where Sally is in (52)).

(51) Simons et al. (2017: 161)
  A: James just found out that Harry’s having a graduation party, and I just can’t understand why he’s so upset about it.
  B: He didn’t find out that HARRY’s having a graduation party, he found out that HARRIET is having a graduation party.
(52) [Interlocutors are aware that their friend Bill is trying to discover the whereabouts of his grown daughter Sally]
  If Bill discovers that Sally is in New York, he’ll be relieved.

Given this and similar observations, Tonhauser et al. (2018) hypothesize that a content C projects to the degree to which it is not-at-issue (what they call the gradient projection principle). This hypothesis was given experimental support in e.g. Amaral et al. (2011); Cummins et al. (2012); Smith and Hall (2011) and Xue and Onea (2011). For example, based on examining the projectivity of content in 19 constructions in English (e.g. non-restrictive relative clauses, possessive NPS, the prejacent of only and complements of stop, discovered and annoyed), as well as the at-issueness of such contents (using assent/dissent reactions), Tonhauser et al. (2018) found that the more not-at-issue a content is judged, the more projective it is.

A result which is of particular interest to us is that of all these 19 constructions, the prejacent of only was found to have the lowest degree of not-at-issueness, and also the lowest degree of projectivity. A similar result regarding only was also reported in Amaral et al. (2011).

As to the sensitivity of projective content to information structure factors, we follow Abrusán’s (2011) approach, who assumes that while not-at-issueness/presuppositional status can be originally conventionalized/lexicalized in the semantics of presupposition triggers,26 it can be overridden when we pay attention to the not-at-issue material, so it becomes at-issue (in which case it is not presupposed to begin with).27 Here is a relevant quotation:

Abrusán (2011: 501)

“Some aspects of the information conveyed are such that we pay attention to them by default, even in the absence of contextual information. On the other hand, contextual cues or conversational goals can divert attention to types of information that we would not pay attention to by default. Either way, whatever we do not pay attention to, be it by default, or in context, is what ends up presupposed.”

5.4 BACK TO BE-SAX HA-KOL

Given the claims in the above reviewed theories, let us now go back to the status of the components of be-sax ha-kol. Following Abrusán’s (2011) view, let us assume that the lexical entry for this particle starts out as (50a) above, where the prejacent is presupposed/not-at-issue and the exclusive component is asserted/at-issue.

With be-sax ha-kolexcl nothing interesting happens, so the components keep their status. But something does happen with be-sax ha-kolapprox. We hypothesize that this might have to do with the way the interpretation of the prejacent in this reading is calculated: as already pointed out in Section 3.4.2, when calculating the meaning of the prejacent and the exclusive component with be-sax ha-kolapprox, there is a possible clash between them. To illustrate again, the interpretation of the positive component of The room is be-sax ha-kol clean, namely the prejacent The room is pos clean, is that the degree to which the room is clean is at least as high as the standard, where crucially the context can, and often does, set this standard at the scale maxima. The negative component, on the other hand, requires that the room is not maximally clean. In a context where the standard in the prejacent is maximal, then, the two components clash.

Hence, as argued in Section 3.4.2 above, the presence of be-sax ha-kol forces us to go back to the prejacent and re-interpret it in such a way that the value of the standard variable is set to being non-maximal (no matter what the original value of this standard is set to by the context).

We thus hypothesize that although the prejacent of be-sax ha-kolapprox is originally backgrounded, this process of re-interpreting the prejacent may be the reason for why it cannot stay backgrounded anymore. In particular, this re-interpretation moves the prejacent to the foreground, so it becomes at-issue. In Abrusán’s (2011: 501) terms, this can be considered a case where a “conversational goal… can divert attention to types of information that we would not pay attention to by default”, and hence makes this type of information at-issue.

Given that there is independent experimental evidence that the not-at-issueness of the prejacent of exclusives seems rather weak to start with (cf. again Amaral 2011; Tonhauser et al. 2018), we end up with the prejacent of be-sax ha-kolapprox getting an at-issue status.

This is not the whole story, though, because remember that given the data in Section 5.1 the change in the status of the prejacent of be-sax ha-kolapprox – from being not-at-issue to being at-issue – is accompanied by a change in the status of the exclusive component – from being at-issue to being not-at-issue. Why don’t both interpretive components with be-sax ha-kolapprox end up being at-issue?

A suggestion made in Bassi et al. (2019) can perhaps help shed some light on the reason for this issue. As pointed out above, Bassi et al. argue that unlike what is traditionally assumed for covert exh, p-exh presupposes exclusion of non-weaker alternatives and asserts the prejacent, in a way which mirror-images overt only: “Only presupposes its prejacent and asserts exhaustivity; p-exh asserts the prejacent and presupposes exhaustivity; and exh presupposes nothing and asserts both the prejacent and the exhaustivity component” (Bassi et al. 2019: 23). Importantly, they further suggest that this proposal for p-exh fares better than the proposal for exh, since p-exh is compatible with the general requirement (which they take to be inspired by Schlenker 2007) that “a contribution must not lead to multiple novel inferences or answer different questions” (Bassi et al. 2019: 23).

Given such a general requirement, then, it can perhaps be also used to explain why, as far as the status of the components is concerned, be-sax ha-kolexcl is the mirror image of be-sax ha-kolapprox., similarly to the way only is the mirror image of p-exh in Bassi et al. (2019).

This suggestion needs to be further clarified and motivated, as well as empirically validated.28 At this point, however, we can at least point out one more construction where such a status mirror image is found, involving evaluative adjective sentences (EASs), described in Tonhauser et al. (2019). Tonhauser et al. discuss two meaning components conveyed by EASs, as in (53a), namely the truth of the prejacent (e.g. Feynman danced on the table) and the generalization (that for Feynman to dance on the table was stupid). The prejacent in such constructions is taken to be presupposed, while the generalization is asserted. This is evidenced in (53b), where the former, but not the latter projects.

(53) a. Feynman was stupid to dance on the table.
  b. Was Feynman stupid to dance on the table?

Tonhauser et al. attribute to Karttunen et al. (2014) the observation that there is variability in the status of the prejacent in this construction. This is seen in attested examples like (54), where the prejacent does not project, i.e. there is no commitment of the speaker that he went stumbling through the junkyard.

(54) Now I knew someone was in the junkyard and the cold wind was carrying the cries. I wasn’t stupid to go stumbling through the junkyard in the dark and get hurt.

What is relevant for us is that Tonhauser et al. observe that in such cases there is variability in the status of the generalization as well. Thus, unlike the prejacent in (54), which indeed does not project, the generalization does project (there is commitment that stumbling through the junkyard is stupid). Tonhauser et al. conclude that in this construction “when the prejacent projects, the generalization does not, and when the prejacent does not project, the generalization does” (Tonhauser et al. 2019: 3).

It seems, then, that the swapped status of the positive and negative components of be-sax ha-kolexcl and be-sax ha-kolapprox is part of a more general pattern found in other constructions, where a change in the not-at-issueness status of one interpretive component leads to a change of the at-issueness status of another component. Whether this pattern is indeed due to the general requirement suggested in Bassi et al. (2019), and whether it applies to all constructions are questions which require further research and are beyond the scope of this paper.

6 CONCLUSION

In this paper we proposed that two readings –exclusive and approximative – of the Hebrew particle be-sax ha-kol are more closely related than they seem to be at first glance, in that under both the particle is a scalar exclusive, having a positive and a negative contribution, namely the truth of the prejacent and the exclusion of stronger focus alternatives. The difference between the exclusive and approximative readings, we suggested, results from a minimal difference in the overtness vs. covertness of the focus associate of be-sax ha-kol, respectively.

Specifically, we proposed that whereas the exclusive reading of be-sax ha-kol is derived in the usual way from its association with overt material, the approximative reading results from its association with the covert degree modifier pos, modifying gradable expressions. In this case the stronger alternative which is rejected is one where the focused pos is substituted with a maximality degree modifier, resulting in “x is pos A, but not maximally A”.

In addition to accounting in a unified way for a wide range of distributional and interpretational observations regarding be-sax ha-kol, our analysis has implications regarding wider topics discussed in the semantics-pragmatics interface literature.

For example, we have shown that the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol is only licensed when the scale associated with the gradable expression is upper-bound, but the standard on this scale is not necessarily maximal. This, we argued, supports a view where scale structure and standards can be dissociated (pace Kennedy & McNally 2005a, and like Rotstein & Winter 2004; McNally 2011; Toledo & Sassoon 2011).

We pointed out that be-sax ha-kol seems similar to other only-like and even-like operators cross linguistically which were reported to associate with covert material. An important implication of the paper, then, is that the ability vs. inability of focus sensitive particles to associate with covert focused material should count as one of the parameters along which focus sensitive particles vary. More generally, the behavior of be-sax ha-kol supports analyses (cf. Chierchia 2013; Liu 2017) where apparent ambiguities of focus particles are attributed to the type of alternatives operated over, rather than to two distinct semantic operations.

Indeed, we argued against taking be-sax ha-kol to be ambiguous between an exclusive and an approximative semantics. We supported this decision by pointing out differences between the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol and that of true approximators (like more or less) which cannot be accounted for by an ambiguity-based analysis, but follow from our proposal. In this sense, our theory can also help sharpen the distinction between true and derivative approximators.

Another wider issue handled by our analysis concerns at- issueness and factors affecting it. We observed that the status of the interpretative components in the approximative reading of be-sax ha-kol – where the prejacent is at issue, and the exclusion of stronger alternatives is not-at-issue – is reversed relative to its exclusive reading and to typical exclusive particles like only. We examined two theoretical directions to capture this observation within our proposal. Given the first, this particle is associated with two closely related lexical entries, which differ minimally in terms of status, and given the second, there is a default lexical entry with one status, and the other status is derived pragmatically. Both directions are inspired by existing theories regarding at-issuenss. The first is inspired by a theory arguing for the mirror imaged status of components of only vs. p-exh, and the second by theories regarding the gradience and flexibility of status and its sensitivity to information structure. More research is clearly needed in order to decide between these two options. On both, though, it seems that the variability of the status of the components with be-sax ha-kol is not an isolated phenomenon, but part of a more general pattern. In this sense, understanding the behavior of be-sax ha-kol can contribute to a better understanding of (not)-at-issueness and the factors affecting it.

In future research we would also like to examine the connection between the internal composition of be-sax ha-kol (‘the sum the whole’) and its semantic effects. One such effect, pointed out in Orenstein & Greenberg (2013) for be-sax ha-kolapprox is an inference that the sentence is uttered based on some “summing-up” evidential basis. For example, uttering The room is be-sax ha-kolapprox clean seems to be based on checking the degree of cleanness in all parts of the room (e.g. under the sofa, at the windows, on the furniture, etc.), and summing the impression from all these parts. According to Orenstein & Greenebrg (2013), the fact that be-sax ha-kolapprox gives rise to this inference can explain felicity contrasts between (55) and (56): in (55) evidence that the door is closed cannot be based on examining parts of the door and summing up impressions about it. In contrast, one can sum up impressions about parts of the agreement document to see whether it is “closed”.

    1. (55)
    1. ??ha-delet
    2.     the.door
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. sgura.
    2. closed
    1.       ‘The door is more or less closed.’
    1. (56)
    1. ha-heskem
    2. the.agreement
    1. be-sax
    2. be-sax
    1. ha-kolapprox
    2. ha-kol
    1. sagur.
    2. closed
    1. ‘The agreement is be-sax ha-kol closed.’

Notice, though, that the full effects of be-sax ha-kolapprox cannot be reduced to this inference, as it cannot explain the negative component of this particle (“the maximal degree does not hold of the subject”), the felicity differences between pointal and non-pointal adjectives (cf. the discussion of The tank is be-sax ha-kolapprox. full/??empty in Section 3.4.2), and the similarity with the exclusive use of be-sax ha-kol. Capturing the intuition about this “summing-up” inference in a precise and compositional way, then, and clarifying its status is left for future research.

Notes

  1. There are two additional readings of be-sax ha-kol, discussed in Orenstein & Greenberg (2013); Orenstein (2016), namely the precise and the discursive readings. The former, translated as altogether, is obtained when be-sax ha-kol combines with numeral expressions:
      1. (i)
      1. tsipiti
      2. I-expected
      1. Se-yagiu
      2. that-will-arrive
      1. 10
      2. 10
      1. orxim.
      2. guests,
      1. basof
      2. eventually
      1. higiu
      2. arrived
      1. be-sax
      2. be-sax
      1. ha-kol 20.
      2. ha-kol 20
      1. ‘I expected 10 guests to arrive. Eventually there were altogether 20.’
    On this reading be-sax ha-kol indicates that the number of guests who arrived is precisely 20. The reading is different from the exclusive reading of be-sax ha-kol as well as from the one we get with the unmarked exclusive in Hebrew rak (‘only’). For example, in a context like (i), with a discourse salient alternative which is weaker than p, rak, as well as only are infelicitous (cf. Orenstein 2016; Greenberg 2019) but be-sax ha-kol is fine. The discursive reading, translated as after all, implies that the information in the prejacent is relevant to all things being considered in the context (in (ii) these can be Danny’s behavior, memory, health conditions, etc.):
      1. (ii)
      1. Dani
      2. Dany
      1. be-sax
      2. be-sax
      1. ha-kol
      2. ha-kol
      1. kvar
      2. already
      1. ben 80.
      2. 80 years old
      1. ‘After all, Danny is already 80 years old.’
    We leave future examination of these readings, and a potential unification with the approximative and exclusive readings of be-sax ha-kol to future research. [^]
  2. The data in this paper is based on introspection, as well as on attested examples collected in natural conversations and web materials. [^]
  3. We discuss a slight difference between rak and be-sax ha-kol on this reading in Section 3.3. Thanks to two Glossa reviewers for raising this issue. [^]
  4. The infelicity of this reaction is improved if legamrey (‘completely’) is accented. This can happen, for example, if the question of whether the room is completely clean is salient in the context. [^]
  5. Notice that the negative component here is scalar (requiring all alternatives stronger than p on the scale to be false). We follow here theories like Klinedinst (2005); Beaver & Clark (2008); Roberts (2011) and Coppock & Beaver (2014), who take this component to apply to all exclusive particles, both scalar (using Horn’s 1969 terminology) as in (ia), and crucially also those which look non-scalar, as in (ib).
    (i) a. John is only a clerk
      b. Only John arrived.
    These theories argue that both kinds of exclusives are inherently scalar, and that they differ in the type of scales involved. Those as in (i) involve evaluative/rank-order scales (e.g. rejecting alternatives like John is a manager) whereas apparently non-scalar cases, as in (ii), involve entailment-based scales (e.g. rejecting alternatives like John and Mary arrived). [^]
  6. Notice that (13) is not yet a lexical entry for scalar exclusives in general, or for any specific scalar exclusive particle, since it does not specify the asserted vs. presupposed status of the two interpretive components. We deal with this in Section 5 below. [^]
  7. Thanks to two Glossa reviewers for raising this point. [^]
  8. Thanks to two Glossa reviewers for raising these issues. Notice that similar observations on preference towards a particular type of scale are reported elsewhere (cf. Coppock & Beaver 2014 on only vs. just). [^]
  9. We assume that the same holds for gradable verbs like understand. However, given that most of the literature on gradability, scale structure, standards, etc. is on adjectives, and given the more complex event-based semantics of verbal expressions, we will from now on concentrate on the approximative reading with adjectives. [^]
  10. See Breheny et al. (2018) for a similar suggestion regarding scalar implicatures. [^]
  11. Kennedy & McNally suggest that this correlation between scale structure and standards is derived from the functional principle of “interpretative economy”. [^]
  12. Thanks to a Glossa reviewer for highlighting this point, as well as the prediction below. [^]
  13. Notice that, the English gloss with more or less is good with both types of adjectives. We come back to this point in Section 4, where we argue against assigning an approximative semantics to be-sax ha-kolapprox.. [^]
  14. We come back to this point in Section 5, where we discuss a potential consequence of such re-interpretations of the standard for the at-issueness status of positive and negative components of be-sax ha-kol. [^]
  15. As a Glossa reviewer points out, given our proposal, p (e.g. The room is pos clean) is entailed by stronger alternative (e.g. The room is completely clean), but it is not clear that the stronger alternatives and p entail weaker alternatives (e.g. The room is a little bit clean). Is the scale for be-sax ha-kolapprox, then, an entailment-based or an evaluative scale? Making the right choice here depends on wider issues discussed in the literature, e.g. whether the weaker alternatives are given an exhaustified/exactly reading, and whether the weaker alternatives are members of C, to start with (cf. Guerzoni 2003; Crnic 2012 and Greenberg 2019, suggesting that p is the weakest alternative in C for only). We leave, then, further examination of the type of scale here to future research. [^]
  16. Roberts (2011) and Alxatib (2013) argue that the requirement for having at least one alternative stronger than p in C with exclusive particles should not be hardwired into the semantics of such exclusives (cf. (13) above), since it is derived from a general constraint on non-vacuous operation. We follow these authors on this assumption. Another reason for not hardwiring such a requirement into C is that the definition of C (as defined in Rooth 1992) is supposed to be uniform for all focus-based phenomena. Thanks to a Glossa reviewer for raising this issue. [^]
  17. Notice that unlike the previous cases where a felicitous be-sax ha-kolapprox is easily translated with more or less, in (39)–(40) modifying e.g. nice, idiotic or talented with more or less is degraded relative to modification by be-sax ha-kol. We discuss this point in the next section, where we argue against giving an approximative semantics to be-sax ha-kol. [^]
  18. Notice that be-sax ha-kolapprox. is felicitous with both good and bad. We take this to indicate that it is not sensitive to the distinction between positive and negative adjectives. Thanks to a reviewer for raising this point. [^]
  19. http://fullgaz.co.il/forums/showthread.php/9832-%D7%A4%D7%A8%D7%92%D7%95%D7%9F-%D7%9C%D7%91%D7%A2%D7%9C-%D7%9E%D7%A7%D7%A6%D7%95%D7%A2. [^]
  20. While the asserted vs. presupposed is not identical to the at-issue/not-at-issue distinction (the former is a special case of the latter, see e.g. Tonhauser et al. 2013), we will not try to distinguish between these terms here and will often use the terms interchangeably. [^]
  21. Thanks to a Glossa reviewer for raising this issue. [^]
  22. Notice that in some such cases we also get the inference that the positive inference, i.e. the prejacent is false. E.g. from (i) we infer that John is not a clerk:
    (i) If John was just a clerk Mary wouldn’t agree to marry him
    See also Coppock & Beaver (2014) and Orenstein (2016), who show that this happens with rank order readings when the alternatives are mutually incompatible with each other. [^]
  23. Notice that in these entries we follow the traditional assumption which takes exclusive particles to be propositional operators (even if their surface position is not sentence initial). Thus, we do not deal with the type (nor with the QUD parameters) introduced in Coppock & Beaver (2014), which are not crucial for the main claim made in this paper. [^]
  24. Cf. Erlewine (to appear) who analyzes Mandarin shi as a not-at-issue exhaustive operator. Erlewine shows that sentences with shi are translatable using English clefts. [^]
  25. Notice that, similarly to what is usually argued to be the default case for scalar implicatures (as in (i)), the exclusive (negative) component of be-sax ha-kolapprox., as in (ii), seems to be cancelled in antecedents of conditionals. We understand that if the room was at least pos clean (and possibly completely clean), my aunt would agree to sleep in it:
      1. (i)
      1. If some students fail the exam, then we should prepare an easier one.
      1. (ii)
      1. im
      2. if
      1. ha-xeder
      2. the-room
      1. be-sax
      2. be-sax
      1. ha-kolapprox
      2. ha-kol
      1. naki
      2. clean
      1. doda
      2. aunt
      1. sheli
      2. mine
      1. taskim
      2. will-agree
      1. lishon bo.
      2. to-sleep in-it
      1. ‘If the room is more or less clean my aunt agrees to sleep in it.’
    One could try to argue that this similarity indicates that the exclusive inference of be-sax ha-kolapprox is also an implicature. However, unlike what happens with scalar implicatures, trying to cancel this inference in matrix sentences, as in (iii), leads to oddness, and to the feeling of self-correction (e.g. the conclusion that the speaker checked again the room and found out that, unlike what she originally thought, the room has no dirt at all):
      1. (iii)
      1. ha-xeder
      2. the-room
      1. be-sax
      2. be-sax
      1. ha-kol
      2. ha-kolapprox
      1. naki.
      2. clean
      1. ??lemaase
      2.     actually
      1. hu
      2. it
      1. legamrey
      2. completely
      1. naki.
      2. clean
      1. ‘The room is more or less clean. ??In fact it is completely clean.’
    Given the independently made claim that scalar implicatures are the result of the operation of p-exh (as in Bassi et al. 2019), we hypothesize, then, that the similarity between (i) with this p-exh and (ii) with be-sax ha-kolapprox, is not due to the implicated nature of the exclusive inference, but due to the fact that with both operators this inference is presupposed/not at issue, and hence is not targeted by the conditional to start with. We leave a more thorough examination of this issue to future research. [^]
  26. Cf. Simons et al. (2017) and Tonhauser (2019). [^]
  27. Another – alternative-based – family of theories dealing with variability in projective content is Abusch (2010) and Romoli (2015). For space reasons we do not review this approach here. [^]
  28. Abrusán (2011), for example, suggests that when not-at-issue content turns to at-issue it is added to the main point of the sentence as “secondary main point”. See also Tonhauser et al. (2019) for a discussion. [^]

Acknowledgements

For constructive discussions and helpful comments on this and previous versions of the paper we would like to thank Elitzur Bar-Asher-Siegal, Gennaro Chierchia, Luka Crnič, Micky Daniels, Edit Doron, Mitcho Erlewine, Danny Fox, Andreas Heida, Aaron Hirsch, Nirit Kadmon, Lena Miashkur, Louise McNally, Barbara Partee, Moria Ronen, Susan Rothstein, Aynat Rubinstein, Galit Sassoon, Aldo Sevi, Todd Snider, Judith Tonhauser and Malte Zimmermann. Many thanks to three anonymous Glossa reviewers for their valuable comments and questions and to Min-Joo Kim, the associate editor, for the helpful editorial guidance. All remaining errors are ours.

FUNDING INFORMATION

This research was supported by ISF grant 1655/16 to Yael Greenberg.

COMPETING INTERESTS

The authors have no competing interests to declare.

References

Abusch, Dorit. 2010. Presupposition triggering from alternatives. Journal of Semantics 27. 37–80. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffp009

Abrusán, Márta. 2011. Predicting the presuppositions of soft triggers. Linguistics & Philosophy 34(6). 491–535. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-012-9108-y

Amaral, Patrícia, Chris Cummins & Napoleon Katsos. 2011. Experimental evidence on the distinction between foregrounded and backgrounded meaning. In Gregory Kierstead (ed.), Proceedings of the 2011 ESSLLI: Workshop on projective content, 1–7. Columbus: The Ohio State University.

Alxatib, Sam. 2013. ‘Only’ and association with negative antonyms. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation.

Amaral, Patricial & Fabio Del Prete. 2010. Approximating the limit: The interaction between quasi ‘almost’ and some temporal connectives in Italian. Linguistics and Philosophy 33. 51–115. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-011-9088-3

Bassi, Itai, Guillermo Del Pinal, & Uli Sauerland. 2019. Presuppositional exhaustification. Ms. https://ling.auf.net/lingbuzz/004821.

Beaver, David & Brady Clark. 2008. Sense and sensitivity: How focus determines meaning (Explorations in Semantics). Oxford, UK: Blackwell. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1002/9781444304176

Beaver, David, Brady Clark, Edward Flemming, T. Florian Jäger & Maria Wolters. 2007. When semantics meets phonetics: Acoustical studies of second occurrence focus. Language 83(2). 245–276. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2007.0053

Beltrama, Andera & M. Ryan Bochnak. 2015. Intensification without degrees crosslinguistically. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 33(3). 843–879. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-015-9294-8

Breheny, Richard, Nathan Klinedinst, Jacopo Romoli & Yasutada Sudo. 2018. The symmetry problem: Current theories and prospects. Natural Language Semantics 26. 86–110. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-017-9141-z

Chierchia, Gennaro. 2013. Logic in grammar: Polarity, free choice, and intervention. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199697977.001.0001

Chierchia, Gennaro, Danny Fox & Benjamin Spector. 2011. The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In Paul Portner, Claudia Maienborn & Klaus von Heusinger (eds.), Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning, 2297–2331. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

Coppock, Elizabeth & David Beaver. 2014. Principles of the exclusive muddle. Journal of Semantics 31. 371–432. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/fft007

Crnič, Luka. 2011. Getting even. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation.

Cummins, Chris, Patricia Amaral, & Napoleon Katsos. 2012. Experimental investigations of the typology of presupposition triggers. Humana Mante Journal of Philosophical Studies 23, 1–15.

Egg, Markus & Malte Zimmermann. 2011. Stressed out! Accented discourse particles – the case of ‘doch’. In Ana Aguilar Guevara, Anna Chernilovskaya & Rick Nouwen (eds.), Proceedings of SuB 16 MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, 225–238.

Erlewine, Michael Yoshitaka. To appear. Mandarin exhaustive focus shì and the syntax of discourse congruence. In Remus Gergel, Augustin Speyer & Ingo Reich (eds.), Particles in German, English, and beyond. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

Féry, Caroline & Shinichiro Ishihara. 2009. The Phonology of second occurrence focus. Journal of Linguistics 459(2). 285–313. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226709005702

Greenberg, Yael. 2019. Even and only: Arguing for parallels in scalarity and in constructing alternatives. In Maggie Baird & Jonathan Pesetsky (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 49, 61–70. Ithaca: Cornell University.

Greenberg, Yael. 2020. An overt even operator over covert-based focus alternatives: The case of Hebrew BIXLAL. Journal of Semantics 37(1). 1–42. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffz010

Greenberg, Yael & Dina Orenstein. 2016. Typologies for even-like and only-like particles: Evidence from Modern Hebrew. A paper presented at ESSLLI 28, Bolzano, 2016.

Guerzoni, Elena. 2003. Why even ask? on the pragmatics of questions and the semantics of answers. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation.

Heim, Irene. 1992. Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics 9(3). 183–221. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/9.3.183

Horn, Laurence. 1969. A presuppositional analysis of only and even. In Papers from the fifth regional meeting, Chicago Linguistic Society [= CLS]5, 97–108. Chicago: University of Chicago.

Kadmon, Nirit. 2001. Formal pragmatics: Semantics, pragmatics, presupposition and focus. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers.

Kadmon, Nirit & Aldo Sevi. 2011. Without ‘Focus’. In Barbara Partee, Michael Glanzberg & Jurgis Skilters (Eds.), Formal semantics and pragmatics. Discourse, context and models. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, Vol. 6. Manhattan, KS: New Prairie Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v6i0.1585

Karttunen, Lauri, Stanley Peters, Annie Zaenen & Cleo Condoravdi. 2014. The chameleon-like nature of evaluative adjectives. In Christopher Piñón (ed.), Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 10. 233–250.

Kennedy, Christopher & Louise McNally. 2005a. Scale structure, degree modification, and the semantics of gradable predicates. Language 81. 345–381. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2005.0071

Kennedy, Christopher & Louise McNally. 2005b. The syntax and semantics of multiple degree modification in English. In Stefan Müller (ed.), Proceedings of the 12th International Conference on Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar, 178–191. Lisbon: University of Lisbon.

Klein, Ewan. 1980. A semantics for positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy 4. 1–45. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/BF00351812

Lasersohn, Peter. 1999. Pragmatic Halos. Language 75. 522–551. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.2307/417059

Liu, Mingming. 2017. Varieties of alternatives: Mandarin focus particles. Linguistics and Philosophy 40. 61–95. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-016-9199-y

McNabb, Yaron. 2012. Hebrew mamaš ‘really’ vs. real cases of degree modification. A paper presented at LSA Annual Meeting. Portland, OR.

McNally, Louise. 2011. The relative role of property type and scale structure in explaining the behavior of gradable adjectives. In Rick Nouwen, Robert van Rooij, Uli Sauerland & Hans-Christian Schmitz (eds.), Vagueness in communication, 151–168. Berlin: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-18446-8_9

Miashkur, Lena. 2017. A parametric comparison of Russian scalar particles daže and voobšce. Ramat-Gan, Israel: Bar Ilan University thesis.

Miashkur, Lena. 2018. A parametric comparison of two scalar particles in Russian. In Noa Brandel (ed.), Proceedings of IATL33 MIT working papers in Linguistics 89. 121–148.

Morzycki, Marcin. 2011. Metalinguistic comparison in an alternative semantics for imprecision. Natural Language Semantics 19(1). 39–86. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11050-010-9063-5

Orenstein, Dina. 2015. A family of exclusives in Hebrew. In Miriam Kaeshammer & Philip Schulz (eds.), Proceedings of the 27th European Summer School in Logic, Language, and Information Student Session, 96–106.

Orenstein, Dina. 2016. The semantics, pragmatics and focus sensitivity of exclusive particles in Modern Hebrew. Ramat-Gan, Israel: Bar Ilan University dissertation.

Orenstein, Dina & Yael Greenberg. 2010. The Semantics and Focus Sensitivity of the Hebrew (unstressed) Stam. In Yehuda Falk (ed.), Proceedings of IATL 26. Bar Ilan University.

Orenstein, Dina & Yael Greenberg. 2013. A flexible exclusive particle: The case of the Hebrew be-sax ha-kol (‘all in all’). In Emmanuel Chemla, Vincent Homer & Grégoire Winterstein (eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 17, 381–397. Paris: ENS

Partee, Barbara. 1999. Focus, quantification, and semantics-pragmatics issues. In Peter Bosch & Rob van der Sandt (eds.), Focus: Linguistic, cognitive, and computational perspectives, 213–231. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Roberts, Craige. 2011. only: A case study in projective meaning. In Barbara Partee, Michael Glanzberg & Jurgis Skilters (Eds.), Formal semantics and pragmatics. Discourse, context and models. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, Vol. 6. Manhattan, KS: New Prairie Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v6i0.1581

Romoli, Jacopo. 2015. The presuppositions of soft triggers are obligatory scalar implicatures. Journal of Semantics 32. 173–291. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/fft017

Rooth, Mats. 1985. Association with focus. Massachusetts, Amherst: University of Massachusetts dissertation.

Rooth, Mats. 1992. A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics 1. 75–116. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/BF02342617

Rotstein, Carmen & Yoad Winter. 2004. Total adjectives vs. partial adjectives: Scale structure and higher-order modifiers. Natural Language Semantics 12. 259–288. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/B:NALS.0000034517.56898.9a

Sassoon, Galit. 2013. A typology of multidimensional adjectives. Journal of Semantics 30. 335–380. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffs012

Sassoon, Galit. 2018. A degree-approach account of multidimensional gradability. Ms. Bar Ilan University.

Sauerland, Uli & Penka Stateva. 2007. Scalar vs. epistemic vagueness: Evidence from approximators. In Tova Friedman & Masayuki Gibson (eds.), Proceedings of SALT 17, 228–245. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v17i0.3091

Simons, Mandy, David Beaver, Craige Roberts & Judith Tonhauser. 2017. The best question: Explaining the projection behavior of factive verbs. Discourse Processes 54(3). 187–206. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1080/0163853X.2016.1150660

Schlenker, Philippe. 2007. Transparency: An incremental theory of presupposition projection. In Uli Sauerland & Penka Stateva (eds.), Presupposition and Implicature in Compositional Semantics, 214–242. London: Palgrave Macmillan. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1057/9780230210752_8

Smith, E. Allyn & Kathleen Currie Hall. 2011. Projection diversity: Experimental evidence. In Gregory Kierstead (ed.), Proceedings of the 2011 ESSLLI Workshop on Projective Content, 156–170. The Ohio State University.

Toledo, Assaf & Galit Sassoon. 2011. Absolute vs. relative adjectives – variance within vs. between individuals. In Neil Ashton, Anca Chereches & David Lutz (eds.), Proceedings of SALT 21. 135–154. Linguistic Society of America. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/salt.v21i0.2587

Tonhauser, Judith, David Beaver, Craige Roberts & Mandy Simons. 2013. Toward a taxonomy of projective content. Language 89. 66–109. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2013.0001

Tonhauser, Judith, David Beaver & Judith Degen. 2018. How projective is projective content? gradience in projectivity and at-issueness. Journal of Semantics 35. 495–542. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/ffy007

Umbach, Carla. 2009. Another additive particle under stress: German additive noch. In Proceedings of LOLA 10, 149–156.

van der Sandt, Rob. 1992. Presupposition projection as anaphora resolution. Journal of Semantics 9. 333–377. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/9.4.333

von Stechow, Arnim. 1984. Comparing semantic theories of comparison. Journal of Semantics 3. 1–77. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/3.1-2.1

Wagner, Michael. 2012. Focus and givenness: a unified approach. In Ivona Kučerová & Ad Neeleman (eds.), Contrasts and positions in information structure, 102–147. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511740084.007

Wiegand, Mia. 2017. Exclusive morphosemantics: Just and covert quantification. A paper presented at 35th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, University of Calgary.

Xue, Jingyang & Edgar Onea. 2011. Correlation between projective meaning and at-issueness: An empirical study. In Gregory Kierstead (ed.), Proceedings of the 2011 ESSLLI: Workshop on projective content, 171–184. Columbus: The Ohio State University.