1. Introduction

Resultatives are a form of complex predicate in which a manner predicate and a result predicate appear in a causal relation within a monoclausal structure. A proto-typical example of this construction is resultative secondary predication, in which a manner verb functions as the main predicate of the clause denoting an action that causes a patient to undergo a change of state, with the result state itself named by a stative secondary predicate (Halliday 1967; Simpson 1983; Beavers 2012). In English, the secondary predicate is realized by a non-verbal predicate, as, for example, by an adjective (Larson 1991).

    1. (1)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim hammered the metal flat.
    2. Kim pushed the door open.

In addition to resultative secondary predication, resultative meaning may be expressed by a means construction (Dowty 1979; Sæbø 2008; Solstad 2009). In this construction, the main predicate of the clause is a causative verb which, by itself, expresses a causative relation between an underspecified event and a result state specified by the root. The manner predicate in this case is realized as an adjunct to the causative predicate modifying the entailed underspecified causing event with, for example, a manner by-phrase in English (also Truswell 2007).

    1. (2)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim flattened the metal by hammering it.
    2. Kim opened the door by pushing it.

The two types of resultative constructions thus differ significantly in their underlying syntactic and sematic composition.

Cross-linguistically, it has been observed that languages vary in the type of construction in which resultative meaning is pre-dominantly realized (Talmy 2000): While satellite-framed languages like English prefer resultative secondary predication, verb-framed languages within the Romance language family prefer means constructions; in fact, resultative secondary predication is usually ungrammatical in verb-framed languages.

    1. (3)
    1. a.
    1.   María
    2.   Maria
    1. aplanó
    2. flatten
    1. el
    2. the
    1. metal
    2. metal
    1. martilleándolo.                         Spanish
    2. hammering
    1.   ‘Maria flattened the metal by hammering it.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. *María
    2.   Maria
    1. martilleó
    2. hammered
    1. el
    2. the
    1. metal
    2. metal
    1. plano.
    2. flat
    1.   Intended: ‘Maria hammered the metal flat.’ (Mateu 2012: 258)

However, this typology has been established primarily on the basis of non-serializing languages, in which the secondary predicate is necessarily realized by a non-verbal predicate; this makes it easy to determine the main predicate status of the verbal predicate. This contrasts with languages that show verb serialization, i.e. constructions in which more than a single verbal predicate can appear in a monoclausal environment (Veenstra & Muysken 2017; Aikhenvald 2018; Hopperdietzel 2020). In resultative serial verb constructions (RSVCs), both the manner and the result predicate are realized by predicates of verbal category, as in the Lao (Kra-Dai) and Mandarin (Sino-Tibetan) examples (Lin 2004; Cole 2016).

    1. (4)
    1. a.
    1. Candii
    2. Jandee
    1. liit
    2. iron
    1. sùa
    2. shirt
    1. liap.                                                                Lao
    2. smooth
    1. ‘Jandee ironed the shirt smooth.’ (Cole 2016: 51)
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Lisi
    2. Lisi
    1. ca-gan-le
    2. wipe-dry-pfv
    1. zhouzi.                                                   Mandarin
    2. table
    1. ‘Lisi wiped the table dry.’ (Lin 2004: 91)

Based on examples with intransitive result verbs as in (4), RSVCs are often treated as resultative secondary predication with verbal secondary predicates (Larson 1991; C. Collins 1997; Stewart 2001), or as a distinct type of equipollently-framed resultative, in which both manner and result predicates exhibit equal syntactic and semantic status (Slobin 2004; Zlatev & Yangklang 2004; Ameka & Essegbey 2013).

In this paper, I present novel data from the serializing language Samoan (Polynesian, Oceanic, Austronesian), in which result predicates of RSVCs are realized by transitive causative verbs (Mosel 2004; Hopperdietzel 2021c; see also Tomioka 2006 on Japanese; Ko & Sohn 2015 on Korean; Sugar 2019 on Uyghur (Turkic)).

    1. (5)
    1. a.
    1. pst
    1. solo
    2. wipe
    1. faʻa-mamā
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Mary cleaned the table by wiping it.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. pst
    1. tipi
    2. cut
    1. faʻa-paʻū
    2. caus-fall
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Pita
    2. Peter
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laʻau.
    2. tree.abs
    1. ‘Peter felled the tree by cutting it.’

The investigation of the morphosyntactic and semantic properties of Samoan RSVCs indicates that they belong to the class of means constructions, in that the adjoined manner verb modifies the underspecified causing event entailed by the causative result verb. Samoan-type RSVCs therefore differ from Mandarin-type RSVCs in the same way that Romance-type resultatives differ from English-type resultatives in non-serializing languages. As a consequence, RSVCs do not instantiate either a uniform or special type of resultative, but reflect the general split in the resultative domain on the relevant level of syntactic and semantic composition (Talmy 2016).

These findings have further consequences for a unified analysis of resultative structures cross-linguistically. Adopting a decompositional approach to event and argument structure (Alexiadou et al. 2015; Folli & Harley 2020; cf. Ramchand 2008), I take manner and result interpretations to arise from designated syntactic positions relative to a causing-event introducing verbalizer v: While a manner interpretation is associated with the modifying position to v (sister of v’), result meaning arises in the argument/complement position of v (Folli & Harley 2020; cf. Embick 2004; Mateu & Acedo-Matellan 2012; Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou 2013).

    1. (6)

To account for the cross-linguistic variation, I propose that resultative constructions can differ in the morphosyntactic type of the constituents that appear in certain positions, i.e. √ vs. XP. Serializing languages like Samoan therefore extend the typology to include verbal manner modification, which so far includes only root, prepositional and nominal modifiers (Pylkkänen 2008; Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou 2020; Folli & Harley 2020). Consequently, the split between non-serializing and serializing languages as between satellite and verb-framed languages can be reduced to language specific constraints on argument and event structure building in the syntax (cf. Beavers et al. 2010 on the motion domain).

This paper is organized as follows: In section two, I motivate a configurational analysis of manner and result meaning based on the complementary distribution of manner and result meaning in simple predicates. Based on the categorization restriction on roots, I show that resultative secondary predication and means constructions represent two available strategies to express resultative meaning in a monoclausal environment. In section three, I compare the syntactic and semantic properties of resultative constructions in two serializing languages: Mandarin and Samoan. The results indicate that resultatives exhibit the same split in both serializing and non-serializing languages. In section four, I sketch out a refined typology of manner and result specification, which leads to a novel understanding of cross-linguistic variation in the verbal domain. Section five concludes.

2. Two types of resultatives

Cross-linguistically, manner and result meanings have been shown to be in complementary distribution in mono-morphemic predicates. Such predicates can lexicalize either manner or result meaning components, but not both simultaneously (manner/result complementarity; Rappaport Hovav & Levin 2010; Beavers & Koontz-Garboden 2020; cf. Gast et al. 2014; Hopperdietzel 2020 for a cross-linguistic picture). Due to this restriction, two strategies of complex predicate formation are used to express resultative meaning in monoclausal structures, which vary in the component of meaning lexicalized by the main verb (Talmy 2000): (i) resultative secondary predication (7a); and (ii) means constructions (7b).

    1. (7)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim pushed the door open.
    2. Kim opened the door by pushing it.

In this section, I present a syntactic approach to event (de)composition that takes manner and result components as positions that are structurally defined relative to a causing-event introducing verbalizer head v (Mateu & Acedo-Matellan 2012; Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou 2013; Folli & Harley 2020). Manner/result complementarity then results from the categorization restriction of the verbalizer, which makes it necessary to merge either the manner or result component as a pre-categorized constituent in resultative structures.1

2.1. The distribution of manner and result meaning

In decompositional approaches to event structure, verbal predicates are built from atomic parts: (i) event structure templates based on grammatical primitives (structural verb meaning), and (ii) roots (lexical verb meaning; cf. Dowty 1979; Rappaport Hovav & Levin 1998; Beavers & Koontz-Garboden 2020), with two atomic eventualities that cannot be further decomposed; namely States and Activities. A State describes a stative eventuality which is denoted by the (stative) root itself (8a), whereas an Activity describes an abstract act(ion) event that is modified by an eventive (manner) root (8b).

    1. (8)
    1. a.
    2.  
    3.  
    4. b.
    5.  
    6.  
    1. State:
    2.  
    3.  
    4. Activity:
    5.  
    6.  
    1. [x <state>]
    2. [door <open>]
    3. The door is open.
    4. [x ACT<manner> (y)]
    5. [Kim ACT<push> (door)]
    6. Kim pushed (the door).

From these atomic eventualities and additional semantic operators, more complex eventualities can be derived: Causative accomplishment verbs such as open combine an underspecified (action) event and a (result) state, which is realized by the single (stative) root, via a cause operator that introduces a causative relation between the two eventualities (cf. Lewis 1973).

    1. (9)
    1. Causative:
    1. [[x ACT] CAUSE [y <state>]]
    2. [[Kim ACT] CAUSE [door <open>]]
    1. Kim opened the door.

In resultative constructions, both the causing action event and the result state are specified by distinct roots: While an eventive root modifies the manner of the causing event, a stative root names the result state (Levin & Rappaport Hovav 2001; Kratzer 2005).

    1. (10)
    1. Resultative:
    1. [[x ACT<manner>] CAUSE [y <state>]]
    2. [[Kim ACT<push>] CAUSE [door <open>]]
    1. Kim pushed the door open.

Consequently, there are two ways for roots to be integrated into the event structure of verbal predicates: either as (i) event modifiers of an abstract act(ion) event specifying the manner of the event, or (ii) event arguments of the causative operator, naming the result state. Crucially, it has been observed that a single root cannot function as an event modifier or event argument simultaneously, resulting in a complementary distribution of manner and result meaning components in mono-morphemic verbs (Rappaport Hovav & Levin 2010).2

    1. (11)
    1. Manner/result complementarity
    2. Manner and result meaning component are in complementary distribution: A verb lexicalizes only one.

Accordingly, roots can be grouped in two broad ontological classes: (i) eventive (manner) roots, such as , or , that act as event modifiers (12a), and (ii) stative (result) roots, such as , or , that specify a result state (12b) of accomplishment predicates (Rappaport Hovav & Levin 2010; Alexiadou et al. 2015; Beavers & Koontz-Garboden 2020).

    1. (12)
    1. a.
    2. b.

Adopting a syntactic approach to event decomposition, I assume that roots enter the derivation acategorially and must be categorized by a verbalizer, where the relative structural position of the root in relation to its verbalizer is semantically meaningful (Folli & Harley 2020; cf. Mateu & Acedo-Matellan 2012; Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou 2013): Eventive manner roots, as event modifiers, merge in the modifier position, i.e. as sisters of v’ (13a), whereas stative result roots, as event arguments, merge in the argument position of v, i.e. as complements of v (13b) (within a pre-categorial Res(ult)P). Manner/result complementarity then follows from two independent syntactic constraints on root categorization: (i) a single categorizer can only categorize a single root, making it impossible for two roots to merge with the same categorizer, and (ii) a single root can only merge in a single structural position (Embick 2010).

    1. (13)
    1. a.
    1.  
    1. b.

Additionally, I take causative semantics to be interpreted configurationally via contextual allosemy, when an eventive verbalizer v takes another eventuality as its complement (Wood 2015; cf. Higginbotham 2000; Ramchand 2008; Alexiadou et al. 2015 on telic pair formation; also Beck & Snyder 2001 on Principle R).3

    1. (14)
    1. v
    2.  
    1. λe. …
    2. λP<v,t>λe.Ǝv. Caus(e, v) ∧ P(v) \ ___ XP<v,t>                            (adapted from Wood 2015: 28)

The agent argument is introduced on top of the vP by a functional head Voice (Kratzer 1996; Alexiadou et al. 2015), resulting in a layered structured verbal domain: (i) VoiceP as the locus of agentive semantics, (ii) vP as the locus of (causative) event semantics, and (iii) ResP as the locus of (result) state semantics.

In the following, I generalize this configurational approach, taking manner and result meaning components as structural notions relative to an eventive verbalizer v, which can be realized by various syntactic constituents. I thus attribute the observed variation in the resultative domain to different strategies that avoid the categorization restriction on roots.

    1. (15)

2.2. Resultative secondary predication

One strategy to circumvent the categorization restriction is to express the result state with a pre-categorized element, i.e. resultative secondary predication (see Beavers 2012 for an overview). In this construction, a manner verb functions as the main predicate denoting the manner of an action that causes a result state denoted by the secondary predicate. In non-serializing languages like English, resultative secondary predicates are necessarily non-verbal; they are adjectival (16a) or prepositional (16b) (Larson 1991; Embick 2004).

    1. (16)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    3. c.
    1.   Kim hammered the metal flat.
    2.   Kim cut the meat into pieces.
    3. *Kim hammered the metal flattened.

As resultative secondary predication shares several syntactic and semantic properties with lexical causatives, both constructions are analysed as bi-eventive accomplishments (Dowty 1979; Levin & Rappaport Hovav 2001; Goldberg & Jackendoff 2004). Manner adverbs like slowly, for example, necessarily scope over the whole complex event in both contexts, and cannot independently modify the causing event in both types of constructions (Higginbotham 2000; Levin & Rappaport Hovav 2001; Koev 2019).4

    1. (17)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim flattened the metal slowly.
    2. Kim hammered the metal flat slowly..

Additionally, both lexical causatives and resultative secondary predication allow for repetitive and restitutive readings of repetitive modifiers like again (von Stechow 1996; Beck & Snyder 2001; Lechner et al. 2015). Therefore, the clauses in (18) can be interpreted either such that the metal was in a state of being flat before or that Kim performed an action that led to the flattening of the metal before. Note that the causing action is only specified in resultative secondary predication.

    1. (18)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim flattened the metal again.
    2. Kim hammered the metal flat again.

Although the (implicit) theme argument of the causing action cannot be overtly realized in resultative secondary predication, the object argument does not need to be shared by the two predicates, as indicated by the felicity of unselected resultatives (Kratzer 2005; Beavers 2012; Levin 2020; cf. Wolff 2003). In (19a), the main predicate run is an intransitive verb that does not take an object in isolation, but appears in transitive resultative secondary predication. Therefore, the object is introduced by secondary predicate threadbare. This also holds for transitive resultatives as in (19b), as the teapot is not the object of drink, but the container of what is drunk, and receives its theta-role from the secondary predicate dry only.

    1. (19)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim ran her shoes threadbare.
    2. Kim drank the teapot dry.

Syntactically, resultative secondary predication has therefore been analysed as an accomplishment predicate on par with lexical causatives, where an eventive verbalizer v takes a stative complement (Hoekstra 1988; Embick 2004). However, resultative secondary predication differs from lexical causatives in the categorial status of the result component, which is realized by an acategorial ResP that incorporates into v for categorization purposes and blocks the insertion of an additional manner root in the context of lexical causatives (see section 2.1).

    1. (20)

In resultative secondary predication however, the result component is realized by a pre-categorized constituent, i.e. an aP (or PP), which does not require (re-)categorization by v.5 The absence of Result-to-v movement therefore facilitates an additional manner modification by an eventive root, which attaches in the modifying position and gets categorized by lowering to v via m(orphological)-merger (Matushansky 2006; Folli & Harley 2020; cf. Mateu 2012).

    1. (21)

From a semantic perspective, the two predicates enter a causative relation, in which the event denoted by the verbal manner predicate causes the result state denoted by the secondary predicate (Dowty 1979; Levin & Rappaport Hovav 2001; Kratzer 2005). Compositionally, the v head introduces an event that is in a causative relation with the state denoted by the aP and is further modified by the manner root that combines with it.6

    1. (22)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    3. c.
    1. hammer
    2. flat
    3. hammer flat
    1. =
    2. =
    3. =
    1. λP<v,t>λe.Ǝs.
    2. λs.
    3. λe. Ǝs
    1. hammer(e) ∧ Caus(e, s) ∧ P(s)
    2. flat(s)
    3. hammer(e) ∧ Caus(e, s) ∧ flat(s)

To summarize, resultative secondary predication exhibits the following properties: (i) the manner verb is the main predicate of the construction, (ii) the pre-categorized stative result predicate is a secondary predicate, (iii) this secondary predicate is an argument/complement of the main predicate, and (iv) both predicates stand in a causative relation.

2.3. Means constructions

Another strategy to circumvent the categorization restriction in resultative constructions is to realize the manner component by a pre-categorized modifier. This configuration has been described as the means construction (Dowty 1979; Sæbø 2008; Solstad 2009). In English for example, manner by-phrases qualify as means constructions. Here, the main predicate is a causative verb that expresses a causative relation between an underspecified event and the result state denoted by the root with the prepositional adjunct specifying the manner of the causing event (also Truswell 2007).

    1. (23)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim opened the door by pushing it.
    2. Kim flattened the metal by hammering it.

According to Sæbø (2008), the preposition by is semantically vacuous and does not contribute any semantics to the composition of the two events denoted by the main and the adjoined predicate. Instead, the manner adjunct adds an event description e’ that identifies the manner of the underspecified causing event e which is entailed by the causative predicate. The two predicates are therefore in an asymmetric part-whole relationship, in which the presence of causative semantics licenses the modification by the by-phrase adjunct.

If both the manner adjunct and the causative verb predicate over the same (causing) event, a separate modification with temporal or manner adverbials will be infelicitous (cf. Eckardt 1998; Ernst 2002). As demonstrated by Fodor (1970), separate temporal modification in the manner adjunct is not felicitous in the context of lexical causatives, which entail a single causing event in their event structure (24a). In periphrastic causatives, which entail two underspecified causing events, namely the one introduced by the causative light verb and the other introduced by the anticausative predicate die, such a modification becomes available if both temporal modifiers are interpreted to scope over different causing events, i.e. John stabbed Bill on Saturday causing him to become dead on Sunday (24b) (cf. Martin 2020).

    1. (24)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. #John killed Bill on Sunday by stabbing him on Saturday.
    2.   John caused Bill to die on Sunday by stabbing him on Saturday.                         (Fodor 1970: 433)

Relatedly, manner by-phrases are ambiguous in periphrastic but not in lexical causatives, reflecting the number of causing events in the event structure of the respective construction. In bi-eventive periphrastic causatives, the by-phrase can either be interpreted as John or Bill swallowing Bill’s tongue, i.e. the by-phrase modifies either the causing or the caused event (25a), whereas in the context of mono-eventive lexical causatives, the by-phrase is unambiguous, i.e. John must be the one who swallows Bill’s tongue (25b).

    1. (25)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. John killed Bill by swallowing his tongue.
    2. John caused Bill to die by swallowing his tongue.                         (Fodor 1970: 435)

The observed ambiguity of manner by-phrases in bi-eventive periphrastic causatives with embedded anticausative predicates further shows that manner by-phrases are event-related modifiers that do not presuppose the presence of an agentive argument (Alexiadou et al. 2015; also Solstad 2009; Biggs & Embick 2020 on manner by-phrases in periphrastic anticausatives).7

As vP-modifiers, manner by-phrases interact with other types of manner modification such as manner roots (see section 2.1): While manner by-phrases are generally felicitous in the context of accomplishment predicates that leave the manner of their causing event underspecified (26), they must be semantically compatible with the event denoted by the manner root (27) (Sæbø 2008; A. Williams 2015; Biggs & Embick 2020), as expected for adjoined structures (cf. Ernst 2002).8

    1. (26)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim flattened the metal
    2. Kim flattened the metal
    1. by hitting it with a tuba.
    2. by driving her roller over it.
    1.         (Biggs & Embick 2020: 16)
    2.  
    1. (27)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim pounded the metal flat
    2. Kim pounded the metal flat
    1.   by hitting it with a tuba.
    2. #by driving her roller over it.
    1. (Biggs & Embick 2020: 16)
    2.  

Syntactically, English means constructions therefore merge a stative result root in the complement position of an eventive v, which incorporates into v to satisfy the categorization requirement. As the causing event-introducing verbalizer cannot categorize an additional manner root, only pre-categorized manner adjuncts, such as manner by-phrases, are able to specify the manner of the causing event. Thus, means constructions are the mirror image of resultative secondary predication, as they merge a pre-categorized XP in the manner position.

    1. (28)

Semantically, the causative result predicate introduces a causative relation between an underspecified event e and a state s, the latter of which is specified by the result root. The manner adjunct instead denotes the manner of an event, which then modifies the underspecified causing event of the causative main predicate, via Predicate Modification, Event Identification or Event Specification (Sæbø 2008; Solstad 2009), depending on the presence of an additional (open) argument variable and existential binding of the event variable in the adjoined predicate (see Alexiadou 2013 on the presence of PRO in English verbal gerunds).

    1. (29)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    3. c.
    1. flatten
    2. by hammering
    3. flatten by hammering
    1. =
    2. =
    3. =
    1. λe. Ǝs
    2. λe.
    3. λe. Ǝs
    1. Caus(e, s) ∧ flat(s)
    2. hammer(e)
    3. hammer(e) ∧ Caus(e, s) ∧ flat(s)

To summarize, the means construction shows the following properties: (i) the causative result verb is the main predicate of the construction, (ii) the manner predicate is the secondary predicate, (iii) the secondary predicate is an adjunct to the main predicate, and (iv) it asymmetrically modifies the (causing) event entailed by the causative main predicate.

2.4. Talmy’s typology

Based on their syntactic and semantic properties, two strategies have been identified that enable the expression of resultative meaning in monoclausal structures by avoiding the categorization restriction on roots: In resultative secondary predication, the verbal main predicate denotes the manner of a causing action taking a pre-categorized stative predicate as a complement, whereas in means constructions, the verbal main predicate is a causative result verb whose causing event is modified by a manner adjunct (Table 1).

Table 1

Syntactic and semantic properties of resultative secondary predication and means constructions.

RSP means
Main predicate manner verb causative result verb
Secondary predicate result XP manner XP
Syntactic composition Complementation Adjunction
Semantic composition Functional Application Predicate Modification

With a focus on the motion constructions, Talmy (2000) demonstrates that, cross-linguistically, languages differ significantly in their preferred strategy to express resultative meaning (see Levin & Rappaport Hovav 2001; Goldberg & Jackendoff 2004; Beavers 2012 on directed motion constructions as resultatives). On the one hand, there are so-called satellite-framed languages like English and German, which typically encode resultative meaning by resultative secondary predication, i.e. the result state is expressed by a secondary predicate, the satellite. In addition, satellite-framed languages usually exhibit a means construction as well.

    1. (30)
    1. a.
    1. Unbekannte
    2. unknown.persons
    1. schossen
    2. shot
    1. den
    2. the
    1. Verbrecher
    2. criminal
    1. tot.                         german
    2. dead
    1. ‘Unknown persons shot the criminal dead.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Unbekannte
    2. unknown.persons
    1. töteten
    2. killed
    1. den
    2. the
    1. Verbrecher
    2. criminal
    1. durch
    2. through
    1. einen
    2. a
    1. Schuss.
    2. shot
    1. ‘Unknown persons killed the criminal with a shot.’ (Solstad 2009: 372)

On the other hand, so-called verb-framed languages like Spanish and other Romance languages typically express resultative meaning by means constructions, i.e. the result state is expressed by the verb itself. In contrast to satellite framed languages, verb-framed languages exhibit only a single strategy, disallowing resultative secondary predication (but see Son & Svenonius 2008 for potential variation across domains within a single language).

    1. (31)
    1. a.
    1.   María
    2.   Maria
    1. aplanó
    2. flatten
    1. el
    2. the
    1. metal
    2. metal
    1. martilleándolo.                         spanish
    2. hammering
    1.   ‘Maria flattened the metal by hammering it.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. *María
    2.   Maria
    1. martilleó
    2. hammer
    1. el
    2. the
    1. metal
    2. metal
    1. plano.
    2. flat
    1.   Intended: ‘Maria hammered the metal flat.’ (Mateu 2012: 258)

To account for this pattern, Folli & Harley (2020) propose that obligatory Result-to-v movement distinguishes satellite-framed from verb-framed languages, in that verb-framed languages require the Result-denoting head to incorporate into v. 9 By the assumption that head movement of a non-verbal head into a verbalizing head blocks the categorization of an additional manner root in the modifying position of v due to the (re-)categorization of the incorporated non-verbal element, resultative secondary predication is unavailable in verb-framed languages, as the manner root would be left uncategorized.10 Resultative secondary predication is therefore not available in verb-framed languages (32b). This contrasts with satellite-framed languages, in which such head movement is optional and thus both resultative secondary predication and means constructions are fully grammatical (32a).

    1. (32)
    1. a.
    1.  
    1. b.

As a consequence, satellite and verb-framed languages do not differ fundamentally in their underlying syntactic configuration, but are subject to parametrized Result-to-v movement, which results in the absence of resultative secondary predication in verb-framed languages.

2.5. Summary

In this section, I have developed a configurational account that treats manner and result meaning as structural notions in relation to an (causing) event-introducing verbalizer v (adjunct/modifier = Manner; argument/complement = Result). On the assumption that the observed complementary distribution of manner and result meaning in mono-morphemic verbs follows from the categorization restriction on roots, resultative meaning must be realized by two types of complex predicates, which differ in the (pre-)categorial status of their respective meaning components: While in resultative secondary predication the result component is realized by a pre-categorized element, it is the manner component in the means constructions. The (cross-linguistic) variation in the resultative domain can therefore be attributed to the properties of the elements that appear in the respective manner or result position (cf. A. Williams 2008, 2015).

    1. (33)

3. Two types of RSVCs

Most studies addressing the internal structure of resultative constructions focus primarily on non-serializing languages, such as English or Spanish, in which the secondary predicate is readily distinguishable from the main predicate by its non-verbal nature. However, in many serializing languages resultative meaning is expressed by RSVCs, in which both the manner and result predicates are realized by verbs (Aikhenvald 2018; cf. von Prince 2017; Verkerk & Frostad 2013).11

    1. (34)
    1. a.
    1. Lisi
    2. Lisi
    1. cav-ganv-le
    2. wipe-dry-pfv
    1. zhouzi.                                                                         Mandarin
    2. table
    1. ‘Lisi wiped the table dry.’ (Lin 2004: 91)
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. pst
    1. solov
    2. wipe
    1. faʻa-mamāv
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Mary cleaned the table by wiping it.’

Although Talmy (2000) includes serializing languages in his original typology, much work on RSVCs (implicitly) presupposes that RSVCs are a uniform phenomenon. Based on studies of RSVCs in African and South-East Asian languages, RSVCs are commonly analysed as a form of resultative secondary predication with verbal secondary predicates (e.g. Larson 1991; C. Collins 1997; Stewart 2001). Moreover, other authors have argued that RSVCs are a distinct type of equipollently-framed resultatives, in which the manner and the result verb have equal predicational status (Slobin 2004; Zlatev & Yangklang 2004; Ameka & Essegbey 2013).

In this section, I compare the syntactic and semantic properties of RSVCs in two serializing languages, Mandarin and Samoan, to demonstrate that resultative constructions in serializing languages exhibit the same split as in non-serializing languages on the relevant level (Talmy 2016). In doing so, I argue that RSVCs are neither uniform nor special.

3.1. Mandarin resultative verbal compounds

In Mandarin, one way to express resultative meaning is via resultative verbal compounds (RVCs; Lin 2004; Huang 2006; Tham 2015). In such compounds, two verbs form a complex predicate in which the initial verb denotes the manner of an action that causes the result state named by the non-initial verb, followed by the aspectual marker le.

    1. (35)
    1. a.
    1. Sanmao
    2. Sanmao
    1. pengv-liev-le
    2. bang-crack-pfv
    1. jingzi.                         Mandarin
    2. mirror
    1. ‘Sanmao banged the mirror, cracking it.’ (Tham 2012: 602)
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Lisi
    2. Lisi
    1. cav-ganv-le
    2. wipe-dry-pfv
    1. wanpan.
    2. dishes
    1. ‘Lisi wiped the dishes dry.’

Although individual analyses of Mandarin RVCs may vary significantly, there is growing consensus that Mandarin RVCs instantiate resultative secondary predication, i.e. the initial manner verb takes the non-initial result verb as a complement (e.g. Lin 2004; Huang 2006; J. Liu 2021).12 In the following, I discuss two major diagnostics that support this line of research, before sketching out an analysis within the framework developed in section 2.

3.1.1. Transitivity of the result predicate

The first diagnostic comes from the transitivity of the result predicate in transitive resultatives: In resultative secondary predication, the result-denoting predicate is intransitive, introducing only the holder of the result state, while the agent role is introduced by the manner predicate (36a). In means constructions however, the causative result predicate is transitive, introducing both the agent and the holder argument (36b).

    1. (36)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. The metal is flat.
    2. Kim flattened the metal.

In Mandarin RVCs, the non-initial result-denoting predicate is an intransitive verb that cannot appear in transitive structures as independent predicates, as illustrated for the result verb lie ‘crack’ and the property concept verb gan ‘dry’ (Tham 2013).13 Outside of RVCs, lie functions as an anticausative predicate that denotes a change into a state. The anticausative nature of lie can be shown by the infelicity of the intensifier hen ‘very’ which solely combines with stative predicates.

    1. (37)
    1. a.
    1.   Jingzi
    2.   mirror
    1. lie-le.                                                  Mandarin
    2. crack-pfv
    1.   ‘The mirror cracked.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. *Jingzi
    2.   mirror
    1. hen
    2. very
    1. lie.
    2. crack
    1.   Intended: ‘The mirror is (badly) cracked.’ (Tham 2012: 601)

While result verbs like crack participate in the (anti-)causative alternation in languages like English, this is not the case Mandarin (38a). Instead, verbs like lie ‘crack’ require the presence of an additional light or manner verb, which introduces the agent argument in transitive contexts (38b).

    1. (38)
    1. a.
    1. *Sanmao
    2.   Sanmoa
    1. lie-le
    2. crack-pfv
    1. jingzi.                                                  Mandarin
    2. mirror
    1.   Intended: ‘Sanmao cracked the mirror.’ (Tham 2012: 601)
    1.  
    1. b.
    1.   Sanmao
    2.   Sanmoa
    1. peng-lie-le
    2. collide-crack-pfv
    1. jingzi.
    2. mirror
    1.   ‘Sanmao banged the mirror, cracking it.’ (Tham 2012: 602)

The same observation holds for property concept verbs like gan ‘dry’, which may be ambiguous between a stative interpretation, e.g. in the context of the intensifier hen (39a), and an anticausative interpretation, e.g. in the context of the perfective suffix le (39b) (Tham 2013).

    1. (39)
    1. a.
    1. Wanpan
    2. dishes
    1. hen
    2. very
    1. gan.                         Mandarin
    2. dry
    1. ‘The dishes are (very) dry.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Wanpan
    2. dishes
    1. (*hen)
    2. very
    1. gan-le.
    2. dry-pfv
    1. ‘The dishes dried.’

Despite this stative/anticausative alternation, Mandarin property concept verbs cannot appear as independent transitive predicates, but, like result verbs, require the presence of a light or manner verb that introduces the agent argument.

    1. (40)
    1. a.
    1. *Sanmao
    2.   Sanmao
    1. gan-le
    2. dry-pfv
    1. wanpan.                                                  Mandarin
    2. dishes
    1.   Intended: ‘Sanmao dried the dishes.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1.   Lisi
    2.   Lisi
    1. ca-gan-le
    2. wipe-dry-pfv
    1. wanpan.
    2. dishes
    1.   ‘Lisi wiped the dishes dry.’

Whereas property concept verbs alternate between stative and anticausative predicates outside RVCs, the infelicity of stative modifiers like hen ‘very’ in the context of RVCs indicates the anticausative nature of the result-denoting verb in such constructions (J. Liu 2021).

    1. (41)
    1. John
    2. John
    1. (*hen)
    2. very
    1. mo-(*hen)-bao-le
    2. rub-very-be.thin-pfv
    1. na-kuai
    2. that-clf
    1. tie-pian                         Mandarin
    2. metal-plate
    1. Intended: ‘John rubbed that metal plate very thin.’ (J. Liu 2021: 75)

Consequently, these observations suggest that the non-initial result verb in Mandarin RVCs is an anticausative secondary predicate, as it can only appear in intransitive contexts.

3.1.2. Narrow repetitive again

Further support for this analysis comes from the unavailability of a narrow repetitive reading of you ‘again’ in the context of Mandarin RVCs. Cross-linguistically, repetitive modifiers like English again have been shown to be ambiguous between a repetitive and restitutive reading in the context of causative or resultative structures (Beck & Snyder 2001).

    1. (42)
    1. a.
    2.  
    3. b.
    4.  
    1. Context: Kim’s kitchen table got dirty. After Kim wiped it table clean, the table got dirty again. Therefore, …
    2. Kim wiped the table clean again.                                             repetitive
    3. Context: Kim bought a new clean table. After a while, the table got dirty. Therefore, …
    4. Kim wiped the table clean again.                                             restitutive

Adopting a structural approach, repetitive and restitutive readings arise from different syntactic positions of repetitive modifiers (von Stechow 1996; Bale 2007; Lechner et al. 2015): If again attaches to the result-denoting phrase, it takes only the result state in its scope (43a). In contrast, if again attaches to the full verb phrase, i.e. to VoiceP, it necessarily takes wide scope over the whole complex event, including the causing action and the result state (43b).

    1. (43)
    1. a.
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ⟦again⟧(aP)    =     again (λs. clean(s) ∧ Hd(table, s))
    2. ➔ presupposition: ∃s’. s’<s ∧ clean(s) ∧ Hd(table, s))
    1. (44)
    1. a.
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ⟦again⟧(VoiceP) = again (λe.∃s Ag(Kim, e) ∧ wipe(e) ∧ Cause(e,s) ∧ clean(e) ∧
    2.                                                                                                                                  Hd(table, s))
    3. ➔ presupposition: ∃e’∃s. e’<e∧ Ag(Kim, e) ∧ wipe(e) ∧ Cause(e,s) ∧ clean(e) ∧
    4.                                                                                                                                  Hd(table, s)

In addition to the wide repetitive reading, a narrow repetitive reading is available in the means construction if again is attached within the manner adjunct (for restitutive and repeptitive readings in the context of causative predicates, see section 2.2).14

    1. (45)
    1. Context: Kim wiped the table, but failed to clean it. Later though, after putting in some more effort,
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1.   Kim cleaned the table by wiping it again.                                       means construction
    2. #Kim wiped the table clean again.                         resultative secondary predication

In this position, again does not c-command the result projection and is therefore able to scope over the causing event to the exclusion of the result state (Hopperdietzel 2020). On the assumption that again only attaches to propositional phrasal nodes, again cannot directly attach to a root, ruling out narrow repetitive readings in resultative secondary predication (see Lechner et al. 2015 for a comparison with re-).

    1. (46)
    1. a.
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ⟦again⟧(Voice2P) = again (λe. Ag(Kim, e) ∧ wipe(e) ∧ Pat(table, e))
    2. ➔ presupposition: ∃e’. e’<e ∧ . Ag(Kim, e) ∧ wipe(e) ∧ Pat(table, e)

In Mandarin, the repetitive modifier you ‘again’ has been demonstrated to resemble the properties of English again, as it is ambiguous between a (wide) repetitive (47a) and restitutive reading in the context of RVCs (47b) (H. Liu 2009; Xu 2016; J. Liu 2021).15

    1. (47)
    1. a.
    1. Context: Zhangsan had opened the door before. After a while, someone else closed the door. Feeling hot, …
    1. Zhangsan
    2. Zhangsan
    1. you
    2. again
    1. da-kai-le
    2. hit-open-pfv
    1. men.                                                  Mandarin
    2. door
    1. ‘Zhangsan opened the door again.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Context: Lisi built a wardrobe for Zhangsan. He set the door on its hinges and then closed it. Curious what was inside the wardrope, …
    1. Zhangsan
    2. Zhangsan
    1. you
    2. again
    1. da-kai-le
    2. hit-open-pfv
    1. men.                                                     Mandarin
    2. door
    1. ‘Zhangsan opened the door again.’ (Xu 2016: 24)

As expected for resultative secondary predication, an additional narrow repetitive reading is absent, showing that again is not able to take scope over the manner predicate alone.

    1. (48)
    1. Context: Yesterday, Zhangsan washed some clothes in the sink, and he managed to do so without any water leaking out of the sink. Today, Zhangsan washed some clothes, but this time the sink leaked while he was washing them.
    1. #Zhangsan
    2.   Zhangsan
    1. you
    2. again
    1. xi-lou-le
    2. wash-leak-pfv
    1. lianpen.                                                  Mandarin
    2. washbasin
    1.   Intended: ‘Zhangsan made the sink leak by washing (some clothes) again.’

Under a structural analysis of Mandarin you (Xu 2016), repetitive modification thus provides semantic evidence for Mandarin RVCs to be analysed as resultative secondary predication.

3.1.3. Mandarin RVCs as resultative secondary predication

Building on the morphosyntactic and semantic properties of Mandarin RVCs, I adopt a complementation analysis in which the initial manner verb takes an anticausative result verb as its complement (J. Liu 2021; cf. Lin 2004; Huang 2006). Therefore, Mandarin RVCs can be analyzed as resultative secondary predication with anticausative secondary predicates, as illustrated in (49) below. In particular, an eventive v2 head takes a result state-denoting ResP as its complement, forming an anticausative result verb via Res-to-v movement. An additional eventive v1 head takes the anticausative v2P as its complement, introducing an additional causing event, which is then modified by the manner root that is m-merged with v1. As a result, Mandarin RVCs involve a stacking of two causative vPs.16 Despite the underlying structure of resultative secondary predication, the compound structure of Mandarin RVCs follows from additional Result-to-v movement of the embedded anticausative verb, familiar from means constructions in verb-framed languages (see section 2.4). While Result-to-v movement is blocked in resultative secondary predication in non-serializing languages due to the non-verbal nature of the result-denoting component, such movement becomes available in serializing languages like Mandarin as the incorporated result verb does not require re-categorization and therefore enables the modification by an additional manner root.

    1. (49)

In addition, Mandarin RVCs differ from resultative secondary predication in non-serializing languages in their event structure. As the anticausative secondary predicate denotes a change-of-state by itself, I propose that Mandarin RVCs exhibit a tri-eventive structure, in which the event denoted by the manner verb causes the process event entailed by the result verb which finally causes the result state.17

    1. (50)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    3. c.
    1. peng
    2. lie
    3. peng-lie
    1. =
    2. =
    3. =
    1. λe.
    2. λe.∃s
    3. λe.∃e∃s
    1. bang(e1) ∧ Caus(e1, e2) ∧ P(e2)
    2. Caus(e, s) ∧ cracked(s)
    3. bang(e1) ∧ Caus(e1, e2) ∧ Caus(e2, s) ∧ cracked(s)

To summarize, Mandarin RVCs exhibit the properties of resultative secondary predication in non-serializing languages, in that the secondary result predicate is a complement/argument of the manner main predicate. They differ however in their lexical category, verbal vs. non-verbal, and event structure, i.e. stative vs. anticausative, of the secondary predicate.

3.2. Samoan RSVCs

In the Polynesian language Samoan, resultative meaning is expressed by the serialization of an initial manner verb and a non-initial result verb (Mosel & Hovdhaugen 1992; Mosel 2004; Hopperdietzel 2020, 2021c). Crucially, the result predicate is marked by the causative prefix faʻa-.

    1. (51)
    1. a.
    1. pst
    1. soloV
    2. wipe
    1. faʻa-mamāV
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Mary cleaned the table by wiping it.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. pst
    1. tipiV
    2. cut
    1. faʻa-paʻūV
    2. caus-fall
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Pita
    2. Peter
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laʻau.
    2. tree.abs
    1. ‘Peter felled the tree by cutting it.’

In this way, Samoan RSVCs superficially resemble means constructions, which also exhibit causative verbs realizing the result component. This first intuition is supported by the result of the syntactic and semantic diagnostics that have already been applied to Mandarin RVCs, which indicate that both types of RSVCs differ in the same way as resultative secondary predication and the means construction do in non-serializing languages.

3.2.1. Transitivity of the result predicate

As noted above, stative and anticausative predicates must be derived by the causative prefix faʻa- to function as the result-denoting predicate in Samoan RSVCs. With respect to transitivity, Samoan faʻa-causatives differ significantly from morphological causatives, like flatten in English, as they do not participate in the causative alternation, but require the presence of an agent argument, which in Samoan is obligatorily marked by ergative case (52a) (Hopperdietzel 2021a; cf. Tollan 2018 on the semantics of Samoan case). Thus, faʻa- only occurs in transitive, but not in intransitive (anticausative) contexts (52b/c).

    1. (52)
    1. a.
    1.   
    2.   pst
    1. faʻa-mamā
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1.   ‘Mary cleaned the table.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. *
    2.   pst
    1. mamā
    2. clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.
    2. table.abs
    1.   Intended: ‘Mary cleaned the table.’
    1.  
    1. c.
    1. #
    2.   pst
    1. faʻa-mamā
    2. caus-clean
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.
    2. table.abs
    1.   Intended: ‘The table became clean.’

Anticausative meaning is instead primarily expressed by stative verbs in the context of the inchoative aspect marker ʻua (Hohaus 2016; cf. Koontz-Garboden 2007 on closely related Tongan).

    1. (53)
    1. a.
    1. pst
    1. mamā
    2. clean
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘The table was clean.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. ʻua
    2. inch
    1. mamā
    2. clean
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘The table became clean.’

Moreover, Samoan faʻa-causatives differ from English lexical causatives in selecting for an already categorized verbal complement (Hopperdietzel 2021a; cf. Pylkkänen 2008; Harley 2017). This is indicated by the presence of verbalizing morphology in between faʻa- and the embedded verb, such as the stativizer ma- (54a) or the anticausativizer liu- (54b).

    1. (54)
    1. a.
    1. pst
    1. faʻa-ma-tala
    2. caus-stat-open
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. faitotoʻa.                         Samoan
    2. door.abs
    1. ‘Mary opened the door.’ (lit.: ‘Mary caused the door to be opened.’)
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. pst
    1. faʻa-liu-suavai
    2. caus-anticaus-liquid
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. le
    2. art
    1. teine
    2. girl
    1. le
    2. art
    1. gao.
    2. fat.abs
    1. ‘The girl melted the fat.’ (lit.: ‘The girl caused the fat to become liquid.’)

In contrast to Mandarin RVCs, the result state in Samoan RSVCs is therefore realized by a transitive causative predicate. Consequently, both predicates could in principle be the main predicate of the construction based on their argument structure.

3.2.2. Narrow repetitive again

Discriminating evidence comes from repetitive modification. Like its English or Mandarin counterparts, Samoan toe ‘again’ has been shown to be ambiguous between a repetitive and a restitutive reading in causative and resultative contexts (Hohaus 2016; Hopperdietzel 2020). In the repetitive reading, toe scopes over both the causing action and the result state (55), whereas in the restitutive reading, toe takes solely the result state in its scope (56).18

    1. (55)
    1. Context: Peter and his family were having breakfast at their kitchen table. After the breakfast, the table was full of crumbs, so Peter wiped the table clean. A few minutes later, one of his children spilled some juice on the table. So, Peter wiped the table clean again.
    1. pst
    1. toe
    2. again
    1. solo~solo
    2. red~wipe
    1. faʻa-mamā
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Pita
    2. Peter
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Peter again cleaned the table by wiping it.’
    1. (56)
    1. Context: Peter bought a new table from the shop. At home, he put the new table in his living room. It is spotlessly clean. After dinner, the table got very dirty, covered in crumbs and sauce, so Peter wiped the table clean again.
    1. pst
    1. toe
    2. again
    1. solo
    2. wipe
    1. faʻa-mamā
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Pita
    2. Peter
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Peter cleaned the table again by wiping it.’

Crucially, repetitive modification in the context of Samoan RSVCs gives rise to an additional, narrow repetitive reading in which toe ‘again’ solely scopes over the causing event to the exclusion of the result state.19

    1. (57)
    1. Context: Peter bought a new table from the shop. At home, he realized that the table had some marks on it. Before he returned the table to the shop, he tried to clean it first. He took a cloth and wiped the table, but the table didn’t get any cleaner. Therefore, he got himself some soap and put it on the cloth. He wiped the table again and then it became clean.
    1. pst
    1. toe
    2. again
    1. solo~solo
    2. red~wipe
    1. faʻa-mamā
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Pita
    2. Peter
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Peter cleaned the table by wiping it.’

As elaborated in section 3.1.2, such a narrow repetitive reading of repetitive modifiers like toe is only expected in the means construction, in which toe can attach to the adjoined manner verb phrase prior to the modification of the causing event entailed by the main predicate.20

3.2.3. Samoan RSVCs as means constructions

Based on the transitivity of the result-denoting predicate and the availability of a narrow reading of the repetitive modifier toe ‘again’, Samoan RSVCs can be identified as a verbal means construction in which the initial manner verb is adjoined to the causative result verb, which functions as the main predicate of the clause. The result component is realized by a stative or anticausative verb, which moves to the causing-event introducing head, spelled-out as faʻa-, to form the causative main predicate of the clause.

    1. (58)

The phrasal status of the manner adjunct is further supported by the ability of adverbial manner modifiers to intervene between the manner and causative verb (cf. A. Williams 2008, 2015). As in Samoan, adverbial modifiers attach to the right edge of the verb phrase (Mosel 2004; J. N. Collins 2017), the occurrence of manner adverbs in SVC-medial position shows that an independent modification of the manner verb is possible.

    1. (59)
    1. a.
    1. pst
    1. [[[solo
    2. wipe
    1. vave]
    2. quick
    1. faʻa-mamā]
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Mary cleaned the table by wiping it quickly.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. pst
    1. [[[solo
    2. wipe
    1. faʻa-mamā]
    2. caus-clean
    1. vave]
    2. quick
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Mary cleaned the table quickly by wiping it.’

Based on the absence of Voice-related morphology, such as the causative prefix faʻa- (Hopperdietzel 2021a), on the initial verb, the manner component is realized by a vP-sized adjunct to the causative main predicate (Hopperdietzel 2020, 2021c).21

    1. (60)
    1. #
    2.   pst
    1. fa’a-gao
    2. caus-break
    1. faʻa-la’iti
    2. caus-small
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Pita
    2. Peter
    1. le
    2. art
    1. lala.                         Samoan
    2. branch.abs
    1.   Intended: Peter made the branch small by breaking it.’

Additional support for the absence of Voice in the manner adjunct comes from object sharing in Samoan RSVCs. As shown in (61a), the internal argument of the manner verb can be neither distinctly realized nor interpreted independently from the single object of RSVCs.22 Instead, the intended meaning must be realized by a bi-clausal construction (61b).

    1. (61)
    1. a.
    1. *
    2.   pst
    1. lamu
    2. chew
    1. (pulu)
    2. gum
    1. faʻa-pa~paʻe
    2. caus-red~white
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. le
    2. art
    1. teine
    2. girl
    1. nifo.                         Samoan
    2. teeth.abs
    1.   Intended: ‘The girl whitened her teeth by chewing (gum).’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1.   
    2.   pst
    1. lamu
    2. chew
    1. pulu
    2. gum
    1. e
    2. genr
    1. faʻa-pa~paʻe
    2. caus-red~white
    1. ai
    2. anaph
    1. ona
    2. 3sg.poss
    1. nifo.
    2. teeth.abs
    1.   ‘She chewed gum to whiten her teeth.’

This contrasts with English-type means constructions, in which the manner adjunct can introduce its own separate object, which can differ from the one of the causative main predicate, if it is interpreted as an instrument or facilitating condition (Wolff 2003; Levin 2020).

    1. (62)
    1. Kim cut herself by carving the pumpkin.

Hopperdietzel (2020) attributes the observed contrast to the availability of a nominal licensing head, such as Voice, in the means adjunct (cf. Sheehan & van der Wal 2018; Nie 2020). In English, the internal argument of the manner predicate is licensed by transitive Voice entailed by the adjoined verbal gerund (cf. Alexiadou 2013). In the absence of transitive Voice in the means adjunct in Samoan RSVCs however, the internal arguments of both the adjoined manner and the causative verb must instead be licensed by a single matrix Voice head via movement (see J. N. Collins 2017 on obligatory object-movement in Samoan). Since the stative/anticausative v3P and the manner v1P are in a configuration that facilitates ATB-movement, both copies move out of the respective vPs to Spec, VoiceP for licensing purposes (see Lidz & Williams 2002 on ATB-movement in Kannada (Dravidian) resultatives; cf. Hiraiwa & Bodomo 2008; Žaucer 2009).

    1. (63)
    1. a.
    1.  
    1. b.

As ATB-movement is subject to identity constraints (Ross 1967; E. Williams 1978), a distinct internal argument in the means adjunct would be left unlicensed, causing the derivation to crash (see also J. N. Collins 2017 on ATB movement of internal arguments to Spec, VoiceP in low vP-coordination in Samoan). Therefore, the contrast between English and Samoan follows from the absence of a nominal licenser in the means adjuncts, and in combination with the morphological evidence supports a vP-adjunction analysis of Samoan RSVCs.

To summarize, Samoan RSVCs qualify as a means construction, based on the main predicate status of the causative result verb. The underspecified causing event is then modified by a vP-adjunct which specifies the manner of causing action.

    1. (64)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    3. c.
    1. faʻa-mamā
    2. solo
    3. solo faʻa-mamā
    1. =
    2. =
    3. =
    1. λe.Ǝs
    2. λe.
    3. λe.Ǝs
    1. Caus(e, s) ∧ clean(s)
    2. wipe(e)
    3. wipe(e) ∧ Caus(e, s) ∧ clean(s)

3.3. Cross-linguistic variation: Against a uniform analysis

The investigation of RSVCs in two serializing languages reveals that serializing resultative constructions exhibit the same split as non-serializing languages do with respect to the predicational status of the manner or result predicate: While Mandarin RVCs qualify as resultative secondary predication, Samoan RSVCs qualify as means constructions. Cross-linguistically, RSVCs may show further variation.

On the one hand, verbal resultative secondary predication does not necessarily involve Result-to-v movement as observed in Mandarin. Languages like Edo (Niger-Congo) or Lao instead show that verbal secondary predicates may also occur separately from the manner verb. In addition, the result component may not necessarily be realized by an anticausative (65a), but also by a stative verb (65b) (Stewart 2001; Cole 2016).

    1. (65)
    1. a.
    1. Oso
    2. Osa
    1. sua
    2. push
    1. Adesuwa
    2. Adesuwa
    1. de.                         Edo
    2. fall
    1. ‘Esosa pushed Adesuwa down.’ (Stewart 2001: 15)
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Candii
    2. Jandee
    1. liit
    2. iron
    1. sùa
    2. shirt
    1. liap.                              Lao
    2. smooth
    1. ‘Jandee ironed the shirt smooth.’ (Cole 2016: 51)

On the other hand, verbal manner adjuncts in means constructions may differ in their morphosyntactic properties. Daakaka (Oceanic, Austronesian) RSVCs show for example that object matching is not a necessary condition on vP-adjoining RSVCs cross-linguistically, as the object of the adjoined manner verb can be interpreted distinctly from the one of main predicate, in the absence of an underlying syntactic representation (as indicated by the suppletive intransitive from of the manner verb; Hopperdietzel 2020; 2021b; also Tomioka 2006 on Japanese RSVCs); an option that is unavailable in Samoan (see fn. 22).

    1. (66)
    1. Bong
    2. Bong
    1. ma
    2. real
    1. ta
    2. cut.intr
    1. sengave
    2. open.tr
    1. seli.                         Daakaka
    2. road
    1. ‘Bong opened/cleared the road by cutting (grass).’

Likewise in Uyghur RSVCs, object matching is optional because the manner component is realized by a VoiceP adjunct, which enables the licensing of an (overt) syntactic object of the manner verb that is distinct from the one the causative result verb (Sugar 2019; also Ko & Sohn 2015 on Korean RSVCs).

    1. (67)
    1. Shox
    2. naughty
    1. bala
    2. child
    1. derizini
    2. window-acc
    1. qol-i-diki
    2. hand-3sg.poss-rel
    1. tash-ni
    2. stone-acc
    1. at-ip
    2. throw-lk
    1. chaq-iwet-di-ø.                         Uyghur
    2. break-compl-pst-3sg
    1. ‘The naughty child broke the window by throwing the stone in their/her/his hand.’ (Sugar 2019: 123)

Therefore, the variation found in RSVCs does not only include the split into resultative secondary predication and means constructions, but also apparent micro-variation based on language specific constraints on event and argument structure (cf. Hopperdietzel 2020).

Consequently, the comparison of RSVCs in different serializing languages demonstrates that RSVCs are neither a uniform syntactic phenomenon (cf. Larson 1991; C. Collins 1997; Stewart 2001) nor a typologically distinct type of equipollently-framed resultatives (cf. Slobin 2004; Zlatev & Yangklang 2004; Ameka & Essegbey 2013). Although Mandarin RVCs may come close to such a type by forming a resultative compound, the underlying syntactic and semantic structure clearly indicates the hierarchical order of the predicates. It is therefore expected that RSVCs can be classified as either resultative secondary predication or means constructions on the relevant compositional level (also Talmy 2016). The difference between serializing and non-serializing languages can thus be reduced to a categorial split in the secondary predicates, as already implicated in the original formulation of the typology by Talmy (2000), as illustrated in Table 2.23

Table 2

Typology of resultative constructions across (non-)serializing languages.

satellite-framed verb-framed
non-serializing English Spanish
serializing Mandarin Samoan

4. Variations on a VP

The investigation of compositional properties of RSVCs indicates that resultative constructions in both serializing and non-serializing languages do not differ fundamentally in their underlying syntactic and semantic structure. Languages instead vary in their specific strategies for expressing resultative semantics, i.e. in the way in which they express manner and result meaning components in configurations relative to a (causing) event-introducing v head. In this section, I briefly review the cross-linguistic variation of manner modification and result complementation that has been observed, sketching out a preliminary typology of resultative constructions by integrating them into the configurational account of the verbal domain developed in section 2.

4.1. Manner component

Several potential ways to realize the manner component in resultative structures have already been discussed. In resultative secondary predication, the manner component is realized by a (manner) root that attaches directly to the (causing) event-introducing v. Due to the categorization restriction, the result component must be realized by a pre-categorized constituent in this context.

    1. (68)
    1. Kim hammered the metal flat.

In addition to root modification, the manner component may be realized by a pre-categorized phrasal constituent, enabling the realization of the result component by a root in means constructions, as demonstrated by prepositional manner by-phrases.

    1. (69)
    1. Kim flattened the metal by hammering.

If resultatives are primarily understood as the specification of both the manner and the result component, anticausatives that co-occur with prepositional causers, like German durch-phrases, fall under this definition. In this construction, the causing event of the anticausative main predicate is modified by the causer PP (Pylkkänen 2008; Schäfer 2008).

    1. (70)
    1. Die
    2. the
    1. Vase
    2. vase
    1. zerbrach
    2. broke
    1. durch
    2. through
    1. ein
    2. an
    1. Erdbeben.                         german
    2. earthquake
    1. ‘The vase broke from an earthquake.’ (Schäfer 2008: 127)

In the same vein, causer-DPs that modify the causing event in internally caused change-of-state (71) or object experiencer psych-verbs in English and Greek have also been argued to function as vP-level event-modifiers (Alexiadou 2014; Alexiadou & Anagnostopoulou 2020). Therefore, causer-DPs can also be taken to realize the manner component in a resultative construction.

    1. (71)
    1. O
    2. the
    1. thalasinos
    2. sea
    1. areas
    2. air
    1. skuriase
    2. rusted
    1. to
    2. the
    1. frahti                         Greek
    2. fence
    1. ‘The sea air rusted the fence.’ (Alexiadou 2014: 884)

Furthermore, verbal manner adjuncts express the manner component of RSVCs in serializing languages such as Samoan, as demonstrated in section 3.2.

    1. (72)
    1. pst
    1. solo
    2. wipe
    1. faʻa-mamā
    2. caus-clean
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. laulau.                         Samoan
    2. table.abs
    1. ‘Mary cleaned the table by wiping it.’

In some languages, manner particles have likewise been shown to modify the manner of a causing action, but cannot occur as independent predicates. In Atsugewi (Hokan), for example, these particles appear in the initial position of the tripartite semantic core of polymorphemic verbs, in which they do not function as the main predicate (Talmy 2000, 2016).

    1. (73)
    1. S’w-cu-st҆aq҆-cis-a.                                                                                                    Atsugewi
    2. 1sg>3sg.fact-with.stick-move.icky.material-into.fire-1sg>3sg.fact
    1. ‘I prodded the guts into the fire with a stick.’ (Talmy 2000: 59)

In contrast, the status of adjectival predicates in manner-modifying positions is yet unclear. In English, examples like dry-clean occur, but they seem rather idiosyncratic and not very productive. The potential absence of adjectival manner modifiers may be related to their stative nature, which makes them unlikely to function as event modifiers (but see Rothmayr 2009 on stative causatives in the pysch domain).

    1. (74)
    1. Kim dry-cleaned her jacket.

This brief overview suggests that manner modification in resultative structures can be realized by adjuncts of various grammatical categories, as long as they obey syntactic constraints, e.g. nominal adjuncts can only occur in a position in which they are licensed (see Sheehan & van der Wal 2018 for a recent discussion), and satisfy semantic requirements on event composition, i.e. they must be of the right event type (see Truswell 2007 for a preliminary survey).24

Due to their status as syntactic adjuncts, manner modifiers are expected to exhibit special properties that distinguish them from syntactic arguments, such as the result component: Firstly, manner modifiers are iterable, as long as they are able to jointly modify a single (causing) event in a non-coordinated structure. This can be illustrated by the co-occurrence of manner by-phrases and root-modifiers in English means constructions (75a) or two manner verbs in RSVCs in Daakaka (75b) (A. Williams 2015; Hopperdietzel 2020).

    1. (75)
    1. a.
    1. By striking it rapidly for hours, Kim pounded the metal flat.
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Bong
    2. Bong
    1. mwe
    2. real
    1. doko
    2. push
    1. sengep
    2. rattle
    1. tiwiye
    2. break
    1. beleem.                         Daakaka
    2. door
    1. ‘Bong broke the door by push’n’rattling it.’

Secondly, wh-extraction out of manner modifiers should be ungrammatical, as adjuncts are syntactic islands. Yet, Truswell (2007) observers that wh-extraction out of manner adjuncts is actually possible, which challenges the argument/adjunct-distinction more generally and raises questions about the syntactic status of the manner modifier.

    1. (76)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1.   Whati did Mary cut herself carving ___i ?.
    2. *Whoi did Mary cry after John hit ___i?

Thirdly, manner modifiers should be optional. While this prediction is borne out for most languages, Hopperdietzel (2020, 2021b) presents data from RSVCs in Daakaka showing that, although manner verbs are adjoined as manner modifiers, they are obligatory for the felicity of causative verbs.

    1. (77)
    1. Bong
    2. Bong
    1. ma
    2. real
    1. *(ta)
    2.   cut.intr
    1. tiwiye
    2. break.tr
    1. lee
    2. tree
    1. ente.                         Daakaka
    2. dem
    1. ‘Bong broke the tree by cutting it.’

The last two data points indicate that the argument/adjunct distinction in resultatives appears to be fuzzy and may shed new light on this distinction more generally (cf. Sæbø 2008).

4.2. Result component

Parallel to the manner component, the result component can also be realized by various strategies. In English means constructions, roots express the result state, such that the manner component is necessarily realized by a pre-categorized manner adjunct.

    1. (78)
    1. Kim flattened the metal by hammering it.

Moreover, pre-categorized phrasal elements can also occur as the result-denoting complement in resultative secondary predication. In English, the result component may therefore be realized by adjectival (79a) or prepositional phrases (79b).

    1. (79)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim hammered the metal flat.
    2. Kim cut the meat into pieces.

In languages like German, also result particles that cannot function as independent predicates, such as auf ‘open’, can denote the result state in resultative secondary predication (Zeller 2001).

    1. (80)
    1. Kim
    2. Kim
    1. schloss
    2. locked
    1. die
    2. the
    1. Tür
    2. door
    1. auf.                                                                           German
    2. open.part
    1. ‘Kim unlocked the door.’ (lit.: ‘Kim locked the door open.’)

While adjectival and prepositional secondary predicates are frequently found in satellite-framed languages, nominal secondary predicates have been observed only rarely, if they exist at all. Although nominal predicates in resultative constructions in Hungarian (Finno-Ugric) or Warlpiri (Pama-Nyungan) appear to resemble resultative secondary predication, more detailed studies have re-analyzed them as either adjuncts, covert prepositional complements, or purpose clauses (see Simpson 1983; Matushansky 2012).

    1. (81)
    1. a.
    1. Futballistá-nak
    2. football.player-dat
    1. neveli
    2. train.pres.sg
    1. a
    2. art
    1. gyerek-ek-et.                                       Hungarian
    2. child-pl.acc
    1. ‘S/he trains the children to become football players.’ (Matushansky 2012: 32)
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Ngaju-rlu=rna
    2. 1sg-erg=1sg.sbj
    1. paka-rnu
    2. hit-pst
    1. nyampu
    2. this
    1. jampita
    2. can
    1. pinpinpa-karda.                         Warlpiri
    2. flatness-trans
    1. ‘I hit this can flat.’ (Margit Bowler, p.c.)

Whether a potential absence of nominal secondary predicates can be attributed to restrictions on nominal licensing or to the semantic properties of nominal predicates is although unclear. However, it should be noted that in English nominal secondary predicates can be grammatical in periphrastic (anti-)causative constructions, in which they may also occur in the means construction.

    1. (82)
    1. a.
    2. b.
    1. Kim became a star by playing the lead role in a movie.
    2. Toni made Kim a star by casting her in the lead role of his movie.

Further, this study has demonstrated that verbal predicates can also realize the result component in serializing languages. Verbal secondary predicates thus differ from stative adjectival secondary predicates in being able to introduce anticausative semantics, as shown for Mandarin RVCs (83a). In non-serializing languages, only prepositional secondary predicates may express similar change-of-state/path semantics within the result component itself (83b/c) (cf. Son & Svenonius 2008).

    1. (83)
    1. a.
    1.   Sanmao
    2.   Sanmao
    1. pengv-liev-le
    2. bang-crack-pfv
    1. jingzi.                                                            Mandarin
    2. mirror
    1.   ‘Sanmao banged the mirror, cracking it.’ (Tham 2012: 602)
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. #Kim hammered the metal flattened/bent.
    1.  
    1. c.
    1.   Kim cut the meat into pieces.

Serializing languages are however not necessarily restricted to realize the result component with verbal predicates, as verbal and adjectival secondary predicates can be found in the same language, e.g. in Edo (indicated by a tone-change; Stewart 2001).

    1. (84)
    1. a.
    1. Òzó
    2. Ozo
    1. giá
    2. cut
    1. írúnmwùn
    2. grass
    1. gièghéV                                                                           Edo
    2. be.short
    1. ‘Ozo cut the grass short.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Òzó
    2. Ozi
    1. giá
    2. cut
    1. írúnmwùn
    2. grass
    1. giéghéadj
    2. short
    1. ‘Ozo cut the grass short.’ (Stewart 2001: 208)

Due to their syntactic status as result complements, only a single (non-distinct) result is expected to be realized per construction (Goldberg 1991 inter alia). This prediction is borne out, as two resultative secondary predicates that are not conjoined are generally ungrammatical across serializing and non-serializing languages (Stewart 2001), which highlights the different status of manner and result predicates in resultatives.25

    1. (85)
    1. a.
    1. *Kim wiped the table clean dry.
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. *Ozo
    2.   Ozo
    1. sua
    2. push
    1. omo
    2. child
    1. de
    2. fall
    1. wu.                                                  Edo
    2. die
    1.   ‘Ozo pushed the child down to its death.’ (Stewart 2001: 100)

Finally, the means construction and resultative secondary predication can co-occur when both the manner and result component are realized by pre-categorized predicates, as in Samoan RSVCs.

    1. (86)
    1. pst
    1. pulu
    2. push
    1. faʻa-ma-tala
    2. caus-stat-open
    1. e
    2. erg
    1. Malia
    2. Mary
    1. le
    2. art
    1. faitoto’a.                         Samoan
    2. door.abs
    1. ‘Mary opened the door by pushing it.’

Therefore, resultative secondary predication and means constructions are not necessarily exclusive strategies to express resultative meaning in a monoclausal environment. Instead, both strategies can interact in more complex resultative constructions, which results in further complexity in the resultative domain.

4.3. Towards a typology of resultative constructions

To summarize, the brief cross-linguistic survey of resultative constructions indicates that the manner and the result component can be realized by constituents of various morphosyntactic categories, as long as they take on the right semantic form. On the one hand, eventive roots, PPs, VPs and NPs can modify the manner component of the causing event in resultative structures, while AP-modifiers are very rare. On the other hand, roots (within ResP), APs, PPs and VPs can realize the stative or anticausative result component, while NP complements are very rare. Finally, the absence of a manner component results in causative accomplishments in which the causing action is left underspecified, whereas the absence of a result component results in mono-eventive activity verbs. Consequently, the data suggests that the underlying syntactic configuration of meaning components within the verbal domain is most likely constant across languages, whereas the morphosyntactic category of the elements that realize such meaning components may vary from language to language (cf. A. Williams 2008; 2015 for a similar intuition).

    1. (87)

The observed cross-linguistic variation is therefore expected to follow from language specific constraints on event and argument structure that restrict the availability of certain types of resultative constructions (cf. Beavers et al. 2010). For example, obligatory Result-to-v movement rules out resultative secondary predication in verb-framed languages, as discussed in section 2.3 (Folli & Harley 2020). In addition, the ability of result roots and verbal resultative secondary predicates to incorporate into the main verb has an effect on word order, as only they can exhibit a non-contiguous word order in SVO languages (A. Williams 2008). Furthermore, the investigation of Samoan RSVCs in section 3.2 shows that the absence of a nominal licensing head in Samoan vP-adjuncts restricts the interpretation of the (covert) object argument, as syntactic identity is a pre-requisite for the object to undergo ATB-movement to a licensing position outside of the adjunct, a restriction not observed in the context of English PP- or Uyghur VoiceP-adjuncts. Moreover, subject-less Mandarin RSVCs as in (88b) reflect the general grammaticality of agent deletion in the context of activity verbs in the language (88a), whereas equivalent structures are ungrammatical in languages like English (cf. A. Williams 2014; J. Liu 2021; Martin et al. forthcoming).

    1. (88)
    1. a.
    1. Wazi
    2. socks
    1. xi-le.                                                  Mandarin
    2. wash-pfv
    1. ‘The socks washed.’
    1.  
    1. b.
    1. Wazi
    2. socks
    1. xi-ganjing-le.
    2. wash-clean-pfv
    1. Lit.: ‘The socks washed clean.’ (Martin et al. forthcoming: 9)

In sum, the presented analysis offers a unified account of the verbal domain that derives various causative and resultative structures from variation in the realization of manner and result meaning components within a potentially universal configuration within the verbal domain.

5. Conclusion

In this paper, I have revisited the internal structure of resultative constructions in serializing languages, which have been claimed to be either a uniform or distinct phenomenon. However, the application of syntactic and semantic diagnostics has revealed that RSVCs in serializing languages like Mandarin or Samoan exhibit the same split in the resultative domain as non-serializing languages do, contrary to the expectation.

Adopting a syntactic approach to event decomposition, I have proposed an analysis of resultative constructions within a configurational account of the vP, in which manner and result meaning components are related to designated positions in relation to the (causing) event-introducing verbalizer v: While manner modifiers merge in the modifier position (sister of v’), result arguments merge as complements of v. Given the categorization restriction on roots, the split in resultative constructions can therefore be interpreted as two distinct strategies to express resultative meaning in a monoclausal structure by realizing at least one of the event components by pre-categorized constituents.

I have suggested that languages vary significantly regarding the morphosytactic and semantic contribution of those pre-categorized elements. Consequently, event structure building may be less sensitive to grammatical categories, but instead be driven primarily by semantic compatibility. If the underlying configurational analysis of manner and result meaning is correct, we expect the observed cross-linguistic variation to be explained by language or construction specific constraints on event and argument structure, as sketched out above for the rather unexpected object matching facts in Samoan RSVCs or agentless Mandarin RSVCs.

However, many of those factors still need to be identified. Even the split of satellite and verb-framed languages, which has been the centre of attention for a while, is not fully understood yet. Likewise, there is no satisfying account of the cross-linguistic distribution of verb serialization. With this paper, I hope to contribute to this enterprise by highlighting the structural similarities in the resultative domain across languages.

Abbreviations

The abbreviations follow the Leipzig Glossing Rules, except: anticaus = anticausative; fact = factual evidential mood; inch = inchoative aspect; lk = linker; part = particle; red = reduplication; stat = stativizer; trans = translative case.

Notes

  1. I exclude so-called spurious or pseudo resultatives, such as Kim painted the wall black or Kim cut the meat thinly, as the result state is already denoted by the verb itself and further modified by the secondary predicate (Washio 1997; Kratzer 2005; Levinson 2010). [^]
  2. The universality of manner/result complementarity has been challenged by potential counterexamples, in which roots arguably lexicalize both manner and result simultaneously, which however does not affect the analysis of this paper (e.g. Beavers & Koontz-Garboden 2012; but see Rappaport Hovav 2017). [^]
  3. The generalizations made in this paper can also be easily accommodated within an analysis that assumes causative semantics to be introduced by designated syntactic heads such as vcause, which would correspond to the causative allotype of v in (14) (e.g. Pylkkänen 2008; Folli & Harley 2020). The source of causative semantics is not directly relevant for the analysis. [^]
  4. A. Williams (2015) presents a potential counterexample to this generalization in which independent manner modification becomes available if the causing event is further specified by a manner adjunct (i).
      1. (i)
      1. Striking the metal rapidly for a long time, Al slowly pounded the metal flat.
    Yet, manner adverbs like slowly and rapidly have been shown to be sensitive to the event structure of the modified predicate. If they attach to accomplishments, they scope over the duration of the complex event, whereas if they attach to activities, they modify the rate of the actions performed (Koev 2019). In (i), the presence of the time adverbial for a long time indicates that rapidly refers to individual strikes, not to the duration of the whole event. [^]
  5. While traditional small clause analyses commonly assume that the small clause subject is introduced by an additional Pred(ication) head (cf. Baker 2003), the existence of Pred has been challenged on both empirical and theoretical grounds (Matushansky 2019), which is why I do not adopt Pred here. [^]
  6. Note that a manner predicate like hammer entails a causative relation only when it appears in resultative secondary predication. In this configuration, the eventive v receives a causative interpretation prior to modification by the manner root (cf. Rothstein 2004 on accomplishment shifts of manner predicates in resultatives). [^]
  7. In this property, manner by-phrases resemble causer from-PPs which can occur in the context of anticausative verbs in the absence of an agent-introducing VoiceP, as indicated by the ungrammaticality of passive by-phrases (ia) that are in turn grammatical in the passive construction (ib), which entails a VoiceP (Alexiadou et al. 2015).
      1. (i)
      1. a.
      2. b.
      1. The window opened from the wind / *by John.
      2. The window was opened by John.
    Manner by-phrases with lexical anticausatives are also attested, though rather rarely. This may be related to the presence of an agentive PRO argument in the manner adjunct that must be licensed by the internal argument of the matrix predicate (cf. Alexiadou 2013).
      1. (ii)
      1. Kimi died by PROi shooting herself with a gun.
    [^]
  8. Note that manner by-phrases must be licensed by causative semantics (cf. Alexiadou et al. 2015 on from-phrases)
      1. (i)
      1. Kim pounded the metal # by hitting it with a tuba.                         (Biggs & Embick 2020: 16)
    [^]
  9. The use of the label “ResultP” in Folli & Harley (2020) is different from “ResP”, as used in this paper. While ResP refers to an acategorial projection in the verbal domain, ResultP subsumes all projections that may encode the result state, i.e. ResP, AP, PP, etc. This distinction is important, as verb-framed languages incorporate all kinds of Result-denoting heads, whereas satellite-framed languages may incorporate only roots. [^]
  10. Folli & Harley (2020) suggest that even pre-categorized roots that incorporate into v are re-categorized by complex head formation, based on more general assumptions on re-categorization, e.g. adjectivization.
      1. (i)
      1. [category]N
      1. [[category]N –al]A
    This analysis may be challenged by classical head-movement analyses of noun incorporation, in which a nominal head moves into a lexical verb without bleeding the categorization properties of the verbal head (Baker 1988; but see Barrie & Mathieu 2016 for a phrasal account). [^]
  11. I assume that RSVCs and RVCs are instances of the same phenomenon (Durie 1997; Stewart 2001). [^]
  12. Mandarin RVCs occur in contexts which are quite unexpected from an English perspective, e.g. subject-less (ia) or subject-oriented RVCs (ib). Here, I focus on object-oriented RVCs and take the observed variation to derive from general properties of Mandarin argument and event structure building (Lin 2004; J. Liu 2021).
      1. (i)
      1. a.
      1. Shu
      2. tree
      1. kan-dao-le.                                                                                                                            Mandarin
      2. chop-fall-pfv
      1. ‘The tree got chopped down.’ (Lin 2004: 105)
      1.  
      1. b.
      1. Zhangsan
      2. Zhangsan
      1. chi-bao-le.
      2. eat-full-pfv
      1. ‘Zhangsan ate himself full.’ (Lin 2004: 100)
    [^]
  13. The verbal status of stative property concept lexemes in Mandarin is under debate (McCawley 1992; Paul 2010). As I will assume that such lexemes actually appear as anticausative predicates in resultatives which are necessarily verbal (Tham 2012), it does not affect my analysis of Mandarin RVCs as serializing structures. [^]
  14. Many thanks to one reviewer for a clarifying discussion of the relevant contexts that facilitate a narrow repetitive reading in means constructions. [^]
  15. The interpretation of Mandarin you is not sensitive to word order, which was the one of the original motivations for the structural analysis to again in English. However, see Xu (2016) for a discussion of (covert) movement of the repetitive modifier and semantic reconstruction in the context of a structural analysis of Mandarin you. [^]
  16. Instead of vP-stacking, it has been proposed that both roots directly merge to a single v head (e.g. J. Liu 2021 on intransitive RVCs), which however is ruled on both theoretical and empirical grounds. Firstly, a single categorizer can only categorize a single root (see section 2.1). Secondly, additional syntactic material, such as the negative particle bu, can intervene between the two verbs (Tham 2012).
      1. (i)
      1. Xiaohair
      2. child
      1. ya-bu-bian
      2. press-neg-flat
      1. ni-tuan.                                                  Mandarin
      2. mudball
      1. ‘The child is unable to flatten the mudball by pressing it.’ (Tham 2012: 609)
    [^]
  17. The tri-eventive semantics predicts that Mandarin RVCs differ from bi-eventive lexical causatives in their event properties, which appears to be borne out by the data. Firstly, Mandarin lexical causative but not RVCs and anticausatives are defeasible, i.e. allow a denial of the result state in certain contexts (Martin & Gyarmathy 2019; Martin et al. forthcoming). Secondly, several authors have noted the prominence of the result state in negation or aspectual modification, not observed for lexical causatives (see Chief 2007 for a discussion). The parallel behaviour of RVCs and anticausative verbs may therefore follow from the embedded anticausative predicate. [^]
  18. As it is the case of Mandarin you, the interpretation of Samoan toe is not sensitive to word order, which however does not preclude a structural analysis (see fn. 15). [^]
  19. One reviewer asks whether Samoan toe resembles English re- rather than again, as re- does allow for a narrow repetitive (and for some speakers a restitutive) reading in English resultative secondary predication, e.g. % Kim re-hammered the metal flat (Lechner et al. 2015; Wilson & Roeper 2021). However, unlike re- (but like again), toe is grammatical in the context of unergative verbs, which supports an analysis of toe parallel to again.
      1. (i)
      1. pst
      1. toe
      2. again
      1. siva
      2. dance
      1. le
      2. art
      1. tama.                                                                                       Samoan
      2. boy
      1. ‘The boy danced again.’
    [^]
  20. Further morphological evidence for the adjunct status of the manner verb comes from the presence of the causative prefix faʻa- on the result verb (Hopperdietzel 2021c). [^]
  21. For the general purposes of this paper, the exact size of the verbal adjunct in Samoan is not relevant (see section 3.3 on VoiceP-adjunct in Uyghur RSVCs). As pointed out by one reviewer, another way to check for the presence of Voice in the means adjunct is the grammaticality of agent-oriented adverbs, such as angrily or unwillingly, in RSVC-medial position. Yet, it is unclear whether Samoan exhibits subject-oriented adverbs, as the respective meaning is commonly realized by either clausal predicates (ia) or prepositional adjuncts which generally appear in clause-final position (ib) (cf. Hopperdietzel 2020). While additional research is needed, subject-oriented modification may be unavailable as a diagnostic for Voice in the means adjunct for independent reasons.
      1. (i)
      1. a.
      1. ua
      2. inch
      1. musu
      2. unwilling
      1. e
      2. genr
      1. alu
      2. go
      1. i
      2. obl
      1. le
      2. art
      1. ā’oga.                                                                     Samoan
      2. school
      1. ‘S/he was unwilling to go to school.’ (Mosel & Hovdhaugen 1992: 369)
      1.  
      1. b.
      1. ua
      2. inch
      1. taufai
      2. all
      1. oso
      2. jump
      1. tagata
      2. people
      1. iate
      2. obl
      1. ia
      2. 3sg
      1. ma
      2. with
      1. le
      2. art
      1. ita.
      2. anger
      1. ‘The people jumped on him angrily.’ (Mosel & Hovdhaugen 1992: 385)
    [^]
  22. Note that although Samoan allows discourse prominent objects to be dropped, they are still syntactically realized by pro, as they trigger ergative case marking on the subject (ia), which is not lexically assigned given the grammaticality of absolutive marked subjects in PNI contexts (ib) (J. N. Collins 2017; Hopperdietzel 2020).
      1. (i)
      1. a.
      1. pst
      1. solo
      2. wipe
      1. #(e)
      2.   erg
      1. le
      2. art
      1. tama.                                                                               Samoan
      2. boy
      1. ‘The boy wiped (something).’
      1.  
      1. b.
      1. pst
      1. solo
      2. wipe
      1. laulau
      2. table
      1. (*e)
      2. erg
      1. le
      2. art
      1. tama.
      2. boy
      1. ‘The boy wiped tables.’
    [^]
  23. While the focus of this paper is primarily on resultative constructions, the classification of serializing languages as satellite or verb-framed makes potential predictions about the availability of structures that have been argued to be part of a macro-parameter. For example, directed motion and double object constructions tend to be absent in classical verb-framed languages (Talmy 2000; Snyder 2001; Folli & Harley 2020); though the existence of a macro-parameter has been challenged by Son & Svenonius (2008). While Mandarin, as a satellite-framed language, has been argued to exhibit both types of constructions (F.-h. Liu 2006; Talmy 2016, 2000), they have been (superficially) described to be marginal or even absent in Polynesian languages like Samoan which may support its verb-framed status (Talmy 2000; Margetts 2007). Since a detailed examination of the Samoan data is beyond the scope of this paper, future research may shed further light on the typological classification of serializing languages with respect to a potential macro-parameter. [^]
  24. This constraint can be satisfied even if the manner adjunct does not specify the manner condition of the causing event, but restricts the set of causing events as it is the case with change-of-state verbs (Sæbø 2008; see also Beavers & Koontz-Garboden 2012 for potential relation to the properties of break-type roots).
      1. (i)
      1. Yahwed saved the Israelites by opening the Sea of Reeds.                         (Sæbø 2008: 141)
    [^]
  25. This also holds for so-called pseudo-resultatives in which an already specified result state may be further specified by an adjunct, like in the lake froze solid (Kratzer 2005; Levinson 2010). [^]

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank not only Aumuagaolo Ropeti Ale, Manumaua Luafata Simanu-Klutz, Fa’afetai Lēsa, and Jianrong Yu for their patience but also Artemis Alexiadou, James Collins, Emily Hanink, Itamar Kastner, Andrew Koontz-Garboden, Fabienne Martin, Diane Massam, John Mayer, Grant Muāgutui’a, Florian Schäfer, Giorgos Spathas, Tonjes Veenstra, and Malte Zimmermann, and the audiences at the Humboldt-University of Berlin, the University of Hawaiʻi at Mānoa, the University of Potsdam, the University of Leipzig, AFLA27, APLL12, CLS57, and GLOW41 for their valuable comments on various parts of this work, as wells as two anonymous reviewers and Guest Editor Gilian Ramchand for their constructive feedback. All errors and shortcomings are my own.

Funding information

This work was partly funded by ERC-2017-COG769192 to Andrew Koontz-Garboden and DFG AL554/8-1 to Artemis Alexiadou.

Competing interests

The author has no competing interests to declare.

References

Aikhenvald, Alexandra Y. 2018. Serial verbs. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/obo/9780199772810-0222

Alexiadou, Artemis. 2013. Nominal vs. verbal -ing constructions and the development of the English progressive. English Linguistics Research 2(2). 126–140. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.5430/elr.v2n2p126

Alexiadou, Artemis. 2014. The problem with internally caused change-of-state verbs. Linguistics 52(4). 879–910. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/ling-2014-0011

Alexiadou, Artemis & Anagnostopoulou, Elena. 2013. Manner vs. result complementarity in verbal alternations: A view from the clear-alternation. Proceedings of the 42nd Annual Meeting of North East Linguistic Society (NELS42/2), 39–52.

Alexiadou, Artemis & Anagnostopoulou, Elena. 2020. Experiencers and causation. In Nora, Bar-Asher Siegal Elitzur Boneh (ed.), Perspectives on Causation, 297–317. Springer: Cham. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34308-8_9

Alexiadou, Artemis & Anagnostopoulou, Elena & Schäfer, Florian. 2015. External arguments in transitivity alternations: A layering approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199571949.001.0001

Ameka, Felix K. & Essegbey, James. 2013. Serialising languages: Satellite-framed, verb-framed or neither. Ghana Journal of Linguistics 2(1). 19–38.

Baker, Mark C. 1988. Incorporation: A theory of grammatical function changing. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Baker, Mark C. 2003. Lexical categories: Verbs, nouns and adjectives. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511615047

Bale, Alan C. 2007. Quantifiers and verb phrases: An exploration of propositional complexity. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 25(3). 447–483. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-007-9019-8

Barrie, Michael & Mathieu, Eric. 2016. Noun incorporation and phrasal movement. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 34(1). 1–51. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-015-9296-6

Beavers, John. 2012. Resultative constructions. In Binnick, Robert (ed.), The Oxford handbook of tense and aspect, 908–933. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195381979.013.0032

Beavers, John & Koontz-Garboden, Andrew. 2012. Manner and result in the roots of verbal meaning. Linguistic Inquiry 43(3). 331–369. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1162/LING_a_00093

Beavers, John & Koontz-Garboden, Andrew. 2020. The roots of verbal meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198855781.001.0001

Beavers, John & Levin, Beth & Tham, Shiao Wei. 2010. The typology of motion expression revisited. Journal of Linguistics 46(2). 311–377. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226709990272

Beck, Sigrid & Snyder, William. 2001. The resultative parameter and restitutive again. In Féry, Caroline & Sternefeld, Wolfgang (eds.), Audiatur vox sapientiae: A Festschrift for Arnim von Stechow, 48–69. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783050080116.48

Biggs, Alison & Embick, David. 2020. On the event structural properties of the English get passive. Linguistic Inquiry just accepted, 1–44.

Chief, Liangcheng. 2007. Scalarity and incomplete event descriptions in Mandarin Chinese. PhD thesis, University of Buffalo, NY.

Cole, Douglas J. 2016. Lao serial verb constructions and their event representations. PhD thesis, University of Iowa, IA.

Collins, Chris. 1997. Argument sharing in serial verb constructions. Linguistic Inquiry 28(3). 461–497.

Collins, James N. 2017. Samoan predicate initial word order and object positions. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 35(1). 1–59. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-016-9340-1

Dowty, David. 1979. Word meaning and Montague grammar: The semantics of verbs and times in generative semantics and in Montague’s PTQ. Dordrecht: Reidel. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9473-7

Durie, Mark. 1997. Grammatical structures in verb serialization. In Alsina, Alex & Bresnan, Joan & Sells, Peter (eds.), Complex predicates, 289–354. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

Eckardt, Regine. 1998. Adverbs, events and other things: Issues in the semantics of manner adverbs. Tübingen: Niemeyer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110913781

Embick, David. 2004. On the structure of resultative participles in English. Linguistic Inquiry 35(3). 355–392. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1162/0024389041402634

Embick, David. 2010. Localism versus globalism in morphology and phonology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262014229.001.0001

Ernst, Thomas. 2002. The syntax of adjuncts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Fodor, Jerry. 1970. Three reasons for not deriving kill from cause to die. Linguistic Inquiry 1(4). 429–438.

Folli, Raffaella & Harley, Heidi. 2020. A head movement approach to Talmy’s typology. Linguistic Inquiry 51(3). 425–470. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00351

Gast, Volker & König, Ekkehard & Moyse-Faurie, Claire. 2014. Comparative lexicology and the typology of event descriptions: A programmatic study. In Gerland, Doris & Horn, Christian & Latrouite, Anja & Ortmann, Albert (eds.), Meaning and grammar of nouns and verbs, 145–183. Düsseldorf: Düsseldorf University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110720075-007

Goldberg, Adele. 1991. It can’t go down the chimney up: Path and the English resultative. Proceedings of the 17th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society (BLS17), 368–378. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.3765/bls.v17i0.1614

Goldberg, Adele & Jackendoff, Ray. 2004. The English resultative as a family of constructions. Language 80(3). 532–568. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2004.0129

Halliday, M. A. K. 1967. Notes on transitivity and theme in English. Journal of Linguistics 3(1). 37–81. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226700012949

Harley, Heidi. 2017. The “bundling” hypothesis and the disparate functions of little v. In D’Alessandro, Roberta & Franco, Irene & Gallego, Angel J. (eds.), The verbal domain, 3–28. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198767886.003.0001

Higginbotham, James T. 2000. Accomplishments. Proceedings of GLOW in Asia II, 72–82.

Hiraiwa, Ken & Bodomo, Adams. 2008. Object-sharing as Symmetric Sharing: Predicate clefting and serial verbs in Dàgáárè. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 26(4). 795–832. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-008-9056-y

Hoekstra, Teun. 1988. Small clause results Lingua 74. 101–139. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/0024-3841(88)90056-3

Hohaus, Vera. 2016. The inchoative aspect in Samoan. Proceedings of the 23rd Meeting of the Austronesian Formal Linguistics Association (AFLA23), 96–110.

Hopperdietzel, Jens. 2020. Resultatives: A view from Oceanic verb serialization. PhD thesis, Humboldt University of Berlin.

Hopperdietzel, Jens. 2021a. Causative morphology as Voice-driven allomorphy: The case of Samoan fa’a-causatives. In Massam, Diane & Clemens, Lauren E. (eds.), Polynesian syntax and its interfaces, 113–146. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198860839.003.0006

Hopperdietzel, Jens. 2021b. A manner condition on causatives: Resultative compounds in Daakaka. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 25 (SuB25), 412–429.

Hopperdietzel, Jens. 2021c. Verbal vP-modifiers in Samoan verb serialization. Proceedings of the 27th Meeting of the Austronesian Formal Linguistics Association (AFLA 27), 42–56.

Huang, C.-T. James. 2006. Resultatives and unaccusatives: A parametric view. Bulletin of the Chinese Linguistic Society of Japan 253. 1–43. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.7131/chuugokugogaku.2006.1

Ko, Heejeong & Sohn, Daeyoung. 2015. Decomposing complex serialization: The role of v. Korean Linguistics 17(1). 78–125. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/kl.17.1.03ko

Koev, Todor. 2019. Adverbs of change. In Altshuler, Daniel & Rett, Jessica (eds.), The semantics of plurals, focus, degree, and times: Essays in honor of Roger Schwarzschild, 283–303. Cham: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-04438-1_14

Koontz-Garboden, Andrew. 2007. Aspectual coercion and the typology of change-of-state predicates. Journal of Linguistics 43(1). 115–152. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226706004464

Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Rooryck, Johan & Zaring, Laurie (eds.), Phrase structure and the lexicon, 109–137. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8617-7_5

Kratzer, Angelika. 2005. Building resultatives. In Maienborn, Claudia & Wöllstein, Angelika (eds.), Event arguments: Foundations and applications, 177–212. Tübingen: Niemeyer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110913798.177

Larson, Richard. 1991. Some issues in verb serialization. In Lefebvre, Claire (ed.), Serial verbs: Grammatical, comparative and cognitive approaches, 185–211. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/ssls.8.07lar

Lechner, Winfried & Spathas, Giorgos & Alexiadou, Artemis & Anagnostopoulou, Elena. 2015. On deriving the typology of repetition and restitution. Paper presented at the 38th Generative Linguistics in the Old World Conference (GLOW38), Paris 8 & CNRS, Paris.

Levin, Beth. 2020. Resultatives and constraints on concealed causatives. In Bar-Asher Siegal, Elitzur & Boneh, Nora (eds.), Perspectives on causation: Selected papers from the Jerusalem 2017 Workshop, 185–217. Dordrecht: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34308-8_6

Levin, Beth & Rappaport Hovav, Malka. 2001. An event structure account of English resultatives. Language 77(4). 766–797. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2001.0221

Levinson, Lisa. 2010. Arguments for pseudo-resultative predicates. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 28(1). 135–182. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/s11049-010-9089-x

Lewis, David. 1973. Causation. The Journal of Philosophy 70. 556–567. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.2307/2025310

Lidz, Jeffrey & Williams, Alexander. 2002. Reflexity and resultatives. Proceedings of the 21th Meeting of the West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL21), 104–114.

Lin, Jimmy. 2004. Event structure and the encoding of arguments: The syntax of the Mandarin and English verb phrase. PhD thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA.

Liu, Feng-hsi. 2006. Dative constructions in Chinese. Language and Linguistics 7(4). 863–904.

Liu, Huijan. 2009. Additive particles in adult and child Chinese. PhD thesis, City University of Hong Kong.

Liu, Jianxun. 2021. The syntax of V-V resultatives in Mandarin Chinese. Singapore: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-33-6846-0

Margetts, Anna. 2007. Three-participant events in Oceanic languages. Oceanic Linguistics 46(1). 71–127. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/ol.2007.0021

Martin, Fabienne. 2020. Aspectual differences between agentive and non-agentive uses of causative predicates. In Bar-Asher Siegal, Elitzur & Boneh, Nora (eds.), Perspectives on causation: Selected papers from the Jerusalem 2017 Workshop, 257–294. Amsterdam: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-34308-8_8

Martin, Fabienne & Gyarmathy, Zsófia. 2019. A finer-grained typology of perfective operators. Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 12. 187–216.

Martin, Fabienne & Sun, Hongyuan & Liu, Jinhong & Demirdache, Hamida. forthcoming. On the zero-change construal of causative simple verbs in Mandarin Chinese. Proceedings of TripleA7.

Mateu, Jaume. 2012. Conflation and incorporation processes in resultative constructions. In Demonte, Violeta & McNally, Louise (eds.), Telicity, change and state, 252–278. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199693498.003.0010

Mateu, Jaume & Acedo-Matellan, Víctor. 2012. The manner/result complementarity revisited: A syntactic approach. In Cuervo, María C. & Roberge, Yves (eds.), The end of argument structure, 209–228. Leiden: Brill. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1163/9781780523774_010

Matushansky, Ora. 2006. Head movement in linguistic theory. Linguistic Inquiry 37(1). 69–109. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1162/002438906775321184

Matushansky, Ora. 2012. On the internal structure of case in Finno-Ugric small clauses. Finno-Ugric Languages and Linguistics 1(1–2). 3–43.

Matushansky, Ora. 2019. Against the PredP theory of small clauses. Linguistic Inquiry 50(1). 63–104. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1162/ling_a_00301

McCawley, James D. 1992. Justifying part-of-speech assignments in Mandarin Chinese. Journal of Chinese Linguistics 20(2). 211–245.

Mosel, Ulrike. 2004. Complex predicates and juxtapositional constructions in Samoan. In Bril, Isabelle & Ozanne-Rivierre, Françoise (eds.), Complex predicates in Oceanic languages: Studies in the dynamics of binding and boundness, 263–296. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110913286.263

Mosel, Ulrike & Hovdhaugen, Even. 1992. Samoan reference grammar. Oslo: Scandinavian University Press.

Nie, Yining. 2020. Licensing arguments. PhD thesis, New York University.

Paul, Waltraud. 2010. Adjectives in Mandarin Chinese: The rehabilitation of a much ostracized category. In Cabredo Hofherr, Patricia & Matushansky, Ora (eds.), Adjectives: Formal analyses in syntax and semantics, 115–151. Amsterdam: Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/la.153.04pau

Pylkkänen, Liina. 2008. Introducing arguments. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/9780262162548.001.0001

Ramchand, Gilian. 2008. Verb meaning and the lexicon: A first-phase syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511486319

Rappaport Hovav, Malka. 2017. Grammatically relevant ontological categories underlie manner/result complementarity. Proceedings of the 32nd Annual Meeting of the Israel Association for Theoretical Linguistics (IATL32), 77–98.

Rappaport Hovav, Malka & Levin, Beth. 1998. Building verb meanings. In Butt, Miriam & Geuder, Wilhelm (eds.), The projection of arguments: Lexical and compositional factors, 97–134. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

Rappaport Hovav, Malka & Levin, Beth. 2010. Reflections on manner/result complementarity. In Rappaport Hovav, Malka & Doron, Edit & Sichel, Ivy (eds.), Lexical semantics, syntax and event structure, 21–38. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199544325.003.0002

Ross, John R. 1967. Constraints on variables in syntax. PhD thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA.

Rothmayr, Antonia. 2009. The structure of stative verbs. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/la.143

Rothstein, Susan. 2004. Structuring events: A study in the semantics of lexical aspect. Malden, MA: Blackwell. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1002/9780470759127

Sæbø, Kjell J. 2008. The structure of criterion predicates. In Dölling, Johannes & Heyde-Zybatow, Tatjana & Schäfer, Martin (eds.), Event structures in linguistic form and interpretation, 127–147. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1515/9783110925449.127

Schäfer, Florian. 2008. The syntax of (anti-)causatives: External arguments in change-of-state contexts. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/la.126

Sheehan, Michelle & van der Wal, Jenneke. 2018. Nominal licensing in caseless languages. Journal of Linguistics 54(3). 527–589. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226718000178

Simpson, Jane. 1983. Resultatives. In Levin, Lori & Rappaport Hovav, Malka & Zaenen, Annie E. (eds.), Papers in lexical-functional grammar, 143–157. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Linguistics Club.

Slobin, Dan. 2004. The many ways to search for a frog: Linguistic typology and the expression of motion events. In Strömquist, Sven & Verhoeven, Ludo (eds.), Relating events in narrative, vol. 2: Typological and contextual perspectives, 219–257. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Snyder, William. 2001. On the nature of syntactic variation: Evidence from complex predicates and complex word-formation. Language 77(2). 324–342. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/lan.2001.0108

Solstad, Torgrim. 2009. On the implicitness of arguments in event passives. Proceedings of the 38th Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS38/2), 365–375.

Son, Minjeong & Svenonius, Peter. 2008. Microparameters of cross-linguistic variation: Directed motion and resultatives. Proceedings of the 27th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL27), 388–396.

Stewart, Osamuyimen T. 2001. The serial verb construction parameter. New York, NY: Garland.

Sugar, Alexander D. 2019. Verb-linking and events in syntax: The case of Uyghur -(i)p constructions. PhD thesis, University of Washington, Seattle, WA.

Talmy, Leonard. 2000. Toward a cognitive semantics, vol. 2: Typology and process in concept structuring. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/6848.001.0001

Talmy, Leonard. 2016. Properties of main verbs. Cognitive Semantics 2(2). 133–163. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1163/23526416-00202001

Tham, Shiao Wei. 2012. Result in Mandarin verb compounds. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 16. 59–612.

Tham, Shiao Wei. 2013. Change of state verbs and result state adjectives in Mandarin Chinese. Journal of Linguistics 49. 647–701. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/S0022226713000261

Tham, Shiao Wei. 2015. Resultative verb compounds in Mandarin. In Wang, William S.-Y. & Sun, Chaofen (eds.), The Oxford handbook of Chinese linguistics, 306–319. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Tollan, Rebecca. 2018. Unergatives are different: Two types of transitivity in Samoan. Glossa 3(1). 35, 1–41. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.223

Tomioka, Naoko. 2006. Resultative constructions: Cross-linguistic variation and the syntax-semantics interface. PhD thesis, McGill University, Montreal.

Truswell, Robert. 2007. Locality of wh-movement and the individuation of events. PhD thesis, University College London.

Veenstra, Tonjes & Muysken, Pieter. 2017. Serial verb constructions. In Everaert, Martin & van Riemsdijk, Henk (eds.), The Wiley-Blackwell companion to syntax, 2nd edn, 1–51. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1002/9781118358733.wbsyncom075

Verkerk, Annemarie & Frostad, Benedicte Haraldstad. 2013. The encoding of manner predications and resultatives in Oceanic: A typological and historical overview. Oceanic Linguistics 52(1). 1–35. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1353/ol.2013.0010

von Prince, Kilu. 2017. Multi-verb constructions: Is there a continuum? Paper presented at the Workshop on Multi Verb Constructions: Semantic, Syntactic and Typological Perspectives (MVC2017), Humboldt-University of Berlin.

von Stechow, Armin. 1996. The different readings of wieder (‘again’): A structural account. Journal of Semantics 13(2). 87–138. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/jos/13.2.87

Washio, Ryuichi. 1997. Resultatives, compositionality and language variation. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 6(1). 1–49. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1008257704110

Williams, Alexander. 2008. Word order in resultatives. Proceedings of the 26th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL26), 507–515.

Williams, Alexander. 2014. Agents in Mandarin and Igbo resultatives. In Li, Audrey & Simpson, Andrew & Wei-Tien, Dylan T. (eds.), Chinese syntax in a cross-linguistic perspective, 270–299. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199945658.003.0011

Williams, Alexander. 2015. Arguments in syntax and semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139042864

Williams, Edwin. 1978. Across-the-board rule application. Linguistics Inquiry 9. 31–42.

Wilson, Michael & Roeper, Tom. 2021. Re-visiting resultatives. Paper presented at The 52nd meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (NELS52), Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ.

Wolff, Phillip. 2003. Direct causation in the linguistic coding and individuation of causal events. Cognition 88(1). 1–48. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(03)00004-0

Wood, Jim. 2015. Icelandic morphosyntax and argument structure. Dordrecht: Springer. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-09138-9

Xu, Ting. 2016. Almost again: On the semantics and acquisition of decomposition adverbs. PhD thesis, University of Connecticut.

Žaucer, Rok. 2009. A VP-internal/resultative analysis of 4 “VP-external” uses of slavic verbal prefixes. PhD thesis, University of Ottawa.

Zeller, Jochen. 2001. Particle verbs and local domains. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI:  http://doi.org/10.1075/la.41

Zlatev, Jordan & Yangklang, Peerapat. 2004. A third way to travel: The place of Thai in motion-event typology. In Strömquist, Sven & Verhoeven, Ludo (eds.), Relating events in narrative, vol. 2: Typological and contextual perspectives, 159–190. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.