1 Introduction
There is a strong cross-linguistic tendency for head-initial phrases not to be dominated by head-final phrases, attributed to the so-called Final-Over-Final Condition (FOFC) (see among others Holmberg 2000; Biberauer & Sheehan 2012; Ledgeway 2012; Sheehan 2013a; b; 2017; Biberauer et al. 2014a; Erlewine 2017; Hein & Murphy 2020; Clem 2021, and the chapters in Sheehan et al. 2017). By studying Basque clausal complementation, this paper explores the question of whether the FOFC should be modeled in narrow syntax (as in e.g. Biberauer et al. 2014a) or in the PF component (as in e.g. Sheehan 2013a; b).
Basque clausal complementation creates a syntactic configuration that does not comply with the FOFC. This paper shows how the varying word orders found in complementation ‘repair’ this violation, via (i) extraposition or pied-piping of the entire clause, or (ii) deletion of the higher copy of the offending heads (and lower copy spell out). The inclusion of phenomena relevant to PF in these strategies –such as phonological content or copy deletion– supports the PF approach to the FOFC. More broadly, the results converge with a growing body of research that suggests that PF factors influence more word order-related phenomena than was standardly thought (see among others Zec & Inkelas 1990; Bošković 2001; 2020; Nunes 2004; Richards 2010; Sabbagh 2014; Kandybowicz & Torrence 2015; Mathieu 2016; Anttila 2016; Bennet et al. 2016; Holmberg et al. 2020). The paper also provides an explanation of word order variation in contexts of embedding in Basque, whereby the clause-internal ordering possibilities depend on the position of the embedded clause within the matrix clause (extraposed, pied-piped, or in situ).
The structure of the paper is the following. Section 2 briefly introduces the FOFC, as well as some ‘compliance strategies’ that have been observed across languages, and explores the type of predictions that narrow syntactic vs. PF-interface approaches make with respect to the possibility for PF-phenomena to affect the evaluation of the FOFC. Section (8) presents some background on the syntax of Basque clausal embedding and spells out the predictions made by the two types of approaches. Section 4 shows that once we factor in clausal extraposition and clausal pied-piping as compliance strategies, the data corresponds exactly to what we would expect under an PF-interface approach. Sections 5 and 6 then discuss word order alternations that are also observed in embedded clauses, and show that they involve yet another compliance strategy, whereby it is the lower, FOFC-complying members of a head-movement chain that get spelled-out, instead of the higher, FOFC-violating ones. Section 7 concludes the paper.
2 Final-over-Final Condition
The observation initially made by Holmberg (2000) is that there is a tendency for head-initial phrases not to be dominated by head-final phrases.1 The example in (1) shows that in Finnish, out of the four conceivable orderings between the auxiliary, the verb and the object, only one is unattested; namely, the one where the auxiliary is on the right and dominates a phrase whose head, V, is on the left of its own complement.
- (1)
- Finnish (Holmberg 2017a: 1)
- a.
- Kyllä
- indeed
- se
- he
- on
- has
- ostanut
- bought
- auton. [Aux [V O]]
- car
- b.
- Kyllä
- indeed
- se
- he
- on
- has
- auton
- car
- ostanut. [Aux [O V]]
- bought
- c.
- Kyllä
- indeed
- se
- he
- auton
- car
- ostanut
- bought
- on. [[O V] Aux]
- has
- d.
- *Kyllä
- indeed
- se
- he
- ostanut
- bought
- auton
- car
- on. [[V O] Aux]
- has
This pattern has been shown to be cross-linguistically robust, and to relate to the generative capacity of language, resulting from the FOFC (cf. Holmberg 2000; Biberauer et al. 2009a; b; Biberauer & Sheehan 2012; Sheehan 2013a; 2017; Sheehan et al. 2017; Biberauer et al. 2014a; b; Etxepare & Haddican 2017; Erlewine 2017; Hein & Murphy 2020; Clem 2021). There are different formulations of this condition; (2) is an adaptation of the generalization given in Holmberg (2000: 124), which I will take as a general reference:2
- (2)
- The Final-over-Final Condition (FOFC):
- If a phrase αP is head-initial, then the phrase βP immediately dominating it is head-initial. If αP is head-final, βP can be head-final or head-initial.
The disharmonic configuration in (3d) below –where the head-final αP dominates the head-initial βP– is the configuration that is banned by the FOFC. It corresponds to the ungrammatical Finnish example in (1d).
- (3)
The remainder of this section presents two aspects of the research on the FOFC that will be central in this paper. Section 2.1 discusses structures that obviate ungrammaticality in what would otherwise be FOFC-violating configurations. Then, Section 2.2 introduces syntactic vs. PF-interface approaches to the FOFC.
2.1 Domains and compliance strategies
The FOFC imposes strict limits on linguistic variability. However, there are two ways in which a certain malleability is made possible: (i) the FOFC appears to apply not over entire clauses, but over impenetrable domains, and (ii) languages appeal to a variety of ‘compliance strategies’ that escape non-compliant configurations. This section briefly introduces these two notions.
The FOFC applies within specific domains of the clause, and not across them. The examples in (4), from Biberauer et al. (2014a), show how, in OV languages such as German, a head-initial DP or PP may be immediately dominated by a head-final VP. That is, the configuration created by a VP dominating a PP/DP is not subject to FOFC-compliance: they constitute differentiated domains for the evaluation of the FOFC.
- (4)
- German (Biberauer et al. (2014a: 197))
- a.
- Johann
- Johann
- hat
- has
- [VP [DP
- einen
- a
- Mann]
- man
- gesehen].
- seen
- Johann has seen a man.
- b.
- Johann
- Johann
- ist [VP [PP
- is
- nach
- to
- Berlin]
- Berlin
- gefahren].
- gone
- Johann has gone to Berlin.
In contrast, the similar configuration where the VP dominates a (finite) complement clause must comply with the FOFC (cf. Biberauer & Sheehan 2012). In German, the expected –but FOFC-violating– [[C TP] V] order is avoided, and embedded clauses surface to the right of V, giving [V [C TP]] order.3 This is illustrated in (5):
- (5)
- German (Biberauer et al. (2014a: 198))
- a.
- *…
- dass
- that
- Johann
- Johann
- niemals
- never
- [CP
- dass
- that
- er
- he
- eigentlich
- actually
- ein
- an
- angenommenes
- adopted
- Kind
- child
- sei]
- be.subj
- besprochen
- discussed
- hat.
- has
- b.
- …
- dass
- that
- Johann
- Johann
- niemals
- never
- besprochen
- discussed
- hat
- has
- [CP
- dass
- that
- er
- he
- eigentlich
- actually
- ein
- an
- angenommenes
- adopted
- Kind
- child
- sei].
- be.sbvj
- … that Johann has never discussed the fact that he is actually an adopted child.
Biberauer & Sheehan (2012) show that CP-extraposition is a general feature of OV languages with clause-initial complementizers (citing Hawkins 1994; 2004; Cinque 2009; Dryer 2009). They argue that it is a FOFC-compliance strategy, which allows the CP to ‘escape’ an otherwise FOFC-violating configuration (see also Biberauer et al. 2009a; 2014a; 2017; Sheehan 2013a).4
Biberauer et al. (2009a; 2014a) also discuss how in OV languages with initial complementizers which –unlike German– lack CP-extraposition, complement clauses remain in the preverbal position but are systematically nominalized (a generalization attributed to Koptjevskaja-Tamm 1988; 1993). As they point out, this suggests an explanation in terms of domains of application for the FOFC, as seen above. As a matter of fact, nominalized clauses are DPs which constitute a domain distinct from the VP that dominates them, which ensures FOFC-compliance.
Another relevant configuration that avoids FOFC-violations is the one resulting from A’-movement. Biberauer (2017: 245) points out the following contrast in Colloquial German, between what would be the ‘neutral’ FOFC-violating V-O-Aux order in (6a) and the same order derived via VP-fronting (7) (from Haider 2012: 80):5
- (6)
- a.
- *…
- dass
- that
- er
- he
- nicht
- not
- mehr
- more
- [VP
- gesprochen
- spoken
- mit
- with
- ihr]
- her
- hat.
- has
- b.
- …
- dass
- that
- er
- he
- nicht
- no
- mehr
- more
- [VP
- gesprochen
- spoken
- hat
- has
- mit
- with
- ihr].
- her
- … that he didn’t talk to her anymore.
- (7)
- [CP [VP
- Gesprochen
- spoken
- mit
- with
- ihr]
- her
- hat-C
- has
- [TP
- er
- he
- nicht
- not
- mehr
- more
- tVP]].
- As for speaking with her, he no longer did that.
The observation is thus that, regardless of the resulting order, A’-movement results in complying configurations.
Summarizing, the strong effects of the FOFC are somehow hidden by (i) the fact that it applies within particular domains of the clause and not across the board, and (ii) by ‘compliance strategies’ such as extraposition and A’-movement, i.e., configurations that provide a kind of repair or escape with respect to the FOFC-violating ones. Different accounts have been developed for these facts in the literature. They are closely dependent on the general analysis that is given for the FOFC, and not directly relevant for us here. For our purpose, it is sufficient to consider them as valid descriptive generalizations, for the discussion in Section 4 will show that they are at play in Basque clausal complementation, too.
2.2 FOFC in the architecture of the grammar: Predictions
The FOFC has been modeled in different ways (see Holmberg (2017b) on different approaches in the light of the issue of word order). One prominent account is the one put forth by Biberauer et al. (2014a), which pursues a core syntactic approach, where FOFC-violating structures simply cannot be built in the syntax. In turn, Sheehan (2013a; b) develops a PF-interface approach, where FOFC-compliance rather results from the way in which the linearization algorithm works (see also Erlewine 2017; Richards 2016; Sheehan 2017; Etxepare & Haddican 2017; Holmberg 2017c; b).6
The syntactic and PF-interface approaches make different predictions in certain regards, and in particular with respect to the possibility for the PF component to play a role in the computation of the FOFC. If narrow syntax just cannot build non-FOFC-complying structures as in Biberauer et al.’s (2014a) analysis –or more generally, if FOFC-compliance is ensured in the syntax–, it implies that only FOFC-complying structures will be sent to PF. Therefore, we would expect phonological or postsyntactic phenomena never to affect FOFC-compliance.
In turn, PF-based approaches open the possibility for such effects. In Sheehan’s (2013a, 2013b) analysis, anything that happens at PF before linearization can have an effect on its output. For instance, extraposition is characterized as the product of linearization: in certain structures, constituents (or their sub-constituents) that have undergone movement cannot be linearized in their higher position, and it is the lower copy of the movement chain which will be pronounced, giving the illusion of rightward movement (see in particular Sheehan 2013a; 2017). Take for instance Sheehan’s (2017) account of the Head Final Filter (Williams 1982), whereby the complements of prenominal adjectives cannot surface in the position between the adjective and the modified noun:
- (8)
- a.
- b.
- c.
- a
- *a
- a
- difficult
- difficult
- difficult
- book
- [for anyone to read] book
- book [for anyone to read]
Sheehan argues that ‘repair’ effects such as CP-extraposition in (8c) result in fact from deleting the higher copy of the complement involved in the movement chain of the AdjP (cf. S. Kayne 1994), and pronouncing the lower one, as represented in (9):
- (9)
- [NP [AdjP difficult [CP for anyone to read]] book [AdjP difficult [CP for anyone to read]]]
Etxepare & Haddican (2017) give a similar account of certain contrasts in Basque modal constructions, where A’-movement, followed by the deletion of the lower, FOFC-violating copy, may bleed the FOFC.
Next section shows how the grammar of Basque clausal embedding provides an rich ground for testing these predictions.
3 Overt vs. null heads in disharmonic configurations in Basque
In Basque clausal complementation, a head-final VP dominates a clause with head-initial left peripheral phrases, creating a potentially FOFC-violating configuration. But the heads in head-initial phrases of the embedded clause will have overt exponents only under certain circumstances. Such alternations between overt vs. null heads thus provide an ideal testing ground for evaluating the syntactic vs. PF approaches to FOFC, since only under the second could there be differences depending on whether or not a FOFC-violating head is overt or not.
This section introduces the different aspects of the above idea, first by giving an overview of the (disharmonic) structure of the Basque clause (Section 3.1), and then by going through the relevant predictions made by the two approaches to the FOFC (Section 3.2).
3.1 Basque clause structure
The classical analysis of Basque clause structure is one which is disharmonic but FOFC-compliant (cf. also Elordieta 2013; Biberauer et al. 2014a). The Basque clause has indeed head-final orders in FinP and below (TP, vP, VP, etc.), and head-initial orders above FinP (ΣP, FocP, TopP, etc.). (10) shows the relevant clause-structure that I will be assuming in this paper (built on work by, among others, Goenaga 1984; Laka 1990; Ortiz de Urbina 1989b; 1999; Artiagoitia 1995; Elordieta 2001; Haddican 2004; Irurtzun 2007). This section explains its most relevant aspects.7,8
- (10)
3.1.1 The head-final domain: FinP and below
Basque is an S-O-V-Aux language, a word order standardly accounted for in terms of the final-headed nature of VP, TP, etc. (cf. among others Goenaga 1984; Ortiz de Urbina 1989b; 1999; Artiagoitia 2002; 2008; Elordieta 2001; 2013). In clausal complements of verbs, -en is used in indirect interrogatives and -ela in declaratives, as illustrated in (11a) and (11b), respectively:9
- (11)
- a.
- Galdetu
- ask
- dute
- aux
- [ea
- Q
- Mikeli
- Mikel.to
- nork
- who
- emango
- give.prosp
- dio-n
- aux-comp
- bihar
- tomorrow
- liburua
- book
- tV+T+Fin].
- They asked who will give the book to Mikel tomorrow.
- b.
- Esan
- say
- dute
- aux
- [Mikeli
- Mikel.to
- Anak
- Ana
- emango
- give.prosp
- dio-la
- aux-comp
- bihar
- tomorrow
- liburua
- book
- tV+T+Fin].
- They said that Ana will give the book to Mikel tomorrow.
In line with Ortiz de Urbina (1999) and Artiagoitia & Elordieta (2016), I assume that complementizers -en and -ela –which attach to the right of embedded finite verbs or auxiliaries– are hosted on Fin. Ortiz de Urbina (1999) provides evidence for the hypothesis that -en encodes Finiteness rather than Force. First, he points out that the complementizer surfaces on finite verbs only, which shows that it is connected with the finite vs. non-finite nature of the embedded inflection. Second, the hypothesis also explains why the complementizer surfaces on Foc together with the finite verb in wh-interrogatives, i.e., the latter undergoes head-to-head movement through Fin when targetting the higher Foc (V-to-T-to-Fin-to-Foc which results in WH-V-XP orders as in (11a); see Section 3.1.2). And third, it also explains why -en can co-occur with illocutionary force markers which encode Force, like the interrogative particle ea in example (11a) (see Ortiz de Urbina 1999; Monforte 2020 and Irurtzun 2022).
Ortiz de Urbina’s (1999) analysis can easily be extended to complementizer -ela.10 (i) Its use is also limited to finite clauses, (ii) it also accompanies verb-movement in V2-type constructions, as can be seen in (11b), and (iii) it is also compatible with heads encoding Force, such as ezen, as illustrated in (12) (see also Ortiz de Urbina 1999 on nola):
- (12)
- Jonek
- Jon
- esan
- say
- du
- aux
- [ezen
- Q
- liburua
- book
- ekarri
- bring
- du-ela].
- aux-comp
- Jon said that he brought the book.
An additional piece of evidence comes from Vergara’s (2018) work on Basque-Spanish code-switching, which shows that an overt Spanish complementizer que (encoding Force) is required in addition to -ela when a Basque finite declarative clause is embedded under a Spanish matrix clause.11 This is illustrated in (13) (from Vergara 2018), with Spanish in italics and Basque in bold:
- (13)
- Pedro
- Pedro
- cree
- think
- que
- comp
- Jon
- Jon
- etorri
- come
- d-ela.
- aux-C
- Pedro thinks that Jon came.
Summarizing this section: all the lower projections of the clause (FinP and below) are harmonically right-headed.
3.1.2 The head-final domain: the left periphery
Turning to the projections above FinP, Basque is a discourse-configurational language, in the sense of É. Kiss (1995), and operations related to interrogatives, focus, topicalization but also negation affect word order. The relevant heads are Foc, Topic, and Σ. The Focus and Topic heads are null (cf. Ortiz de Urbina 1989b; 1999; Elordieta 2001; Irurtzun 2007), and following Haddican (2004; 2008), I will assume that Σ, the head of the projection that hosts negation (cf. Laka 1990) is null as well. These heads are however the target of movement of lower heads such as V, T and/or Neg. What follows explains these assumptions.
ΣP can induce changes in word order with respect to plain affirmative S-O-V-Aux sentences. As illustrated in (14), in the context of negation, the auxiliary surfaces to the left of the clause, immediately following the negative marker ez, resulting in an ‘inversion’ in the relative order of the auxiliary and the verb:
- (14)
- a.
- Ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- emakumeak
- woman
- leihoa
- window
- ireki.
- open
- The woman didn’t open the window.
- b.
- *Ez
- neg
- emakumeak
- woman
- leihoa
- window
- ireki
- open
- du.
- aux
- c.
- *Emakumeak
- woman
- leihoa
- window
- ireki
- open
- ez
- neg
- du.
- aux
Following Laka (1990), I assume that the negative marker and the auxiliary surface on Σ, the head of a projection dominating the inflectional heads and dominated by FocP (cf. also Elordieta 2001).12 However, I will distance myself from Laka’s (1990) analysis in assuming with Haddican (2004); Elordieta (2013); Etxepare & Haddican (2017) and Elordieta & Haddican (2018) that the negative marker raises to this projection from a lower position located between VP and TP (named NegP in (10)). Thus, in negative clauses, ez raises to Σ via head-movement, together with the inflected auxiliary.13,14
As argued by Haddican (2004), the movement analysis of negation explains why, even though negation surfaces unusually high in Basque, elements to its right scope over it. This is the case for instance of evidential particles. As pointed out by Haddican (2004: 99), the infelicity of the continuation in (15)–where the only possible reading is the one where the person in question is said not to have been born anywhere– suggests that the evidential outscopes negation:
- (15)
- Ez
- neg
- omen
- evid
- zen
- aux
- Oiartzunen
- Oiartzun.in
- jaio,
- be.born
- #
- baina
- but
- ez
- neg
- omen
- evid
- zen
- aux
- kanpoan
- outside.in
- jaio
- be.born
- ere.
- also
- They say she wasn’t born in Oiartzun, # but they say she wasn’t born outside (Oiartzun) either.
Therefore, if evidential particles are merged in a ModalP projection in the vicinity of T (as argued by Elordieta 2001; Haddican 2004; Etxepare 2010; 2016), ez being generated below it and moving to a higher position explains the word order and interpretive facts.
The movements taking place in negative clauses are represented in (16b):
- (16)
- a.
- Ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- emakumeak
- woman
- leihoa
- window
- ireki.
- open
- (= (14a))
- The woman didn’t open the window.
- b.
This analysis implies that the negative marker is first merged to the right of the lexical verb. It thus predicts that clauses that do not project ΣP will display V-Neg order. This is precisely what seems to be happening in certain particular instances of non-finite coordinated clauses, such as the one in (17):
- (17)
- Mundu
- world
- guztia
- all
- esperoan
- wait.in
- eduki
- keep
- eta
- and
- [bera
- they.sg
- agertu
- show.up
- ez]. [Etxepare 2003: 537]
- neg
- Everybody was waiting and they(sg) didn’t show up.
What suggests that the bracketed constituent in (17) might not project ΣP is its general deficient structure: it lacks an auxiliary, and thus arguably a TP projection. It is also deficient in that for instance verbs with a prospective suffix produce a deviant output (18):
- (18)
- *Mundu
- world
- guztia
- all
- esperoan
- wait.in
- eduki
- keep
- eta
- and
- [bera
- they.sg
- agertu-ko
- show.up-prosp
- ez].
- neg
- Lit. Everybody waiting and they(sg) won’t show up.
Concerning the projections above ΣP, adopting Rizzi’s (1997, et seq.) split-CP system with a richly articulated left periphery, and in line with Ortiz de Urbina (1999) and Irurtzun (2007; 2016), I assume that wh-phrases and foci undergo A’-movement to the left-peripheral specifier position of Foc(us)P dominating ΣP.15 This is followed by ‘T-to-C movement’, where the lexical verb and the auxiliary raise to the Foc head. Following standard assumptions, I postulate that FocP is head-initial, which explains the V2-like obligatory adjacency between wh-phrases (or foci) and the verb (cf. Ortiz de Urbina 1989b; 1999; Elordieta 2001; Irurtzun 2007; 2016). (19) and (20) illustrate this point for wh-interrogatives and foci, respectively:16
- (19)
- a.
- Nork
- who
- ireki
- open
- du
- aux
- leihoa?
- window
- Who opened the window?
- b.
- *Nork
- who
- leihoa
- window
- ireki
- open
- du?
- aux
- Who opened the window?
- (20)
- a.
- EMAKUMEAK
- woman
- ireki
- open
- du
- aux
- leihoa.
- window
- THE WOMAN opened the window.
- b.
- *EMAKUMEAK
- woman
- leihoa
- window
- ireki
- open
- du.
- aux
- THE WOMAN opened the window.
The movements taking place in focal and wh-interrogative structures are represented in (21b):17
- (21)
- a.
- Nork
- who
- ireki
- open
- du
- aux
- leihoa?
- window
- (=(19a))
- Who opened the window?
- b.
Just above Foc is the Topic projection. Topicalized constituents move to its specifier, and nothing surfaces in its head position (cf. Ortiz de Urbina 1999; Elordieta 2001).18 Certain DPs constitute improper topics. This is the case for instance of strictly non-presuppositional indefinite pronouns, such as free-choice or existential indefinites reinforced with the additive particle ere ‘too/even’ (Etxeberria & Irurtzun 2015), like zerbait ere ‘something or other’. The left of a wh-phrase is thus unambiguously the topic position, since that area can only host presuppositional expressions, as illustrated in (22):
- (22)
- a.
- Leihoa
- window
- nork
- who
- ireki
- open
- du?
- aux
- Who opened the window?
- b.
- *Zerbait
- something
- ere
- AddP
- nork
- who
- ireki
- open
- du?
- aux
- Who opened something or other?
Finally, following Ortiz de Urbina (1999); Artiagoitia & Elordieta (2016); Elordieta & Haddican (2018); Monforte (2019) among others, I postulate a Force projection, which satisfies the subcategorization requirements of the matrix predicate, and which can host clause-typing markers. There are no mandatory overt Force heads. Nonetheless, Ortiz de Urbina (1999) identifies the (optional) interrogative particle ea as an illocutionary force marker, the overt exponent of a Force head (see also Monforte (2019) and Irurtzun (2022) on other illocutionary markers). This marker is illustrated in example (23) (see also (11a)):
- (23)
- Anak
- Ana
- galdetu
- ask
- du
- aux
- [ForceP
- (ea) [FinP
- q
- Miren
- Miren
- etorriko
- come.prosp
- d-en]].
- aux-C
- Ana asked whether Miren will come.
In a nutshell: whereas Basque declaratives have S-O-V-Aux order, negative and wh-interrogative clauses display leftward movement of heads such as V, Neg and/or T (henceforth “V heads”), resulting in orders that have sometimes been assimilated to ‘residual V2 effects’ (cf. Ortiz de Urbina 1989b; 1994). Topicalization in turn triggers movement of constituents but no leftward movement of V heads. Finally, Force optionally hosts an overt exponent.
3.2 A testing ground for the FOFC
Similar to the German-like OV languages discussed in the literature (see Section 2), Basque clausal embedding creates a potentially FOFC-violating configuration, where a head-final VP selects a head-initial CP/ForceP:
- (24)
What distinguishes the Basque case is that the heads in the head-initial area of the FOFC-violating configuration are potentially phonologically empty. Force only optionally hosts an overt interrogative particle (e.g. ea), Top has no overt exponent, and Foc and Σ trigger movement of V heads in contexts of negation or wh-interrogatives only (and they are arguably absent otherwise).
This offers a nice testing ground to contrast and evaluate the narrow syntactic vs. PF-centric approaches to the FOFC, for only the latter leave room for the phonological properties of heads to feed the evaluation of the FOFC. From the perspective of the syntactic approach, assuming that embedded clauses are all headed by a Force head –overt or null–, clausal complementation in Basque systematically results in a disharmonic FOFC-violating structure. Therefore, it predicts a systematic appeal to compliance strategies such as extraposition or A’-movement –like in the German examples in Section 2.1–, irrespective of whether or not there is an overt exponent such as ea on Force.19
In turn, under a PF-interface approach, where the phonological properties of a derivation could in principle affect the FOFC, we could expect to observe asymmetries in clauses with an overt vs. null Force head. Only the first would appeal to compliance strategies. Then, clauses with vs. without topicalization should not display any differences, given that the Top head is always null. And finally, both approaches make the same prediction with respect to wh-interrogative and negative clauses: these should systematically undergo ‘repair’, for head-movement to Foc and Σ creates a FOFC-violating configuration in which overt heads (V, T, Neg, Fin) end up surfacing in head-initial phrases dominated by a head-final VP.
Next section shows how, even if they are ‘hidden’ by repair strategies, FOFC-effects are observed in Basque clausal complementation, and that, crucially, they closely correlate with overtness, as predicted under the PF-interface approach (and unexpected under the narrow syntactic approach).20
4 FOFC-effects: Displaced vs. in situ clausal complements
The effects of the FOFC are almost invisible in Basque clausal complementation.21 This section shows how they are ‘hidden’ by a number of independent factors, and at the same time it builds a case in favor of a PF-centered approach to the FOFC.
The suffixal complementizers -ela and -en are used in declarative and interrogative clauses respectively, as illustrated in (25) (they are Fin heads; see Section 3.1):
- (25)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- [etorri
- come
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esan
- say
- du.
- aux
- Miren said that they came.
- b.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- [etorri
- come
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu
- ask
- du.
- aux
- Miren asked whether they came.
These examples show that complement clauses can surface preverbally, in what looks like a violation of the FOFC, where a head-final VP would be dominating a head-initial ForceP (see (24)). What is more, embedded clauses with an overt Force head ea or with head-movement to Σ or Foc are also allowed in the preverbal area, as illustrated in (26):
- (26)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- [ea
- Q
- etorri
- come
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu
- ask
- du.
- aux
- Miren asked whether they came.
- b.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- [ez
- neg
- d-ela
- aux-C
- etorri]
- come
- esan
- say
- du.
- aux
- Miren said that they didn’t come.
- c.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- [nor
- who
- etorri
- come
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esan
- say
- du?
- aux
- Who did Miren say that came?
That is, both syntactic and PF-interface approaches to FOFC seem to make incorrect predictions. However, other facts show that a finer analysis is necessary. First of all, clausal complements can surface postverbally, too, as illustrated in (27) (cf. Euskaltzaindia 1999; Ormazabal et al. 1994; Eguzkitza 2003; Artiagoitia 2003a; Elordieta 2008):
- (27)
- Mirenek
- Miren
- esan
- say
- du
- aux
- [etorri
- come
- d-ela].
- aux-C
- Miren said that they came.
This contrasts with the behavior of object DPs, which cannot surface postverbally in neutral contexts (de Rijk 1969):22
- (28)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- hau
- this
- esan
- say
- du.
- aux
- Miren said this.
- b.
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- esan
- say
- du
- aux
- hau.
- this
- Miren said this.
The contrast between (27) and (28b) echoes with the case of German-like languages seen in Section 2.1, and suggests that CP-extraposition is available in Basque too. This in turn suggests that CP-extraposition is potentially a FOFC-compliance strategy, used to ‘escape’ non-compliant configurations.23
Returning now to preverbal clauses: Basque famously allows clausal pied-piping (cf. Ortiz de Urbina 1989b; 1993; Arregi 2003; Heck 2008; Irurtzun 2016). Clausal pied-piping involves clauses that embed a focal or wh-phrase in a long-distance A’-dependency. Instead of this element undergoing A’-movement to the higher SpecFocP, it is the whole clause that is fronted, followed by movement of matrix [V+Aux] to Foc. Crucially, this is actually the standard analysis for examples such as (26c), repeated in (29) (with additional topicalization of the matrix subject Miren):
- (29)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- [nor
- who
- etorri
- come
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esan
- say
- du?
- aux
- (=(26c))
- Who did Miren say that came?
- b.
That is, even if it is left-adjacent to the matrix verb, the complement clause in (26c) does not surface in complement position. It has undergone A’-movement. We saw however that A’-movement escapes the FOFC (Section 2.1); consequently (29) (=(26c)) involves a FOFC-complying configuration.
Crucially, in the same line of analysis, it is possible that the preverbal clauses in (26c) and (26b) embed a focused constituent (or that they are focused as a whole), and –like the complement in (26c)–have pied-piped to the matrix SpecFocP, followed by movement of [V+Aux] to Foc.24 Again, given that A’-movement escapes the FOFC, they would be in FOFC-complying configurations, which would explain why the sentences are grammatical.
In sum, the preverbal position of clausal complements in Basque is structurally ambiguous: it can be either the (in situ) complement of V, or the preverbal focus position. Therefore no relevant conclusion can be drawn concerning the FOFC from examples such as (25) or (26).
There is nonetheless a very specific context that can be used to ensure that no pied-piping (or extraposition) is taking place. This is the so-called ‘quasi-focus’ construction, which involves sentential negation (see Lafitte 1944[1962]; Oyharçabal 1985; de Rijk 1996; Herburger 2000; Etxepare 2003; Ortiz de Urbina 2003; Etxepare & Uribe-Etxebarria 2008). Quasi-focus is the domain of negative clauses which is sandwiched between the [Neg+Aux] cluster and the lexical verb, where constituents can have a focus-like interpretation. In example (30), the object DP leihoa ‘window’ surfaces in this quasi-focus domain.
- (30)
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- leihoa
- window
- itxi.
- close
- Miren didn’t close the window.
What is relevant for us is that this is a position where the constituents remain in situ: given that in contexts of negation the lexical verb remains in V and [Neg+Aux] surface on Σ (see (16)), the domain between them includes the specifiers and modifiers of the projections below ΣP (Ortiz de Urbina 2003). Since FocP is higher than ΣP, a pied-piped clause would surface on the left of negation. Therefore, a clause in the quasi-focus domain will be unambiguously in the in situ, complement-of-V position.25
This is consequently also a position in which a head-initial phrase will create a FOFC-violating configuration with respect to the dominating VP (as in (24)). Thus it allows us to test the predictions made above: if the FOFC is evaluated in the syntax, no finite embedded clause will be able to surface in this position, whereas if it is evaluated at PF, overtness of heads could be a decisive factor, embedded clauses being allowed in that position provided they have null heads on their left-peripheral phrases.
The following examples show that declarative -ela and interrogative -en clauses can indeed surface in that position, as expected under PF-interface approaches only:
- (31)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- etorri
- come
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esan. [In situ declarative clause]
- say
- Miren did not say that Ana came.
- b.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- etorri
- come
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu. [In situ indirect interrogative]
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana came.
Furthermore, overtness of heads affects the grammaticality of the sentence. The following examples show that when left-peripheral heads are overtly involved, either by simply being overt (as with the ea Force head in (32a)) or by hosting lower heads (as with [Neg+Aux] in the negative clause in (32b) or [V+Aux] in the embedded wh-interrogative as in (32c)), then the sentences involving in situ complement clauses are ungrammatical or degraded.26
- (32)
- a.
- ??Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [ea
- q
- Ana
- Ana
- etorri
- come
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu. [In situ ea clause]
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana came.
- b.
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- d-en
- aux-C
- etorri]
- come
- galdetu. [In situ negative clause]
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana didn’t come.
- c.
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en
- aux-C
- Ana]
- Ana
- galdetu. [In situ wh-clause]
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask when Ana came.
This shows that if the sentences in (31) are grammatical, it is due to there not being any overt heads on their left-periphery.
At this stage, the PF-centric approach we sketched above makes a further prediction: the same clauses with overt heads should be grammatical in extraposed postverbal position or in pied-piped preverbal position. This is again the case, as shown in (33) and (34), respectively:27
- (33)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- galdetu
- ask
- [ea
- q
- Ana
- Ana
- etorri
- come
- d-en]. [Extraposed ea clause]
- aux-C
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana came.
- b.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- galdetu
- ask
- [Ana
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- d-en
- aux-C
- etorri]. [Extraposed negative clause]
- come
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana didn’t come.
- c.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- galdetu
- ask
- [noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en
- aux-C
- Ana]. [Extraposed wh-clause]
- Ana
- Miren didn’t ask when Ana came.
- (34)
- a.
- [Ea
- q
- Ana
- Ana
- etorri
- come
- d-en]
- aux-C
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- galdetu
- ask
- Mirenek. [Pied-piped ea clause]
- Miren
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana came.
- b.
- [Ana
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- d-en
- aux-C
- etorri]
- come
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- galdetu
- ask
- Mirenek. [Pied-piped negative clause]
- Miren
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana didn’t come.
- c.
- [Noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en
- aux-C
- Ana]
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- galdetu
- ask
- Mirenek. [Pied-piped wh-clause]
- Miren
- Miren didn’t ask when Ana came.
To close this argumentation, we can check a final prediction of the PF-approach: left-peripheral operations with no overt head or overt head-raising should not affect the evaluation of the FOFC whatsoever. Topicalization, which involves raising to the specifier of a null Top head is precisely like that: it does not lead to ungrammaticality in in situ, quasi-focus clauses. This is illustrated in the minimal pair in (35), where inverting the order between the subject and the object in the (b) sentence –which signals that the object has raised above the subject to TopP– does not lead to ungrammaticality:
- (35)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Anak
- Ana
- leihoa
- window
- itxi
- close
- du-ela]
- aux-C
- esan. [In situ declarative clause]
- say
- Miren did not say that Ana closed the window.
- b.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [leihoa
- window
- Anak
- Ana
- itxi
- close
- du-ela]
- aux-C
- esan.
- say
- Lit. Miren did not say that the window, Ana closed.
Summarizing, this section has identified extraposition and pied-piping as compliance strategies that are at play in Basque clausal complementation. Thus like in other cases identified in the literature, displacing the head-initial phrase dominated by a head-final phrase from a final-over-initial configuration ensures FOFC-compliance. I have argued that ‘hidden’ pied-piping explains why preverbal clausal complements do not trigger FOFC-effects, by showing that clauses that are unambiguously not pied-piped –in in situ (quasi-focus) contexts– do show FOFC-effects. I have also shown that these effects only arise with clauses in which the head-initial domain of the clause (ForceP, FocP or ΣP) hosts some overt exponent. Such contrasts between structurally identical sentences are unexpected under the syntactic approach to the FOFC. In turn, under a PF-interface approach, these complex patterns are expected, if not predicted: it is the presence of overt heads in the head-initial domain of the clause that results in FOFC-violation.28
The next two sections explore certain poorly understood ordering facts of clausal embedding in Basque, which will strengthen and develop the analysis put forth here.
5 Another compliance strategy: V-final order
It is a known feature of Basque that there are word order differences between root and embedded clauses, especially in the context of negation (cf. Altube 1929; Azkue 1923–25[1969]; de Rijk 1969; 1972; Goenaga 1980; Ortiz de Urbina 1989b; Laka 1990; 1991; Euskaltzaindia 1999; Etxepare 2003; Oyharçabal 2003; Artiagoitia 2003a; Artiagoitia & Elordieta 2016; Elordieta & Haddican 2018; Salaberri 2018).
This section discusses these patterns of word order alternations in clausal complements. It argues that they result from FOFC-compliance strategies which involve (i) negative clauses having the negative marker surface between the verb and the auxiliary (Section 5.1), and (ii) wh-interrogatives having the verb in clause-final position and all non-wh material topicalized (Section 5.2). Both cases are then brought together, as a ‘V-final order’ requirement on in situ clauses, where V/Aux/Neg/Fin heads surface on the right edge of the clause (Section 5.3).29
5.1 Word order in negative clauses
In the previous section, the negative sentences all displayed a root-like order where the negative marker –together with the auxiliary– surfaces on the left, rendering the ‘inverted’ [Neg+Aux(-C)…V] order. But is has long been noted that another order is possible in embedded clauses, where the lexical verb and the auxiliary are not inverted, and the negative marker surfaces sandwiched between them: [V+Neg+Aux-C] (henceforth ‘non-inverted order’; see the references above). This order is out in root contexts (see (14c) above). The two orders are illustrated in (36a) and (36b), respectively:30
- (36)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- [ez
- neg
- d-ela
- aux-C
- etorri]
- come
- esan
- say
- du. [Inverted]
- aux
- Miren said that she didn’t come.
- b.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- [etorri
- come
- ez
- neg
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esan
- say
- du. [Non-inverted]
- aux
I will argue that the non-inverted order reveals yet another FOFC-compliance strategy. The idea is that this surface order ‘repairs’ the violation that is otherwise induced by standard structures with negation. In sum, while pied-piping makes (36a) FOFC-compliant, it is the absence of negative inversion that makes (36b) FOFC-compliant. This hypothesis makes a clear prediction: negated clauses with non-inverted order should be allowed in quasi-focus position, where clauses with inverted, root-like order are otherwise out, as was illustrated in (32b), repeated below in (37).
- (37)
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- d-en
- aux-C
- etorri]
- come
- galdetu.
- ask
- (=(32b)) [Inversion + Quasi-focus]
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana didn’t come.
The example in (38) shows that a non-inverted order indeed makes the sentence grammatical:
- (38)
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- etorri
- come
- ez
- neg
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu. [Non-inversion + Quasi-focus]
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana didn’t come.
This hypothesis, especially if we take non-inversion to be a last resort strategy, can also explain why this order is not found in root clauses: in the absence of clausal embedding, there is no FOFC-violation to be circumvented. Similarly, if this is on the right track, then we could expect clausal complements that independently satisfy the FOFC via extrapostion or pied-piping not to display non-inverted orders either. Again, that is the tendency we observe:31
- (39)
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- esan
- say
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- etorri
- come
- ez
- neg
- d-ela]. [Non-inversion + Extraposition]
- aux-C
- Miren said that Ana didn’t come.
- (40)
- */??[Nor
- Who
- etorri
- come
- ez
- neg
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esan
- say
- du
- aux
- Mirenek? [Non-inversion + Pied-piping]
- Miren
- Lit. That who didn’t come did Miren say?
Summarizing, in cases of violation of the FOFC by [Neg+Aux-C] surfacing in the head-initial domain of the clause, Basque uses another FOFC-compliance strategy besides extraposition and pied-piping, which consists in the negative marker surfacing between the verb and the auxiliary.
We can be even more precise in the description of the position of the relevant heads since, as shown by the example in (41), no other constituent –such as the adverb gaur ‘today’– can surface to the right of the [V+Neg+Aux-C] cluster in non-inverted structures.32 That is, the heads must be clause-final:
- (41)
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- etorri
- come
- ez
- neg
- d-en
- aux-C
- gaur]
- today
- galdetu. [Non-inverted]
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask whether Ana didn’t come today.
The FOFC-compliance strategy identified here thus consists in the [V+Neg+Aux-C] string surfacing on the right edge of the embedded clause.
5.2 Word order in wh-interrogative clauses
Another context in which word order facts can be different in root vs. embedded clauses is that of wh-movement (see also Uribe-Etxebarria 2003). Example (32c) (repeated here as (42)) showed that as such, the latter cannot surface in quasi-focus position:
- (42)
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en
- aux-C
- Ana]
- Ana
- galdetu. [Quasi-focus]
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask when Ana came.
However, with a minimal change, this becomes possible:
- (43)
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu.
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask when Ana came.
The difference, on the surface, lies in the position of the subject Ana: whether it surfaces to the right of the verb, or whether it is topicalized and surfaces clause-initially. That such constituents undergo topicalization is shown by the fact that they cannot be strictly non-presuppositional:
- (44)
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [zerbait
- something
- ere
- addP
- noiz
- when
- gertatuko
- happen
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu.
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask when something or other will happen.
All constituents besides the wh-phrase must undergo topicalization in this configuration:
- (45)
- a.
- *Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en
- aux-C
- etxe-ra]
- house-to
- galdetu.
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask when Ana came home.
- b.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- etxe-ra
- house-to
- noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu.
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask when Ana came home.
In the ungrammatical (45a) the subject undergoes topicalization, but the adjunct etxera ‘home’ does not. Topicalization of the latter, as in (45b), is necessary for the sentence to be grammatical.
Topicalization is thus mandatory in in situ wh-interrogatives (see also Uribe-Etxebarria (2003) on systematic topicalization in embedded interrogatives). But one can also see how all the grammatical sentences above have the [V+Aux-C] cluster on the right edge of the embedded clause. The ‘V-final’ order is thus a second, interrelated, property of embedded wh-interrogatives.
Now, I would like to propose that the mandatory V-final order in embedded wh-interrogatives should be understood as resulting from a FOFC-compliance strategy, just like in embedded negative clauses: something that repairs the final-over-final disharmonic configuration created by clausal embedding. Under that view, we can consider that V-final orders are not mandatory in root wh-interrogatives because there is no need to make use of such a strategy. And the same pattern can be expected of clauses where FOFC-compliance is ensured by other means, like extraposition and pied-piping. The examples in (46) show that that is indeed the case:33
- (46)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- galdetu
- ask
- du
- aux
- [noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en
- aux-C
- Ana]. [Extraposition]
- Ana
- Miren asked when Ana came.
- b.
- (?)
- [Noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en
- aux-C
- Ana]
- Ana
- galdetu
- ask
- du
- aux
- Mirenek. [Pied-piping]
- Miren
- Miren asked when Ana came.
The above examples show that postverbal material is allowed (and topicalization is not obligatory) precisely in clausal complements that are extraposed (46a) or pied-piped (46b).34
5.3 Conclusion: V-final order as a compliance strategy
This section observed that clause-internal word order changes take place in complement clauses which are in situ and are not repaired by extraposition or pied-piping. It has proposed that these changes are to be related to yet another compliance strategy.
Negative clauses display clause-final non-inverted [V+Neg+Aux-C] orders, and wh-interrogatives display V-final order and are subject to obligatory topicalization. Both cases involve the heads V/Neg/T/Fin surfacing on the right edge of the clause. As a first step towards understanding the mechanism behind these compliance strategies, I thus conclude that both cases can be subsumed under a single generalization, whereby what I will henceforth call the ‘V-heads’ surface on the right, in V-final order (where ‘V’ is a covert term for all the relevant heads; cf. Section 3.1):35
- (47)
- Generalization on word order alternations in Basque clausal embedding:
- V-final order in in-situ complement clauses is a FOFC-compliance strategy.
As a final comment, I would like to point out that the results of this section also show that word order alternations are not ‘free’ in clausal complements, as one could conclude from previous descriptions of Basque. There are in fact three positions in which the embedded clauses can surface (pied-piped position, extraposed position, or in situ), and the internal word order possibilities co-vary with them.
6 Clause-final V as in-situ V
Section 4 has argued that Basque clausal embedding is ruled by FOFC-evaluation at PF. More precisely, head-initial left-peripheral projections dominated by a head-final VP trigger FOFC-violation only when they host overt heads. Then, Section 5 has argued that clause-final V is a FOFC-compliance strategy. The present section brings these two claims together, by putting forth an analysis of V-final orders which is integrated in the PF-approach to the FOFC.
Recall first that the relevant structures –negative clauses and wh-interrogatives clauses– both involve movement of heads from the head-final domain of the clause to the head-initial domain: movement of Neg+Aux to Σ and movement of V+Aux to Foc, respectively. Now, the V-final order of embedded clauses mirrors the V-final order of the neutral declarative root clauses of this SOV language, where the relevant heads remain in their FinP-internal position. I propose that V-final patterns in embedded clauses indeed result from the relevant heads surfacing FinP-internally in their base position (i.e. in situ), rather than in the left-peripheral domain of the clause. Sections 6.1 and 6.2 provide arguments for this analysis for negative and wh-clauses respectively, and Section 6.3 develops an explanation based on lower copy-deletion, compatible with the PF-approach to FOFC advocated for in this paper.
6.1 Negative clauses
If the in-situ analysis of heads in V-final configurations is on the right track, it means that in negated embedded clauses, none of the V-heads surfaces on Σ, as represented in (48b):36
- (48)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Anak
- Ana
- leihoa
- window
- itxi
- close
- ez
- neg
- du-ela]
- aux-C
- esan.
- say
- Miren didn’t say that Ana didn’t close the window.
- b.
Beyond the word order facts, this analysis explains why these heads behave as a cluster, allowing no phrasal constituent to intervene (as illustrated in (49a)), which contrasts with what is observed for instance in negative root clauses with inverted [Neg+Aux…V] order –where phrasal structures such as DPs or full clauses can surface between [Neg+Aux] and V (see (49b)):
- (49)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Anak
- Ana
- (leihoa)
- window
- itxi
- close
- (*leihoa)
- window
- ez
- neg
- (*leihoa)
- window
- du-ela]
- aux-C
- esan.
- say
- Miren didn’t say that Ana didn’t close the window.
- b.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- leihoa
- window
- itxi.
- close
- Miren didn’t close the window.
Evidence also comes from the relative position these heads occupy with respect to adverbs of manner in negative contexts. The latter are VP-level adverbs that immediately precede the lexical verb (cf. Euskaltzaindia 1985; Elordieta 2001; 2003; Vicente 2008). The example in (50) illustrates this with the adverb azkar ‘quickly, fast’:
- (50)
- Ana
- Ana
- azkar
- fast
- etorri
- came
- da.
- aux
- Ana came fast.
The adverb surfaces to the left of the lexical verb in contexts of negation, too. But this time it is preceded by [Neg+Aux], as illustrated in (51). This is the quasi-focus position; the adverb is therefore in its base-generated position here.
- (51)
- Ana
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- da
- aux
- azkar
- fast
- etorri.
- come
- Ana didn’t come fast.
Adverbs of manner do not easily undergo focus- or topic-movement to the left of the negative marker (52), which indicates that they preferably remain in their base position as modifiers of VP (see Elordieta 2001: 195):
- (52)
- *Azkar
- fast
- ez
- neg
- da
- aux
- Ana
- Ana
- etorri.
- come
- Ana didn’t come fast.
Now, within non-inverted negative clauses, adverbs of manner surface to the immediate left of [V+Neg+Aux-C], as illustrated in (53):
- (53)
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Ana
- Ana
- azkar
- fast
- etorri
- come
- ez
- neg
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esan.
- say
- Miren did not say that Ana didn’t come fast.
The adverb in (53) could not be in a position above ΣP; otherwise we would expect the sentence to be as deviant as (52). It is thus in its base-position, adjoined to VP. Therefore, the negative marker and auxiliary to its right are not on Σ. That is, they surface in their base-position: in a final-headed phrase internal to FinP.
An additional argument can be made based on the behavior of negative polarity items (NPI, cf. Laka 1990; Uribe-Etxebarria 1994; Etxeberria et al. 2021). Etxepare (2003: 545-6) points out that while only a single NPI can surface to the left of negation in root contexts (54), this restriction is lifted in embedded clauses with V-final orders (55):37
- (54)
- a.
- Ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- inork
- anybody
- ezer
- anything
- egin. [Etxepare (2003: 545)]
- do
- Nobody did anything.
- b.
- Inork
- anybody
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- ezer
- anything
- egin.
- do
- c.
- ??Inork
- anybody
- ezer
- anything
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- egin.
- do
- (55)
- Jonek
- Jon
- [inork
- anybody
- ezer
- anything
- egin
- do
- ez
- neg
- du-ela]
- aux-C
- esan
- say
- du.
- aux
- [Adapted from Etxepare (2003: 546)]
- Jon said that nobody did anything.
The examples in (54) show that NPIs can remain in their argument position to the right of [Neg+Aux] (54a), and that no more than one can move to the left-periphery, to the left of [Neg+Aux] on Σ (54b)–(54c). In non-inverted embedded clauses such as (55), they can all be grouped together to the left of the V-heads. This contrast is expected under the in-situ analysis of non-inverted negation. That is, since as argued here, in (55) the V-heads surface in their in situ position and nothing surfaces on Σ, the left-peripheral phrases (topics and foci) as well as the arguments that remain in their base-position will surface indistinguishably on the left of V. Under this analysis, one can thus describe root and embedded clauses as falling under the very same generalization, namely that only one NPI can surface above ΣP.
6.2 Interrogative clauses
The in situ structure of V-final orders in interrogative clauses is less transparent than in negative clauses, because of a structural ambiguity: the V-heads could either be on Foc or in their base-position. Section 5.2 showed that in embedded interrogatives in quasi-focus position, any remnant constituent undergoes obligatory topicalization. Thus, a string such as the one in (56a) could be analysed either as in Hypothesis 1 or Hypothesis 2 below:
- (56)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [leihoa
- window
- nork
- who
- itxi
- close
- du-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu.
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask who closed the window.
- b.
- Hypothesis 1.
- c.
- Hypothesis 2.
The evidence in favor of Hypothesis 2 comes from a specific construction for foci and wh-interrogatives, namely the ‘reinforced’ construction used in Eastern varieties of Basque. While standard wh-constructions involve movement of [V+Aux] to Foc as described in Section 3.1, in reinforced constructions only the inflected auxiliary moves, leaving the lexical verb behind (cf. Lafitte 1944[1962]; Duguine & Irurtzun 2010; Etxepare 2016)):
- (57)
- a.
- Nork
- who
- itxi
- close
- du
- aux
- leihoa? [Standard wh-interrogative]
- window
- Who closed the window?
- b.
- Nork
- who
- du
- aux
- leihoa
- window
- itxi? [Reinforced wh-interrogative]
- close
- Who closed the window?
With this inversion between the verb and the auxiliary, reinforced interrogatives signal unambiguously that the auxiliary surfaces on Foc. They can therefore help us check Hypothesis 2. Now, the example in (58b) shows that this construction cannot be embedded in quasi-focus contexts:
- (58)
- a.
- Anak
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [leihoa
- window
- nork
- who
- itxi
- close
- du-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu. [Standard]
- ask
- Ana didn’t ask who closed the window.
- b.
- *Anak
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [leihoa
- window
- nork
- who
- du-en
- aux-C
- itxi]
- close
- galdetu. [Reinforced]
- ask
- Ana didn’t ask who closed the window.
The above contrast is exactly what can be expected if the V-heads must surface in their own in situ position within these in situ embedded clauses: (58b) is ungrammatical because the auxiliary surfaces on Foc (thus generating a non-compliant configuration), whereas (58a) is grammatical because neither V or Aux surface on Foc.
A further prediction is that the reinforced construction should be possible in extraposed indirect interrogatives. As illustrated in (59), this is borne out:38
- (59)
- Anak
- Ana
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- galdetu
- ask
- [nork
- who
- du-en
- aux-C
- itxi
- close
- leihoa].
- window
- Ana didn’t ask who closed the window.
Next section puts forth an analysis of in situ V-heads based on lower copy pronunciation: the V-heads in clause-final position constitute the lower tail of a movement chain in which the higher copy is not pronounced so as to ensure PF-convergence.
6.3 Lower copy spell-out for FOFC-compliance
If the V-heads surface in situ, does this imply that they do not undergo movement to Σ/Foc in embedded clauses? In other words, is the syntax of V-final clauses different from the others’? Nothing in our data, beyond the contrast in word order, suggests that such an analysis is necessary. The explanation I would like to put forth is that even though head-movement does take place, the heads get ultimately pronounced in the lower position. I thus propose an analysis in terms of copy-deletion (cf. Chomsky (1995) a.o.), where in embedded clauses the V-heads raise to Σ and/or Foc in contexts of negation and/or wh-interrogatives, but instead of the higher copy, it is the lower copy of movement which gets pronounced (and the higher one is deleted).
Under the assumption that pronouncing the lower member of a movement chain is legitimate in cases in which pronouncing the higher one would lead to a PF violation, a rich literature has shown that lower copy spell-out (or lower copy pronunciation) is at play in cases of A’-movement, A-movement, or head movement across languages (cf. among others Bobaljik 1994; 2002; Bošković 2001; 2011; Nunes 2004; Corver & eds.; Kandybowicz 2008; Villa-Garcia 2019). This can be illustrated with a case-study from Bošković (2001), which deals with a particular cases of head-movement in Romanian, which involves syllabic contraction in contexts of clitic-climbing. Romanian clitics undergo contraction when they surface to the left of an auxiliary starting with a vowel. The examples in (60) feature the first person dative clitic just before the finite auxiliary au: the contrast between the two sentences shows that in such contexts the clitic must undergo clitic weakening:
- (60)
- a.
- *Îmi
- me.dat
- au
- have
- ales
- chosen
- articolul. [Romanian; Bošković (2001)]
- article.the
- They have chosen my article.
- b.
- Mi-au
- me.dat-have
- ales
- chosen
- articolul.
- article.the
Contraction does not take place when the clitic is adjacent to a main verb which starts with a vowel:
- (61)
- Îmi
- me.dat
- au
- have
- articolul
- article.the
- pe
- on
- masă.
- table
- They have my article on the table.
But not all clitics show this behavior. Thus, the feminine singular accusative clitic o just cannot occur on the left of auxiliaries starting with a vowel (62a), and it surfaces as an enclitic (62b), even though it can otherwise surface to the left of e.g. main verbs (63):
- (62)
- a.
- *O
- her
- am
- have
- vazut.
- seen
- I have seen her.
- b.
- Am
- have
- vazut-o.
- seen-her
- I have seen her.
- (63)
- O
- her
- am.
- have
- I have her.
Bošković (2001) puts forth the following straightforward account in terms of higher copy deletion: assuming that (i) the feminine singular accusative clitic o cannot take part in the syllabic reduction process when used proclitically, and that (ii) all pronominal clitics –o included– undergo clitic climbing in auxiliary+participle constructions, he proposes that pronouncing the lower copy of o when it undergoes clitic climbing in an auxiliary+participle construction is the only way to derive a legitimate PF output.
My claim is that in Basque a similar mechanism explains the word order alternations observed within clausal complements. The idea is that movement of V-heads to Σ or Foc takes place in all the cases studied above. However, in those cases that would create a FOFC-violating output, the higher copies of this movement chain are deleted and the lower ones pronounced, producing a PF-convergent output.39
The derivation of the non-inverted negative clause in (48a) and the V-final wh-interrogative in (56a) (repeated in (64a) and (65a) respectively) will thus be as follows:
- (64)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [Anak
- Ana
- leihoa
- window
- itxi
- close
- ez
- neg
- du-ela]
- aux-C
- esan.
- say
- Miren didn’t say that Ana didn’t close the window.
- b.
- (65)
- a.
- Mirenek
- Miren
- ez
- neg
- du
- aux
- [leihoa
- window
- nork
- who
- itxi
- close
- du-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu.
- ask
- Miren didn’t ask who closed the window.
- b.
In sum, lower copy pronunciation offers a straightforward explanation for the V-final requirement on clausal complements. Leftward head movement takes place, but generates a FOFC-violating configuration. Deleting the higher copies of the movement chain instead of the lower ones ensures convergence. Furthermore, this explanation is aligned with the analyses made in e.g. Sheehan (2013b; 2017) and Etxepare & Haddican (2017), where lower copy pronunciation as a repair strategy that ensures FOFC-compliance explains a variety of word order facts (see Section 2.2).
6.4 Main Clause Phenomena and alternative analyses
It is a standard observation that cross-linguistically, certain types of embedded clauses do not allow operations that are otherwise possible in root contexts in particular (cf. Hooper & Thompson 1973; Green 1973). Syntactic explanations of such contrasts typically appeal to differences between clause-types: differences in structural size, and/or intervention effects specific to clauses with operator-movement (cf. a.o. Haegeman 2006 and Haegeman & Ürögdi 2010 on the two approaches).
Precisely, in line with this type of approaches, Elordieta & Haddican (2018) develop an analysis of word order alternations in Basque clausal embedding which covers part of the data studied here.40 They argue for instance that in embedded interrogatives introduced by complementizer -en (yes/no interrogatives in their work), (i) the left periphery is truncated and (ii) an interrogative operator undergoes movement. It is then the interaction between these two phenomena that gives as a result for instance what we have called negative clauses with ‘non-inverted order’. Such analyses are categorical: each clause type is expected to behave in a given, regular manner. But what the empirical exploration of clausal embedding in Sections 4 and 5 has shown is that in fact, the word order facts vary in accordance with the syntactic environment of the embedded clause: inversion is allowed in extraposed clauses, pied-piped clauses, but not in in situ clauses, regardless of the complementizer or the clause-type. These patterns cannot be explained in a truncation-based approach, where the internal structure of the clause directly correlates with its type and thus cannot be subject to variation.41
Note furthermore that the approach put forth here relies on a universal generalization: it is based on the FOFC, i.e., on an undoubtedly typologically strong generalization, which results from the way hierarchical structures are built in the grammar (cf. Roberts 2017). The asymmetries and word order alternations are explained without having to postulate structural differences. This is I believe a, important advantage of the present proposal.
7 Conclusion
Basque clausal complementation creates a potentially FOFC-violating configuration with a head-final VP dominating a head-initial ForceP. But the special feature of Basque in this regard is that the head-initial phrases in this configuration do not necessarily host overt exponents, which opens the possibility to test the relevance of overtness for the FOFC. And indeed, this paper has shown that overtness matters for the evaluation of the FOFC. It matters whether Force has an overt exponent or not, but it also matters whether lower head-initial phrases (TopP, FocP and ΣP) host overt heads or not. Among the strategies that allow to escape configurations where overt heads on Force, Foc and/or Σ would be dominated by VP are (i) extraposition or pied-piping of the clause and (ii) lower copy spell out of the offending heads, resulting in strict V-final orders in embedded clauses.
The analysis implies that at the base of these strategies is the fact that FOFC-violations follow from the relevant heads being phonologically overt. If they are null or deleted, compliance ensues. Consequently, the FOFC is a PF phenomenon, sensitive to whether heads have a phonological content, as well as to the specific positions in which heads are realized. This result converges with a growing body of research that suggests that PF factors influence more word order-related phenomena –typically associated to syntax proper– than was standardly thought (see among others Zec & Inkelas 1990; Bošković 2001; 2020; Nunes 2004; Richards 2010; Sabbagh 2014; Kandybowicz & Torrence 2015; Mathieu 2016; Anttila 2016; Bennet et al. 2016; Holmberg et al. 2020).
The results also imply that mere phonological (c)overtness must be integrated in the analyses of the FOFC. Naturally, the studies of the FOFC have in general explored word orders facts with overt heads (as this makes their behavior directly observable), and therefore they do not uncover the potential effects of phonological nullness. It thus remains to be seen what the broader implications are for the earlier literature, i.e., whether all the FOFC-effects that have been described in the literature can be reinterpreted this way and whether more independent evidence can be added that bears witness to the post-syntactic nature of the FOFC. But the analysis also makes more general predictions, and we would expect overt/null alternations of heads in other languages to display the same type of contrasts in grammaticality and/or in appeals to compliance strategies as in Basque, when they occur in non-compliant configurations.42
Finally, concerning the syntax of Basque, by exploring in detail the relation between the different positions in which embedded clauses can surface in the matrix clause and their internal syntactic and PF-properties, this paper has shown that word order alternations are not free, and that they do not correlate with the opposition between root vs. embedded clauses either. They result from different strategies that can be appealed to in a configuration that potentially violates the FOFC. Pied-piping and extraposition allow a complement clause to escape the FOFC, as do non-inverted/V-final orders within in situ embedded clauses. What could look like Main Clause phenomena must in fact be attributed to the FOFC.
Abbreviations
The abbreviations follow the Leipzig Glossing Rules, except: AddP = additive particle; pot = potential; part = partitive; prosp = prospective aspect.
Notes
- As acknowledged in the literature on the FOFC, related observations have been made in earlier works (cf. for instance Greenberg 1963; Williams 1982; Hawkins 1994). [^]
- Note that Holmberg (2000) does not name the generalization; the designation as the Final-Over-Final Condition (FOFC) was put forth in later work. [^]
- The [[C TP] V] order is possible, but assumedly in an A’-position. [^]
- Biberauer et al. (2014a) indicate that Sheehan (2008) was the first to point out the significance of this observation with respect to the FOFC. [^]
- Biberauer et al. (2014a) discuss similar VP-fronting data from Latin and Sardinian. [^]
- Other approaches to the FOFC propose that it derives from factors related to processing (cf. Hawkins 2004; Cecchetto 2013; Philip 2013). [^]
- For expository convenience, I will use a representation with specifier-head-complement order of final-headed phrases. See however the antisymmetric approaches to Basque word order in Ormazabal et al. (1994); Elordieta (1997); Haddican (2004; 2008); Etxepare & Haddican (2017), as well as the discussion of some of their shortcomings in Elordieta (2008; 2013) and Vicente (2008). Alternatively, other works adopt a harmonically right-headed clause-structure (cf. Arregi 2002; Arregi & Nevins 2012). I refer the reader to the literature cited below in this section for further evidence in favor of the disharmonic structure assumed here. What this paper will ultimately show is that certain left-peripheral PF-phenomena feed the evaluation of the FOFC. The results must therefore be taken into account independently of the adopted model. [^]
- For the sake of simplicity, I will abstract away from heads that are not immediately relevant to the discussion, such as the v, Aspect or Applicative heads. [^]
- The suffix -en also surfaces on subjunctives. Other complementizers include declarative bait-, negative -enik, factive -ena (see Artiagoitia 2003b). [^]
- Monforte (2019; 2020) argues that the interrogative particle -a, used in Eastern varieties, is yet another exponent of Finiteness. [^]
- In Vergara’s (2018) analysis, -en and -ela can nonetheless encode both Finiteness and Force. [^]
- In Haddican (2004; 2008) and Elordieta & Haddican (2018), ez is instead assumed to be phrasal. [^]
- Ortiz de Urbina (1988; 1994) and G. Elordieta (1997) develop similar analyses, where ez is first-merged below TP/InflP and raises to a higher head-initial phrase together with the auxiliary. [^]
- The emphatic affirmative marker ba- has the same syntax as the negative marker (Oyharçabal 1984; Laka 1990). For simplifying the discussion, in this paper I will exclusively focus on negation. [^]
- This is nowadays the most prominent analysis in Basque syntax. Alternatives analyses have been proposed, where for instance focus does not involve leftward movement, as in Elordieta (2001) or Arregi (2002). See Irurtzun (2007) for a discussion and evaluation of both types of approaches. [^]
- The younger speakers of Eastern dialects allow non adjacent orders like the ones in (19b)-(20b), in what is a wh-in-situ strategy (cf. Duguine & Irurtzun 2014). I am abstracting away from it here, and focusing on standard interrogatives. [^]
- The syntax of wh-interrogatives and foci are virtually identical, which is why in the rest of the paper, for the sake of simplicity and readability, I will only use examples with wh-interrogatives to illustrate both cases. Thus every mention of “wh-interrogatives” should be understood as “wh-interrogatives and/or foci”. See nonetheless footnote 31 on a possible difference when pied-piping is involved. [^]
- Ortiz de Urbina (1999) distinguishes two Topic positions, above and below ForceP. This distinction is not relevant for our purposes here. [^]
- Alternatively, one could argue that the absence of an overt Force head implies the absence of a Force projection altogether (though see Section 6.4 on the viability of approaches based on e.g. truncation). In this case, appeal to repair strategies only in the presence of an overt Force head would be expected. But then, we would expect topicalization to make a difference: embedded clauses with a topicalized constituent –and thus a (null) Top head– should systematically appeal to compliance strategies, while clauses without topicalization should not. As shown below, this prediction is not borne out, since topicalization is not a factor associated with FOFC-effects. (Note that under the syntactic approach, one could not appeal to the hypothesis that TopP is right-headed either, since this would give a FOFC-violating configuration where a right-headed TopP dominates a left-headed FocP or ΣP.) [^]
- As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, the idea that the Top/Foc/ Σ heads could create a FOFC-violating configuration with a higher VP contravenes the definitions of the FOFC such as the one in (2), which refer to the relevant dominance relations as being ‘immediate’ (since their relation is mediated by (at least) the intervening ForceP). See the discussion in footnote 28. [^]
- I will exclusively focus on finite clauses, leaving aside non-finite complementation. The latter nonetheless is most probably relevant, for it displays word order alternations which might be connected to compliance strategies (cf. for instance Ortiz de Urbina 1989a; Artiagoitia 2003a; b; Etxepare 2003; Etxepare & Ortiz de Urbina 2003). [^]
- See Ortiz de Urbina (2002) on clause-final wh-phrases and foci (see also Uribe-Etxebarria 2002). [^]
- I will remain agnostic as to whether extraposition in Basque is a syntactic or post-syntactic phenomenon. The PF-approach to the FOFC developed below is in principle compatible with both hypotheses. [^]
- See also Artiagoitia (2003b: 652), who points out that focused clauses tend to be preverbal rather than postverbal (i.e., extraposed), as well as Zabala (2000) and Vicente (2008)). [^]
- Etxepare & Uribe-Etxebarria (2008) put forth an analysis where the (quasi-)focal constituent moves to a ‘low’ FocP projection on the periphery of the VP, and where scrambling of other constituents can also take place. Irrespective of the analysis we adopt, what is important is that no initial-headed phrase is involved; this is thus arguably a domain of the clause which creates a disharmonic, “final VP over initial ForceP” configuration. [^]
- In (32c), the postverbal subject signals unambiguously that the wh-phrase and the verb surface on the left periphery. [^]
- The sentences in (34) could constitute answers to a question like “What didn’t Mary ask?”, with the whole embedded clause being focused. [^]
- As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, considering that embedded TopP/FocP/ΣP could create FOFC-violating configurations with a higher VP contravenes the definitions of the FOFC such as the one in (2), which refer to the relevant dominance relations as being ‘immediate’. Indeed, there is always an intervening ForceP, arguably, but also potentially a TopP, etc. Our results thus imply that the definition of the FOFC must be changed, by suppressing the reference to immediateness. Note nonetheless that immediateness is not necessarily relevant for the earlier works on the FOFC either. These do not take into consideration the possibility for overtness to be a factor and hence they systematically have local relationships between phrases. That is, if there is an intervening phrase βP between two phrases αP and ɣP that violate the FOFC, βP will also be in a FOFC-violating configuration with either αP or ɣP, as illustrated in (i):
- (i)
- V-final orders are observed in a wide array of clausal embedding constructions in Basque (cf. Euskaltzaindia 1999; Artiagoitia 2003a; Elordieta & Haddican 2016, and references therein); they are even a strict requirement in e.g. relative clauses (Oyharçabal 2003). Exploring these cases goes beyond the scope of this paper. [^]
- Some authors consider declarative -ela clauses (unlike interrogative -en clauses) with non-inverted [V+Neg+Aux-C] orders to be deviant, even though they acknowledge their use (cf. Artiagoitia 2003b; Artiagoitia & Elordieta 2016; Elordieta & Haddican 2018). However, the Academy of the Basque Language and other authors take these orders to be grammatical (cf. Euskaltzaindia 1999; Etxepare 2003). Moreover, they are widely attested in contemporary written and oral usage, and importantly, speakers have very clear intuitions regarding the contexts in which they are allowed. The bracketed embedded clauses in the following sentences found on the Contemporary Reference Prose corpus of the University of the Basque Country UPV/EHU illustrate the use of this ordering in fiction, essays, translations, and newspapers (https://www.ehu.eus/euskara-orria/euskara/ereduzkoa/):
- (i)
- From an essay (Euskararen etxea, Pello Salaburu (2002: 59)):
- [Deusik
- Nothing
- ere
- AddP
- aldatu
- change
- ez
- neg
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- pentsatzen
- think
- duten
- aux.C
- horien
- those.gen
- gogoa
- mind
- freskatzeko
- refresh.nmlz.to
- balio
- use
- dezake
- aux.pot
- horrek
- that
- That can be used to refresh the mind of those who think that nothing has changed.
- (ii)
- From a translated essay (Loroaren teorema, Denis Guedj / Jon Muñoz (2006: 136)):
- [Gauza
- thing
- bat
- one
- existitzen
- exist
- ez
- neg
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esateko,
- say.nmlz.to
- existitzerik
- exist.nmlz.part
- ez
- neg
- dauka-la
- has-C
- frogatzea
- prove.nmlz
- da
- is
- era
- mode
- bakarra.
- single.D
- In order to say that something does not exist, the only way is to prove that it cannot exist.
- (iii)
- From a novel (Lagun izoztua, Joseba Sarrionandia (2001: 327)):
- [Atertzen
- clear.up
- ez
- neg
- du-ela]
- aux-C
- ohartzean,
- realize.nmlz.in
- elkarren
- each.other.gen
- beldur
- fear
- susmoak
- suspicions
- sentituko
- feel.prosp
- dituzue.
- aux
- When you realize that the weather does not clear up, you will feel afraid of each other.
- (iv)
- From a newspaper (Berria. 2004-01-31):
- [Erraza
- easy
- izango
- be.prosp
- ez
- neg
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- jakin
- know
- badaki,
- know.3sg
- hau
- this
- izango
- be.prosp
- baitu
- because.aux
- laugarren
- fourth
- Munduko
- world.of
- Txapelketa.
- championship
- They do know that it will not be easy, since this will be their fourth World Championship.
- The judgements are less clear with focus-induced pied-piping, where for some speakers negative inversion is not as bad. This is illustrated in (i), which differs minimally from (40). It looks like for these speakers A’-movement with focus does not necessarily ensure FOFC-compliance. I leave this issue on the interaction between type of A’-movement and the FOFC for future research.
- (i)
- */?[ANA
- Ana
- etorriko
- come.prosp
- ez
- neg
- d-ela]
- aux-C
- esan
- say
- du
- aux
- Mirenek. [Non-inversion + Pied-piping]
- Miren
- Miren said that ANA won’t come.
- The strict V-final requirement on non-inverted negative clauses has been observed in other types of embedding: see footnote 29. [^]
- Many speakers prefer pied-piped clauses to involve topicalization, as in (i) (cf. Uribe-Etxebarria 2003):
- (i)
- [Ana
- Ana
- noiz
- when
- etorri
- come
- d-en]
- aux-C
- galdetu
- ask
- du
- aux
- Mirenek.
- Miren
- [Pied-piping + Topicalization]
- Miren asked when Ana came.
- (46b) could be an answer to the question ‘What did Miren ask?’, with focus on the embedded clause. [^]
- The label “V-head” is given for practical reasons; it does not imply that the relevant heads have e.g. V features or verbal properties. [^]
- I will remain agnostic as to whether head-to-head movement still takes place within the FinP. [^]
- See also Laka (1990: 47) who makes a similar point regarding relative clauses. [^]
- These results bring more nuance to Duguine & Irurtzun’s (2010) description of reinforced constructions whereby even though they are generally not allowed in embedded contexts, some variation is observed across speakers. [^]
- See also Arregi & Pietraszko’s (2021) analysis of head-movement in which ‘moved’ heads can be pronounced either in their higher position or a lower one (cf. lowering). [^]
- Even though, unlike in the present paper, it does not take into account the varied positions in which embedded clauses surface with respect to the matrix clause, Elordieta & Haddican’s (2018) work covers a large typology of clauses and it also aims at accounting for the contrasts in the verb-first restriction observed across this typology. Exploring these two empirical domains goes beyond the scope of this paper. Duguine (to appear) nonetheless discusses the V-final ordering across different types of clausal embedding in Basque, showing how in relativized or adjunct clauses, overtness of heads, but also their affixation properties affect the word order possibilities, and thus, arguably, FOFC-compliance. [^]
- A reviewer suggests that an alternative account could be considered in which just those clauses that are allowed in situ and show non-inverted orders are truncated, and maybe lack the relevant left-headed functional projections (Force, Top, Foc, Σ, etc). Such an analysis could be considered, which would not necessarily be related to Main Clause Phenomena. However, as the reviewer themself points out, it would predict e.g wh-movement or topicalization not to take place in these contexts, contrary to fact (the data in Section 5.2 shows that constituents to the left of wh-phrases are necessarily topics, showing furthermore that wh-phrases surface in SpecFocP). [^]
- In this respect, Biberauer et al. (2014a) present Hindi data as evidence in favor of a narrow syntactic approach to the FOFC (and against one in which overtness could matter). Hindi is an OV language with clause-initial complementizers and clause-extraposition, which Biberauer et al. take to indicate that preverbal clauses are not FOFC-compliant. Citing Josef Bayer (p.c.) they point out that null complementizers are allowed in this language, but yet they do not facilitate preverbal CPs, as shown in (i):
- (i)
- Hindi (Davison 2007: 177; cited in Biberauer et al. 2014a: 186)
- a.
- usee
- 3sg.dat
- (yah)
- this
- maluum
- known
- hai
- is
- [ki
- that
- vee
- 3pl
- aa
- come
- rahee
- prog
- haiN].
- are
- He/She knows that they are coming.
- b.
- *usee
- 3sg.dat
- [(ki)
- that
- vee
- 3pl
- aa
- come
- rahee
- prog
- haiN]
- are
- maluum
- known
- hai.
- is
- He/She knows that they are coming.
- (ii)
- It is believed [(that) he likes linguistics].
- (iii)
- a.
- b.
- c.
- d.
- e.
- f.
- It seemed at that time [*(that) David had left].
- What the students believe is [*(that) they will pass the exam].
- They suspected and we believed [*(that) Peter would visit the hospital].
- Mary believed Peter finished school and Bill [*(that) Peter got a job].
- [*(That) John likes Mary] Jane didn’t believe.
- [*(That) he liked linguistics] was widely believed.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank three anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments and suggestions, and the audiences in GLOW43, CamCoS9, Hizkuntzalari Euskaldunen V. Topaketa [5th Meeting of Basque Linguists], where I have presented parts of the material included in this paper, as well as my colleagues at IKER UMR5478, HiTT (UPV/EHU) and in the UV2 group, and in particular Aritz Irurtzun, Georg Kaiser and Myriam Uribe-Etxebarria, for comments and helpful discussion. Thanks are also due to the editor, Johan Rooryck, and the volume editors, Despina Oikonomou and Gillian Ramchand for facilitating the reviewing process. All errors are my own.
Funding information
This work was partially funded by the ANR-DFG project Uncovering V2 effects: An interface-based typology (UV2) ANR18-FRAL0006.
Competing interests
The author has no competing interests to declare.
References
Altube, Sebero. 1929. Erderismos. Bermeo: Gaubeka.
Anttila, Arto. 2016. Phonological effects on syntactic variation. Annual Review of Linguistics 2. 115–137. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-linguistics-011415-040845
Arregi, Karlos. 2002. Focus on Basque movements. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation.
Arregi, Karlos. 2003. Clausal pied-piping. Natural Language Semantics 2. 115–143. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1024499226731
Arregi, Karlos & Nevins, Andrew. 2012. Morphotactics: Basque auxiliaries and the structure of spellout. Dordrecht: Springer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-3889-8
Arregi, Karlos & Pietraszko, Asia. 2021. The ups and downs of head displacement. Linguistic Inquiry 52(2). 241–289. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00377
Artiagoitia, Xabier. 1995. Verbal projections in Basque and minimal structure. International Journal of Basque Linguistics and Philology (ASJU) 36. 355–405.
Artiagoitia, Xabier. 2002. The functional structure of the Basque noun phrase. In Artiagoitia, Xabier & Goenaga, Patxi & Lakarra, Joseba A. (eds.), Erramu Boneta: A festschrift for Rudolf P. G. de Rijk, 73–90. Vitoria-Gasteiz: UPV/EHUko Argitalpen zerbitzua.
Artiagoitia, Xabier. 2003a. Adjunct subordination. In Hualde, José Ignacio & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz (eds.), A Grammar of Basque, 710–762. Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Artiagoitia, Xabier. 2003b. Complementation. In Hualde, José Ignacio & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz (eds.), A Grammar of Basque, 634–710. Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Artiagoitia, Xabier. 2008. Izen sintagmaren hurrenkera: osagarriak aurretik, buruak gero. In Arteatx, Inigo & Artiagoitia, Xabier & Elordieta, Arantzazu (eds.), Antisimetriaren hipotesia vs. Buru parametroa: Euskararen oinarrizko hurrenkera ezbaian, 157–198. Bilbao: UPV/EHUko Argitalpen Zerbitzua.
Artiagoitia, Xabier & Elordieta, Arantzazu. 2016. On the semantic function and selection of Basque finite complementizers. In Boye, Kasper & Kehayov, Petar (eds.), Complementizer semantics in European languages, 379–413. Berlin & Boston: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110416619-013
Azkue, Resurrección María de. 1923-25[1969]. Morfología vasca. Bilbao: LGEV 2nd edn. Bennet, Ryan, Emily Elfner & James McCloskey. 2016. Lightest to the right: An apparently anomalous displacement in Irish. Linguistic Inquiry 47(2). 169–234. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00209
Biberauer, Theresa. 2017. The Final-over-Final Condition and Particles. In Sheehan, Michelle & Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Holmberg, Anders (eds.), The Final-Over-Final Condition: A Syntactic Universal, 187–296. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8687.003.0012
Biberauer, Theresa & Holmberg, Anders & Roberts, Ian. 2014a. A syntactic universal and its consequences. Linguistic Inquiry 45(2). 169–225. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00153
Biberauer, Theresa & Holmberg, Anders & Roberts, Ian & Sheehan, Michelle. 2017. Empirical evidence for the final-over-final-condition. In Sheehan, Michelle & Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Holmberg, Anders (eds.), The Final-over-Final Condition. A syntactic universal, 11–25. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8687.003.0005
Biberauer, Theresa & Newton, Glenda & Sheehan, Michelle. 2009a. Limiting synchronic and diachronic variation and change: the Final-Over-Final Constraint. Language and Linguistics 10(4). 699–741.
Biberauer, Theresa & Newton, Glenda & Sheehan, Michelle. 2009b. The Final-over-Final Constraint and predictions for diachronic change. In Compton, Ruth & Irimia, Monica (eds.), Toronto Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 31. http://twpl.library.utoronto.ca/index.php/twpl/article/view/6091.
Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Sheehan, Michelle. 2014b. No-choice parameters and the limits of syntactic variation. In Santan-LaBarge, Robert (ed.), Proceedings of WCCFL 31. 399–408. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.
Biberauer, Theresa & Sheehan, Michelle. 2012. Disharmony, Antisymmetry, and the Final-over-Final Constraint. In Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam & Valmala, Vidal (eds.), Ways of structure building, 206–244. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199644933.003.0009
Bobaljik, Jonathan. 1994. What does adjacency do? MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 22. 1–32.
Bobaljik, Jonathan. 2002. Syncretism without Paradigms: Remarks on Williams 1981, 1994. In Booij, Geert & van Marle, Jaap (eds.), Yearbook of morphology 2001, 53–85. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3726-5_2
Bošković, Željko. 1997. LF Movement and the Minimalist Program. In Tamanji, Pius & Kusumoto, Kiyomi (eds.), Proceedings of NELS 28. 43–57. University of Massachusetts Amherst: GLSA.
Bošković, Željko. 2001. On the Nature of the Syntax-Phonology Interface. Cliticization and Related Phenomena. Oxford: Elsevier. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1163/9780585474250
Bošković, Željko. 2011. Rescue by PF deletion, traces as (non-)interveners, and the that-trace effect. Linguistic Inquiry 42. 1–44. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00027
Bošković, Željko. 2020. On the Syntax and Prosody of Verb Second and Clitic Second. In Biberauer, Theresa & Wolfe, Sam & Woods, Rebecca (eds.), Rethinking Verb Second, Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198844303.003.0021
Bošković, Željko & Lasnik, Howard. 2003. On the distribution of null complementizers. Linguistic Inquiry 34(4). 527–546. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/002438903322520142
Cecchetto, Carlo. 2013. Backward dependencies must be short. In Challenges to Linearization, 57–92. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9781614512431.57
Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2009. The fundamental left-right asymmetry of natural languages. In Scalise, Sergio & Magni, Elisabetta & Bisetto, Antonietta (eds.), Universals of language today, 165–184. Springer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-8825-4_9
Clem, Emily. 2021. Disharmony and the Final-Over-Final Condition in Amahuaca. Linguistic Inquiry 1–14. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00425
Corver, Norbert & Nunes, Jairo (eds.). 2007. The Copy Theory of Movement. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.107
Davison, Alice. 2007. Word order, parameters, and the Extended COMP projection. In Bayer, Josef & Bhattacharya, Tanmoy & Babu, M. T. Hany (eds.), Linguistic theory and South Asian languages, 175–198. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.102.16dav
de Rijk, Rudolph P. G. 1969. Is Basque an SOV Language. Fontes Linguae Vasconum 1. 319–351.
de Rijk, Rudolph P. G. 1972. Studies in Basque Syntax: Relative Clauses. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation.
de Rijk, Rudolph P. G. 1996. Focus and quasifocus in Basque negative statements. Revista Internacional de Estudios Vascos RIEV 41. 63–76.
Dryer, Matthew. 2009. The branching direction theory of word order correlations revisited. In Scalise, Sergio, Magni, Elisabetta & Bisetto, Antonietta (eds.), Universals of language today, 185–207. Berlin: Springer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-8825-4_10
Duguine, Maia & Irurtzun, Aritz. 2010. Opérateurs d’exclusivité dans les questions et réponses en basque. Revue de Sémantique et Pragmatique 27. 105–117.
Duguine, Maia & Irurtzun, Aritz. 2014. From obligatory Wh-movement to optional Wh in situ in Labourdin Basque. Language 90(1). e1–e30. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2014.0006
Eguzkitza, Andolin. 2003. Eskumaldera bazterturiko perpaus osagarriak. In Makazaga, Jesus Mari & Oyharcabal, Bernard (eds.), Euskal Gramatikari eta literaturari buruzko Jardunaldiak XXI. mendearen atarian (I-II), 195–205. Bilbao: Jesus Mari Makatzaga and Bernard Oyharcabal.
Elordieta, Arantzazu. 2001. Verb movement and constituent permutation in Basque. Utrecht: LOT.
Elordieta, Arantzazu. 2003. Moduzko adberbioak eta adberbioen arteko hurrenkeraz. In Makazaga, Jesus Mari & Oyharcabal, Bernard (eds.), Euskal Gramatikari eta literaturari buruzko Jardunaldiak XXI. mendearen atarian (I-II), 207–232. Bilbao: Euskaltzaindia.
Elordieta, Arantzazu. 2008. OA hizkuntza: oinarrizko hurrenkeraz eta hurrenkera eratorriez. In Arteatx, Iñigo & Artiagoitia, Xabier & Elordieta, Arantzazu (eds.), Antisimetriaren hipotesia vs. Buru parametroa: Euskararen oinarrizko hurrenkera ezbaian, 97–129. Bilbao: UPV/EHUko Argitalpen Zerbitzua.
Elordieta, Arantzazu. 2013. On the relevance of the Head Parameter in a mixed OV language. In Biberauer, Theresa & Sheehan, Michelle (eds.), Theoretical approaches to disharmonic word order, 306–329. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199684359.003.0011
Elordieta, Arantzazu & Haddican, Bill. 2016. Strategies of verb and verb phrase focus across Basque dialects. In Fernandez, Beatriz & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz (eds.), Microparameters in the Grammar of Basque, 221–242. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/lfab.13.08elo
Elordieta, Arantzazu & Haddican, Bill. 2018. Truncation feeds intervention. Two clause type effects in Basque. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 36. 403–443. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-017-9381-0
Elordieta, Gorka. 1997. Morphosyntactic feature chains and phonological domains. Los Angeles, CA: University of Southern California dissertation.
Erlewine, Michael Yoshitaka. 2017. Low sentence-final particles in Mandarin Chinese and the Final-over-Final Constraint. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 26(1). 37–75. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s10831-016-9150-9
Etxepare, Ricardo. 2003. Negation. In Hualde, José Ignacio & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz (eds.), A Grammar of Basque, 516–564. Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110895285.516
Etxepare, Ricardo. 2010. Omen bariazioan. In Fernández, Beatriz & Albizu, Pablo & Etxepare, Ricardo (eds.), Euskara eta euskarak: aldakortasun sintaktikoa aztergai, 85–112. Bilbao: UPV/EHUko Argitalpen zerbitzua.
Etxepare, Ricardo. 2016. Laguntzailea aditz sintetiko gisa ekialdeko hizkeretan. Lapurdum 19. 251–263. DOI: http://doi.org/10.4000/lapurdum.3350
Etxepare, Ricardo & Haddican, Bill. 2017. Repairing Final-Over-Final Condition violations: Evidence from Basque verb clusters. In Bailey, Laura R. & Sheehan, Michelle (eds.), Order and structure in syntax I: Word order and syntactic structure, 135–157. Berlin: Language Science Press.
Etxepare, Ricardo & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz. 2003. Focalisation and Wh-movement in Basque. In Hualde, José Ignacio & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz (eds.), A Grammar of Basque, 459–515. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Etxepare, Ricardo & Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam. 2008. On negation and focus in Spanish and Basque. In Artiagoitia, Xabier & Lakarra, Joseba (eds.), Gramatika Jaietan. Patxi Goenagaren omenez, 287–310. Bilbao: UPV/EHUko Argitalpen Zerbitzua.
Etxeberria, Urtzi & Irurtzun, Aritz. 2015. The Emergence of Scalar Meanings. Frontiers in Psychology 6(141). DOI: http://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00141
Etxeberria, Urtzi & Tubau, Susagna & Borras-Comes, Joan & Espinal, M. Teresa. 2021. Polarity Items in Basque. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 39. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-021-09513-2
Euskaltzaindia. 1985. Euskal Gramatika: Lehen Urratsak I. Iruñea: Euskaltzaindia.
Euskaltzaindia. 1999. Euskal Gramatika. Lehen Urratsak V. Bilbao: Euskaltzaindia.
Goenaga, Patxi. 1980. Gramatika bideetan. Donostia: Erein.
Goenaga, Patxi. 1984. Euskal sintaxia: konplementzioa eta nominalizazioa. Vitoria-Gasteiz: University of the Basque Country UPV/EHU dissertation.
Green, Georgia. 1973. Main clause phenomena in subordinate clauses. Language 52. 382–397. DOI: http://doi.org/10.2307/412566
Greenberg, Joseph. 1963. Some universals of grammar with particular reference to the order of meaningful elements. In Greenberg, Joseph (ed.), Universals of language, 58–90. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Haddican, Bill. 2008. Euskal perpausaren oinarrizko espez-buru-osagarri hurrenkeraren aldeko argudio batzuk. In Arteatx, Iñigo & Artiagoitia, Xabier & Elordieta, Arantzazu (eds.), Antisimetriaren hipotesia vs. Buru parametroa: Euskararen oinarrizko hurrenkera ezbaian, 69–96. Bilbao: UPV/EHUko Argitalpen Zerbitzua.
Haddican, William. 2004. Sentence polarity and word order in Basque. The Linguistic Review 21. 87–124. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/tlir.2004.004
Haegeman, Liliane. 2006. Conditionals, factives and the left periphery. Lingua 116. 1651–1669. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2005.03.014
Haegeman, Liliane & Ürögdi, Barbara. 2010. Operator movement, referentiality and intervention. Theoretical Linguistics 36. 233–246. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/thli.2010.017
Haider, Hubert. 2012. Symmetry Breaking in Syntax (Cambridge Studies in Linguistics). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139084635
Hawkins, John. 1994. A performance theory of order and constituency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511554285
Hawkins, John A. 2004. Efficiency and complexity in grammars. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199252695.001.0001
Heck, Fabian. 2008. On pied-piping: wh-movement and beyond. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110211467
Hein, Johannes & Murphy, Andrew. 2020. VP-Nominalization and the Final-over-Final Condition. Linguistic Inquiry 1–34. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00407
Herburger, Elena. 2000. What counts. Focus and Quantification. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/7201.001.0001
Holmberg, Anders. 2000. Deriving OV order in Finnish. In Svenonius, Peter (ed.), The derivation of VO and OV, 123–152. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.31.06hol
Holmberg, Anders. 2017a. Introduction. In Sheehan, Michelle & Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Holmberg, Anders (eds.), The Final-over-Final Condition. A syntactic universal, 1–10. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8687.003.0004
Holmberg, Anders. 2017b. The Final-over-Final Condition and Linearization in Generative Grammar. In Sheehan, Michelle & Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Holmberg, Anders (eds.), The Final-over-Final Condition. A syntactic universal, 43–77. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8687.003.0007
Holmberg, Anders. 2017c. The Final-over-Final Condition in a mixed-word-order language. In Sheehan, Michelle & Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Holmberg, Anders (eds.), The Finalover-Final Condition. A syntactic universal, 297–322. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8687.003.0013
Holmberg, Anders & Sakhai, Heete & Tamm, Anne. 2020. Prosody distinguishes Estonian V2 from Finnish and Swedish. In Proceedings of the 10th International Conference on Speech Prosody 2020. Tokyo: Tokyo University. DOI: http://doi.org/10.21437/SpeechProsody.2020-90
Hooper, Joan & Thompson, Sandra. 1973. On the applicability of root transformations. Linguistic Inquiry 4. 465–497.
Irurtzun, Aritz. 2007. The Grammar of Focus at the Interfaces. Vitoria-Gasteiz: University of the Basque Country (UPV/EHU) dissertation.
Irurtzun, Aritz. 2016. Strategies for argument and adjunct focalization in Basque. In Fernandez, Beatriz & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz (eds.), Microparameters in the Grammar of Basque, 243–263. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/lfab.13.09iru
Irurtzun, Aritz. 2022. Basque non-interrogative nola as a factive complementizer. In J˛edrzejowski, Łukasz & Umbach, Carla (eds.), Non-interrogative Subordinate Wh-clauses, xx–xx. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Under revision.
Kandybowicz, Jason. 2008. The grammar of repetition: Nupe grammar at the syntax-phonology interface. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/la.136
Kandybowicz, Jason & Torrence, Harold. 2015. The Prosodic Licensing of Wh-In-Situ: Evidence from Krachi and Wasa. In Kramer, Ruth & Zsiga, Elizabeth C. & Boyer, One Tlale (eds.), Selected Proceedings of the 44th Annual Conference on African Linguistics. 146–157. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.
Kayne, Richard S. 1994. The Antisymmetry of Syntax. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Kiss, Katalin E. (ed.). 1995. Discourse Configurational Languages. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Koptjevskaja-Tamm, Maria. 1988. A typology of action nominal constructions. Stockholm: Stockholm University dissertation.
Koptjevskaja-Tamm, Maria. 1993. Nominalizations. London: Croom Helm.
Lafitte, Pierre. 1944[1962]. Grammaire basque: Navarro-labourdin litteraire. Bayonne: Le livre.
Laka, Itziar. 1990. Negation in Syntax: On the Nature of Functional Categories and Projections. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation.
Laka, Itziar. 1991. Sentence Negation in Basque. In Lakarra, Joseba A. (ed.), Memoriae L. Mitxelena Magistri Sacrum, 899–929. Donostia: UPV/EHUko Argitalpen zerbitzua.
Ledgeway, Adam. 2012. From Latin to Romance: Morphosyntactic Typology and Change. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199584376.001.0001
Mathieu, Eric. 2016. The wh-parameter and radical externalization. In Eguren, Luis & Fernández-Soriano, Olga & Mendikoetxea, Amaya (eds.), Rethinking parameters, 252–290. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190461737.003.0009
Monforte, Sergio. 2019. Question particles in Basque. Isogloss. A journal on variation of Romance and Iberian languages 4(1). 29. DOI: http://doi.org/10.5565/rev/isogloss.48
Monforte, Sergio. 2020. Galdera partikulak euskaraz. Fontes Linguae Vasconum 130. 399–424. DOI: http://doi.org/10.35462/flv.130.2
Nunes, Jairo. 2004. Linearization of chains and sideward movement. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/4241.001.0001
Ormazabal, Javier & Uriagereka, Juan & Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam. 1994. Word order and wh-movement: Towards a parametric account. Paper presented at the 17th GLOW, Vienna.
Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 1988. Negative structures in Basque. University of Deusto.
Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 1989a. Dislocaciones verbales en estructuras de polaridad. Anuario del Seminario Julio de Urquijo XXIII(2). 393–410.
Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 1989b. Some Parameters in the Grammar of Basque. Dordrecht: Foris. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110876741
Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 1993. Feature percolation and clausal pied-piping. In Hualde, José-Ignacio & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz (eds.), Generative Studies in Basque Linguistics, 193–208. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/cilt.105.08urb
Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 1994. Verb-initial patterns in Basque and Breton. Lingua 94(2). 125–153. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1016/0024-3841(94)90023-X
Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 1999. Focus Phrases, Force Phrases and Left Heads in Basque. In Franco, Jon & Landa, Alazne & Martin, Juan (eds.), Grammatical Analyses in Basque and Romance Linguistics. Papers in honor of Mario Saltarelli, 179–194. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/cilt.187.11urb
Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 2002. Focus of correction and remnant movement in Basque. In Artiagoitia, Xabier & Goenaga, Patxi & Lakarra, Joseba A. (eds.), Erramu Boneta: Festscrift for Rudolf P.G. de Rijk, 510–524. Bilbo: Gipuzkoako Foru Aldundia and UPV/EHU.
Ortiz de Urbina, Jon. 2003. Ezezko perpausetako fokoak (galdegaiak eta ukagaiak). In Makazaga, Jesus Mari & Oyharcabal, Bernard (eds.), Euskal Gramatikari eta literaturari buruzko Jardunaldiak XXI. mendearen atarian (I-II), 343–356. Bilbao: Euskaltzaindia.
Oyharcabal, Bernard. 1984. Ba- baiezkoa aurrizkia. Euskera 29. 351–371.
Oyharcabal, Bernard. 1985. Behako bat ezezko esaldieri. Euskera 30. 103–115.
Oyharcabal, Bernard. 2003. Relatives. In Hualde, José Ignacio & de Urbina, Jon Ortiz (eds.), A Grammar of Basque, 762–823. Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Philip, Joy. 2013. (Dis)harmony, the Head-Proximate Filter, and linkers. Journal of Linguistics 49(1). 165–213. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226712000163
Richards, Norvin. 2010. Uttering Trees. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262013765.001.0001
Richards, Norvin. 2016. Contiguity Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/10542.001.0001
Rizzi, Luigi. 1997. The Fine Structure of the Left Periphery. In Haegeman, Lilian (ed.), Elements of Grammar, 281–337. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-5420-8_7
Roberts, Ian. 2017. Harmony, symmetry, and dominance in word order universals. In Sheehan, Michelle & Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Holmberg, Anders (eds.), The Final-Over-Final Condition. A syntactic universal, 27–42. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8687.003.0006
Sabbagh, Joseph. 2014. Word order and prosodic-structure constraints in Tagalog. Syntax 17(1). 40–89. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/synt.12012
Salaberri, Iker. 2018. Ezeztapenaren hurrenkera euskal egitura perifrastikoetan: hurbilpen diakroniko-tipologikoa. Fontes Lingua Vasconum 125. 55–83. DOI: http://doi.org/10.35462/FLV125.2
Sheehan, Michelle. 2013a. Explaining the Final-over-Final Constraint: Formal and functional approaches. In Biberauer, Theresa & Sheehan, Michelle (eds.), Theoretical approaches to disharmonic word orders, 407–468. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199684359.003.0015
Sheehan, Michelle. 2013b. Some implications of a Copy Theory of Labelling for the Linear Correspondence Axiom. Syntax 16. 362–396. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1111/synt.12010
Sheehan, Michelle. 2017. The Final-over-Final Condition and the Head-Final Filter. In Sheehan, Michelle & Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Holmberg, Anders (eds.), The Final-Over-Final Condition. A Syntactic Universal, 121–150. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8687.003.0010
Sheehan, Michelle & Biberauer, Theresa & Roberts, Ian & Holmberg, Anders. 2017. The Final-over-Final Condition. A syntactic universal. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/8687.001.0001
Subbārāo, Kārumūri V. 2012. South Asian Languages. A Syntactic Typology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139003575.007
Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam. 1994. Interface licensing conditions on negative polarity items: A theory of polarity and tense interactions. Storrs: University of Connecticut dissertation.
Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam. 2002. In situ questions and masked movement. Linguistic Variation Yearbook 2. 215–255. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/livy.2.09uri
Uribe-Etxebarria, Myriam. 2003. Euskararen eta hizkuntza erromanikoen foko egituren arteko zenbait paralelotasunez. In Euskaltzaindia (ed.), Euskal gramatikari eta literaturari buruzko jardunaldiak XXI. mendearen atarian, 437–457. Bilbao: Euskaltzaindia.
Vergara, Daniel. 2018. Basque complementizers under the microscope. A Spanish/Basque codeswitching approach. In Lopez, Luis (ed.), Code-switching – Experimental Answers to Theoretical Questions: In honor of Kay González-Vilbazo, 223–256. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI: http://doi.org/10.1075/ihll.19.09ver
Vicente, Luis. 2008. El movimiento del verbo en un análisis antisimetrico del euskara. In Arteatx, Inigo & Artiagoitia, Xabier & Elordieta, Arantzazu (eds.), Antisimetriaren hipotesia vs buru parametroa: euskararen oinarrizko hitz hurrenkera ezbaian, 131–155. Vitoria-Gasteiz: UPV/EHUko Argitalpen zerbitzua.
Villa-García, Julio. 2019. Clitic climbing (or lack thereof) and the Copy Theory of Movement. Glossa: a journal of general linguistics 4(1). DOI: http://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.965
Williams, Edwin. 1982. Another argument that passive is transformational. Linguistic Inquiry 13. 160–163.
Zabala, Igone. 2000. Hitz-hurrenkera euskara tekniko-zientifikoan. EKAIA 12. 143–166.
Zec, Draga & Inkelas, Sharon. 1990. Prosodically constrained syntax. In Inkelas, Sharon & Zec, Draga (eds.), The Phonology-Syntax Connection, 365–378. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.